ebook img

Power Sharing in Deeply Divided Places PDF

449 Pages·2013·4.362 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Power Sharing in Deeply Divided Places

Power Sharing in Deeply Divided Places NATIONAL AND ETHNIC CONFLICT IN THE TWENTY- FIRST CENTURY Brendan O’Leary, Series Editor Power Sharing in Deeply Divided Places Edited by Joanne McEvoy and Brendan O’Leary UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA PRESS PHILADELPHIA Copyright © 2013 University of Pennsylvania Press All rights reserved. Except for brief quotations used for purposes of review or scholarly citation, none of this book may be reproduced in any form by any means without written permission from the publisher. Published by University of Pennsylvania Press Philadelphia, Pennsylvania 19104- 4112 Printed in the United States of America on acid- free paper 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Library of Congress Cataloging- in- Publication Data Power sharing in deeply divided places / edited by Joanne McEvoy and Brendan O’Leary. — 1st ed. p. cm. — (National and ethnic confl ict in the twenty-fi rst century) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-8122-4501-1 (hardcover : alk. paper) 1. Ethnic groups—Political activity. 2. Minorities—Political activity. 3. Representative government and representation. 4. Ethnic confl ict—Political aspects. 5. Cultural pluralism—Political aspects. I. McEvoy, Joanne. II. O'Leary, Brendan. JF1061.P68 2013 320.90089—dc23 2012041497 CONTENTS 1. Power Sharing in Deeply Divided Places: An Advocate’s Introduction Brendan O’Leary 1 PART I. POWER SHARING AND ELECTORAL SYSTEMS 2. Electoral Rules and Ethnic Repre sen ta tion and Accommodation: Combining Social Choice and Electoral System Perspectives . Hodgson Bernard Grofman 67 3. Th e Track Record of Centripetalism in Deeply Divided Places Allison McCulloch 94 4. Electoral Engineering for a Stalled Federation Kris Deschouwer and Philippe Van Parijs 112 PART II. HISTORICAL AND CONCEPTUAL FORAYS INTO POWER SHARING 5. A Th eory of Accommodation Versus Confl ict: With Special Reference to the Israel- Palestine Confl ict Ronald Wintrobe 135 6. Th e Success of Religion as a Source for Compromise in Divided Empires: Ottoman and Safavid, Past and Present Benjamin Braude 176 vi Contents 7. Geopolitics and the Long- Term Construction of Democracy Randall Collins 198 8. Courts, Constitutions, and the Limits of Majoritarianism Samuel Issacharoff 214 PART III. CONTEMPORARY POWER SHARING QUESTIONS 9. A Revised Th eory of Federacy and a Case Study of Civil War Termination in Aceh, Indonesia Alfred Stepan 231 10. We Forbid! Th e Mutual Veto and Power- Sharing Democracy Joanne McEvoy 253 11. Northern Ireland: Power Sharing, Contact, Identity, and Leadership Ed Cairns 278 12. Public Opinion and Power Sharing in Deeply Divided Places Colin Irwin 295 13. Th e Balkans: Th e Promotion of Power Sharing by Outsiders Florian Bieber 312 14. Governing Polarized Cities Scott A. Bollens 327 15. Power Sharing in Kirkuk: Th e Need for Compromise Liam Anderson 364 16. Power Sharing: An Advocate’s Conclusion Brendan O’Leary 386 List of Contributors 423 Index 425 Ac know ledg ments 437 CHAPTER 1 Power Sharing in Deeply Divided Places: An Advocate’s Introduction Brendan O’Leary Th e Mafi a makes off ers that cannot be refused. In one peace pro cess a poli- tician was once accused of making off ers that no one could understand ( O’Leary 1990). Do these statements explain the diff erence between power and power sharing? Is power coercive capacity, whereas power sharing is incomprehensible? Power sharing is not incomprehensible, but it is frequently misunder- stood. To aid comprehension a comparison is useful. In standard En glish, power is the ability to act, to be able to produce an intended eff ect (Russell 1992 [1938]). Th e powerless lack the capacity to do things they might want to do. Th e powerful are in the opposite situation. Power sharing, therefore, suggests spreading access to the capacity to get things done. Power is also a synonym for authority, jurisdiction, control, command, sway, or dominion, as well as the capacity to persuade, induce, constrain, oblige, or force. It fol- lows that power sharing minimally means widening the access of persons or groups to the same domains or attributes. In standard usage power is also “a possession,” “held” by those with authority or infl uence over others, es- pecially public offi cials, governments, offi cers, managements, or establish- ments who constitute what Paul’s Letter to the Romans described as “the powers that be.” Power sharing, therefore, broadens membership of “the powers that be.” It also requires that the included parties have access to key and observable “decision making.” Th ere must be no important “non– decision making” taking place off stage, that is, no hidden possessors of power who 2 Brendan O’Leary control the agenda or exclude some issues from being addressed. Th ere must instead be an open and negotiable public agenda among the power- sharers, or at least among their leaders. Any suppression of (controversial) issues must be mutually agreed upon among those who share power. Th eorists contrast “power to” and “power over” (see Morris 2002; Parsons 1969). “Power to” is ability, “power over” is domination. Th e contrast resem- bles that between “positive- sum” and “zero- sum” relationships. “Positive- sum” power is joint, collaborative, or cooperative. All gain from its exercise, even if the benefi ts are not the same for all. “Zero- sum power,” by contrast, de- scribes a distinct antagonism: if power could be mea sured, then A’s gain and B’s loss would sum to zero. Positive- sum and zero- sum conceptions do not exhaust the logical possibilities of power relations. Th e exercise of power may generate net losses (a “negative sum”) or the mutual ruin of the con- tending parties. It may create winners and losers; there may be disparities in benefi ts among the winners as well as in losses among the losers; and only one party may gain, while the others experience no net losses. Power shar- ing, for its proponents, is defended as “power to.” It enhances collective ca- pacity; it is “positive sum.” Th ose who share will gain from a constructive way of making public decisions, from which all stand to gain, notably through the preservation of order and peace. Critics, by contrast, suggest that power sharing shapes public life at the expense of other and better kinds of politics— more competitive, individualist, or harmonious. Th e opposite of power sharing is power’s monopolization by a person, faction, group, or ga ni za tion, or party. On inspection, it is usually true that the chief power- holder has to delegate some power to or ga nize and maintain the monopoly. But to delegate power is not to share it. Th e principal who delegates requires the delegated agent to perform specifi ed tasks and may withdraw the mandate. Monopolies of power exist, at least formally, in tyrannies, despotisms, military autocracies, monarchies, lordships, papacies, theocracies, and one- party dictatorships. Th ey also exist, however, in democracies, a more unset- tling idea. To say that democracy may coexist with monopolistic domination requires no commitment to theories suggesting that behind the façade of electoral competition lies the power of a ruling class or a power elite (see, e.g., Miliband 1980 [1969]; Domhoff 1990; Mills 1956). For example, no matter how competitive or free elections may be, critical po liti cal power can be monopolized between elections by the incumbent president, prime min- ister, cabinet, and nominated judges associated with the dominant party, Introduction 3 ethos, or ideology. Even a temporary domination (between elections) is nevertheless domination, and the opportunities for elected leaders to domi- nate their societies against widespread or deeply held public preferences are signifi cant (see, e.g., Nordlinger 1981, 92– 94, 111– 12, 130– 32). Th at democracy might lead to domination was the theme of the “tyr- anny of the majority,” which deeply concerned eighteenth- century republi- cans, such as James Madison, and nineteenth- century liberals, such as Alexis de Tocqueville and John Stuart Mill. Th ey were mostly preoccupied, how- ever, with the impact of that possible tyranny on the individual’s property and liberty (including the individual’s religious beliefs) rather than on national, ethnic, or linguistic minorities as such (Madison, Hamilton, and Jay 1987 [1788]; Mill 1997, 5– 6, 81– 82, 192– 94; de Tocqueville 1988 [1835, 1840], vol. 1., chap. 7, esp. 250ff ). Democracy is, however, also straightforwardly compatible with the (tem- porary) tyranny of a minority, especially democracies with institutions that encourage the “winner” to take all. For example, an ideological faction, not supported by a majority of voters in a country, may nevertheless control a cabinet, which in turn controls a party, and which in turn controls a legisla- ture. In consequence, law or public policy may be dictated in the interests of the faction as long as its control is maintained. Defi ning Power Sharing, Deeply Divided Places, and Well- Ordered States Th ese considerations suggest the following broad defi nition of power sharing: Any set of arrangements that prevent one agent, or or ga nized collective agency, from being the “winner who holds all critical power,” whether temporarily or permanently. Th is suggestion explains why the synonyms of power sharing usually include the following generally positive connotations: “co ali tion” or “cooperative” government and “consensual” and “inclusive” decision making. Critics of power sharing just as powerfully insist upon negative connotations. Th ey refer to power- sharing arrangements as “rudderless” or “leaderless,” and they complain of “stalemated,” “deadlocked,” or “blocked” decision making. Th e general defi nition of power sharing just suggested is broad if not vague. It does not, for example, specify how power is shared among the parties. It is capacious enough to include arrangements such as the Roman Republic’s executive, based on the annual election of two consuls, and its tribunes, who

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.