, ! Possible Experience Understanding Kant's Critique ofPure Reason Arthur W. Collins UNIVERSITY OF CALIF Berkeley Los Ange UniversityofCalifornia Press Berkeleyand LosAngeles,California UniversityofCalifornia Press,Ltd. London, England ©1999by TheRegentsoftheUniversityofCalifornia LibraryofCongressCataloging-in-PublicationData Collins,Arthur W. Possibleexperience:understandingKant's Cri tiqueofpurereasonIbyArthurW.Collins. p, em, Includesbibliographical referencesand index. ISBN0-52.0-21498-6(alk.paper).- ISBN0-520-21499-4 (pbk.:alk.paper) 1.Kant,Immanuel, 1724-1804. Kritikdel'reinenVernunft. 2.Knowledge, of. 3. Causation. 4. Reason. LTitle. B2779·C54 1999 121-dc21 98-33670 CIP Printed intheUnitedStatesofAmerica 9 87 6 5 4 3 2 I Thepaper usedinthispublicationmeetsthemini mumrequirements ofAmericanNationalStandards forInformationSciences-PermanenceofPaperfor PrintedLibrary Materials, ANSIZ39.48-1984. for Rufus andJacob Contents Preface IX Note on Texts and Abbreviations xix Kant and the CartesianPhilosophy ofMind 1. I 2. Subjectivismversus Idealism 8 3· Idealism and TranscendentalIdealism 20 4· AreThings-in-Themselves Noumena? 26 k 5. The Conceptof Representation 31 ,qI ~ 6. "Space Isin Us" 60 7· Outer Causes ofPerception 73 'I 8. Kant Nota Foundationalist 82 ,I 9· The "How-Possible" Questions 91 iI 10. The "Clue" for Finding the Categories 101 q The Parallelism ofInner and Outer Sense 1 I >tIL °7 12. The SubjectofExperience 121 'I 13· How Representations Make Objects Possible 14° II 14· Objects and Empirical Realism 143 15· The IdealisticUnderstanding ofKant's 11 TheoreticalPhilosophy 153 II 11 Notes 183 Index 199 ! 11 vii Preface This bookidentifies and triesto remove thegreatestsingleobstaclefaced I bystudents andteachers intheirattempts to understand Kant's theoret- I icalphilosophy.Wecan approachthis obstaclethroughthe phrase tran- i scendentalidealism, whichisone of the titles Kant giveshis philosophy I as a whole. These words naturally suggest that Kant ispresentingsome + ,i \~.I"\~~ Jill..-j~fl.~~ i~ form ofidealism, but infact heisnot. QhilosQJ2.b.J;: an,Y.£2.!l: I. ¥i'<\1")~' \:§ption"_Q..Lcon§.Sioll§Q~ss knowl<:,4.g~..e£s;or5!illgJ5l ~hish.c!.h.~~!h!.~ and .. iln~~iaj~.!.Y.~P.l2r~b-"c:.!24jrL~J?£tk!!f~_~~!s..ali!ie§..Jh~1~2fl~ljl.1~Q..ru; I'",}< we I i ~u1l!if!i:.Ifthere are nonmental realities at all, they are positedreal- 1\ : itiesor,ifwe can knowthingsoutside ourminds, they are known medi- I i atelyandbyinference from ourunmediatedexperienceofmentalthings. II ii' Apartfrom afewvoicesto the contrary,most readersofKant, from well ~, before the appearance ofthe Critique ofPure Reasonup to the present, il II have assumed that transcendental idealism is, first of all, idealism, and !1 that the relevant problem of interpretation isthat of finding the differ- ii ence, ifany,.between Kant's idealism and that of other idealistphiloso- ;i phers. I say that this view is incorrect and that its dominance has been 1!I1 extremely harmful to thinking about Kant. Although I approach Kant Ii throughonly one issue,the discussioninvolvesthe maincontentionsand I-I features of Kant's theoretical philosophy. I am convinced that a sound II understanding of this issue is crucial to comprehension of the Critique 11 ofPure Reason as a whole. II H Ix Preface x Readers frequently find some version of phenomenalism in Kant's account of experience and knowledge. For our purposes, we can treat phenomenalism as a form of idealism becausepheno~ne1!.a..l~§.!Q...!~..!!_4Y£: tiye; and it is!!..Q!1!'1)el"!!gLilii!lg§!h<l!..fl!:~..r_~_slllS~c!· Byincluding phenom enalism as a variety of idealist interpretation, I am willing to disregard distinctions some philosophers want to respect." A putative contrast between phenomenalism and idealism issupported by the thought that .12.hf.l}om~lla1.~QLc!Q~not.g.~D.Y.._!h.e..~2Cj§!~pceof.fl.2!nnental..2.£j~~s ~~.!<;:~~.1?~e.~e.~!~_~1];..~~pJa}~at!o.n9-f..Lll.§.t1Yh?,:!,1~!£h.£QI~ts ~. Forexam ple, theyare "logicalconstructsoutof sense data." Acommonobjective of the reduction attempted by a phenomenalist logical construction is ontological parsimony. The same parsimony is intended by any phe nomenalist translation of statements about physical objects into a lan guage the referring terms of which are confinedto sense data and other mental existents. While we ordinarily allow for the existence of mental realities suchas thoughts and perceptualexperiences and also allowfor the existence of outer nonmental objects as entities in addition to and otherthanmentalthings,the logicalconstruction,or the translationpro gram, proposes the deletion of the nonmental objects from our ontol ogy.fujygca!~§_.Qf-2h~!1.9m~!l~Jj§Q1.sp.~'!!~.()fo..l.!!~Ll'h.~i<,:aLo!?i.~~!~.QllLgg ~Q.Lt:b~r~Qy.gQJ~.e.YQPSL<l!}.5m!Ql()gygnfle,J;l!a.:I.tl1ings,c1ll.cJ..tl1.LlSC1Q.i~e.C1J: i~£12!£logy. Ihavealso includedunderthe broadumbrellaofidealismviewssome timesascribedto Kantthatare notreductiveandthatmerelyconfinethe evidencefor the existenceofnonmentalthingsto mentalrepresentations. Such theories are not phenomenalist, butthey do belong to the classof views that Kant brings together under the heading "problematic ideal ism." They do notclose the door to skepticism but virtually invite the skeptical thought, "Any amount of such 'evidence' is compatible with the nonexistence of outer objects," and the skeptical question, "With what right do we regard mental states as evidence for nonrnental reali ties at all?" Again, manyreaders thinkthat, in the face of criticalreactions to the obviouslyidealistictenetsofthe first editionofthe CritiqueofPureRea son, Kantcontradictedthosetenetsinthe secondedition,or exacerbated contradictions thatwere already present in the first edition. The understandable thought that Kant's transcendental idealism is a genuine form of idealism is conveyed, for example, by the definition of the termidealisminSimonBlackburn's 1994 OxfordDictionaryofPhi- Preface xi losophy: "Any doctrine holding that reality isfundamentally mental in nature ..." and "major forms of idealism include subjective idealism, or the position better called immaterialism and associated with Berke ley,according to which to exist isto beperceived, transcendentalideal ism, and absolute idealism" [emphasis addedj.?Ifwe judge in the light of two hundred years of idealist interpretation of Kant, this dictionary entry seems to be in good order. If, on the other hand, that interpreta tion is fundamentally wrong, as I mean to argue, the explanation for such awidespread misunderstandingmust lienotmerely withthis army of readers but just as much with Kant himself. Indeed, the supposition thatKant'sphilosophyisaform ofidealismisbyno means asimple prej udice read out of the words "transcendentalidealism." The Critique of Pure Reason abounds in apparent confirmations of that supposition. Manyconfirmations take the form ofwhatsoundlikeflat statements of an idealisticthesis. There are also fundamental and large-scale develop ments inKant'ssystem thatseem to requireidealismifthey are to make any sense at all. For illustration of the flat statements, consider Kant's repeated contention that we can apprehend only appearances and that appearances are "representations" and can exist only in our faculty of representation. Surely all the things that exist in our faculty of repre sentationare mentalthings. Asan illustrationofthe fundamental devel opments,considerKant's grandeffortto showthatobjectsofexperience are products of a synthesis we perform, that is, of a mental combinato rial activity operating on mental representations. In light of these Kantian assertions and doctrines, it would be sur prising if most students of Kant did not find an idealism in his work, since the appearance of idealism could not be much more prominent than it is. In the last chapter of this book, I discuss a number of inter pretations of Kant byfirst-rate philosophers, past and present, in order to convey something of the history, the persistence, and the variety of idealisticreadings,andIalsotake note oftheworkofseveral recent non idealistic commentators. For the main body of this book, I do not talk about the interpretations of other writers on Kant. In order to under stand the widespread incorrect interpretation, Iuse only Kant's writing as the source for the seeming idealism of his work. One olJ.1}e feat..!1r~ t;;hflct.mgl<e.t.4~J?.!'.~.s.~n,t".§tlJ4y'...gJ~Jig£t~I~j§_t1}5:.~~!!!;;Q!J2!LiLgiY~,§ ..!9~.th~ llj;Q.Ql.~.m.QLr~.<:(?}1c:iling" the,l11o,s,t..p.~()miQ~ll.La.!.1:4.l.11~~k~.s!i!.1:K.lfl$_a.listic:.: §.olll1clil1gassertionsa119thf:l11esin.I\a.£lt~itl1 a'Yh<?J!Y}1.o.!},i4~.~E§.ti£",2.,\1t JQ2!~:J will also locatethe interpretationofKantthatIdefendhere with xii Preface respect to the small minority of recent commentators who do not pre sent Kant asan idealist. This book isneither a briefgeneralcommentaryonthe Critique ofPure Reason nor an introductory text. Iaddress only one topic, albeit a per vasivetopic, and Itry to make only one point, albeit a point of funda mental importance.The book discussesprominentthemesinKant's the oretical philosophy,withthe singleobjective ofmakingitpossibleto see apparentlyidealistic passageswithoutthe idealism.Itisacommonplace that Descartes's introduction of the egocentric skeptical perspective in philosophy has had and continues to have a decisive role in modern thinking. Inwhatfollows, Itty to sho~how t~broadll: Cartesian0l.l;.t- k' I~an!_en~E.lC?~th~ w":!.!.~g§a~~~!tj.ons lookofreade!:sof t9seeinhis that are qu~~~l~.~~imLc.?D.~~s~~hLtakes him~~!fto_ J2~m<t~1f!.g.Ofcourse, his vocabulary and rhetoric are partly to blame for misunderstandings. The term transcendental idealism is only the most obvious example. In spite of such difficultiesin Kant's texts, the great preponderance of the misreading of Kant arises from Cartesian presuppositions on the part ofthe reader that make it hard or impossi bleto recognize the verymany clear indications ofKant's oppositionto idealism, root and branch. The presentwork concentrates on Kant's conception of "representa tions," on hisconception of space and time, on the nonfoundationalist stance ofhisfamous "How-possible?" questions,and on hisdeepargu ment against the verypossibility of a Cartesiansubject enduringintime while surveying the contents of its own consciousness. I do not find a singlediscussion in the Critique or in any other of Kant's works where he presentsthis last argumentinfull.Idrawon diversematerialson this point, most prominently on the Paralogisms and the Refutation of Ide alismbutalsoonKant's repeateddiscussionsoftheneedtorepresentthe unity of time spatially. Where the precise wording of the text seems important for my single objective, I have not hesitated to present very detailed analyses of it. In these explications, I believethat the structure ofKant's argumentscan beusedto more or lessprove hisentirely anti idealist intentions. Thesections ofthe Critique towhichIhavedevotedthemost detailed examination are the Transcendental Aesthetic and parts of the Tran- r Preface xiii 'I scendentalDeduction ofthe Categories, aswellasthe above-mentioned Refutation and Paralogisms. In orderto profitfrom the reflections that are presented here, it seemsto me that a reader must have made, or be intheprocessofmaking, asubstantialeffortto understandKantthrough hardstudyofthe Critique.Undergraduateandgraduatestudentsarecer tainly to befound among such readers of Kant, and I intend this work to beof interestand ofuseto students at all levels,aswellasto profes sional philosophers and Kant scholars. Icame to most of the ideas pre sented here inthe contextofefforts to help students in numerous semi nars on the Critique. I hope that their understanding was helped, and since I am sure that mine was, I am grateful to those students. I have translated all ofthe quoted passages myselfwith consultationand help from othertranslations. Atthe same time, Ihavebeencareful not to let an appearanceofsupportfor myunderstanding ofapassage reston my translation. Where Ifind that options available to a translator impinge significantly on the issue of idealism, I discuss the translation explicitly and Iinclude the Germantextin the notes. :1 I i My interests inthis topic are not merelyhistorical.The skepticalmoves I that lead to one or another form of idealism in metaphysics are part of 'j awidelysharedphilosophicalinheritance. AbroadlyCartesianoutlook ,I ~; stilldominates the preliminary "set" from whichphilosophicaltheoriz ,1 il ingtakes it start. The tenacity ofthis preliminary outlook derives from :1 I! its apparentfitwith obvious facts about experience. For the most part, Ii ifnotinallcases,we knowwhat our beliefsare evenifthey turn outto :1 befalse beliefs.Weknow howthings appear to us, even ifappearances II prove to be radically misleading. What is the subject matter of the knowledge that survives erroneous beliefs and illusory appearances? II Most philosophers accept the idea that the subject matter belongs, in Il somesense,tothecontentsofourconsciousness. ThismuchoftheCarte ~l sian method of doubt and its idealist resolution is retained, even by philosopherswho repudiateDescartes's dualism and conceptionofmen r tal substance. Our states of beliefand other "mental representations," together with our perceptual experiences, are inner realities of some kind, although there is no consensus whatever ahout the kind of reali ties these mental things are. Debates flourish about the nature of these inner mental representations, while the idea that immediate experience
Description: