ebook img

Politics and the imagination PDF

217 Pages·2010·0.995 MB·English
by  GeussRaymond
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Politics and the imagination

POLITICS AND THE IMAGINATION This page intentionally left blank POLITICS AND THE IMAGINATION Raymond Geuss princeton university press princeton and oxford Copyright © 2010 by Princeton University Press Published by Princeton University Press, 41 William Street, Princeton, New Jersey 08540 In the United Kingdom: Princeton University Press, 6 Oxford Street, Woodstock, Oxfordshire OX20 1TW All Rights Reserved Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Geuss, Raymond. Politics and the imagination / Raymond Geuss. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-691-14227-2 (hardcover : alk. paper) — ISBN 978-0-691-14228-9 (pbk. : alk. paper) 1. Political science—Philosophy. 2. Imagination (Philosophy) I. Title. JA71.G47 2010 320.01—dc22 2009017105 British Library Cataloging-in-Publication Data is available This book has been composed in Sabon Printed on acid-free paper. ∞ press.princeton.edu Printed in the United States of America 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Contents Preface vii Acknowledgments xv I Political Judgment in Its Historical Context 1 II The Politics of Managing Decline 17 III Moralism and Realpolitik 31 IV On the Very Idea of a Metaphysics of Right 43 V The Actual and Another Modernity Order and Imagination in Don Quixote 61 VI Culture as Ideal and as Boundary 81 VII On Museums 96 VIII Celan’s Meridian 117 IX Heidegger and His Brother 142 X Richard Rorty at Princeton Personal Recollections 151 XI Melody as Death 164 XII On Bourgeois Philosophy and the Concept of “Criticism” 167 Bibliography 187 Index 193 This page intentionally left blank Preface It has sometimes been claimed that the oldest continuous fragment of Western philosophical thought is a brief remark attributed by a commen- tator on the works of Aristotle, Simplicius, to the sixth-century Ionian philosopher Anaximander: [λέγει ὁ Ἀναξίμανδροs] ἐξ (cid:1)ὡν δὲ ἡ γένεσίs ἐστι τοˆιs ο(cid:1)ὐσι, καὶ τὴν ϕθορὰν εἰs ταῦτα γίνεσθαι κατὰ τὸ χρεών διδόναι γὰρ αὐτὰ δίκην καὶ τίσιν ἀλλήλοιs τ(cid:1)ηs ἀδικίαs κατὰ τὴν το(cid:1)υ χρόνου τάξιν.1 Almost nothing about the text or interpretation of any part of this ar- chaic statement is uncontroversial, and any translation of it must be highly speculative, but the approximate sense seems to be: [Anaximander says that] from whatever it is that things have their origin, of necessity they must also have their destruction into that, for they must give justice and make amends to each other for their injustice according to the order of time. Whatever the exact details of the metaphysical views which fi nd ex- pression in this fragment, in one respect its basic meaning is clear enough. It is a slightly spruced-up and intellectualized—and characteristically gloomy—Hellenic version of a piece of enduring peasant wisdom: men will reap what they sow; what goes around, comes around. A kind of order which is both moral and “natural” prevails in the world, and this order will eventually, but necessarily—κατὰ τὸ χρεών—reestablish itself. Any apparent violations of this order will show themselves in the longer run to be mere momentary aberrations. The gloomy gloss on this thought consists in the tacit assertion that being-something—being anything at all—is already an injustice that deserves, and will incur, punishment. Even to be in existence at all makes something culpable.2 If one ignores for a moment the pessimistic twist,3 one can see why the rest of this piece 1 Hermann Diels and Walther Kranz(Weidman, 1951), Fragment 1, p. 89. For further analysis of this fragment see Friedrich Nietzsche, “Die Philosophie im tragischen Zeitalter,” inKritische Studienausgabe, ed. Giorgio Colli and Mazzino Montinari (de Gruyter, 1967) vol. 1, pp. 817–22, or the highly speculative Heidegger, “Der Spruch des Anaximandros,” inHolzwege(Klostermann, 1950), pp. 296–344. 2 As Mephistopheles puts it in Faust (line 1339f): “denn alles was entsteht / ist wert daß es zugrunde geht”[“Everything that comes into being / deserves to perish”]. 3 One can trace a development here from this form of metaphysical pessimism to a politi- cal version of the same thing in 1938. See also Brecht, “An die Nachgeborenen” (1938): viii PREFACE of peasant wisdom is still so deeply entrenched even in modern and pur- portedly enlightened ways of thinking and why the view expressed is so diffi cult to eradicate: it is too comforting to lose. Wrongdoers may seem invincible now, but eventually they will pay. So powerful is the human imagination that people can take some comfort in this thought, even if they know they will no longer themselves be around to view the reestab- lishment of the “natural order,” the triumph of “justice,” etc. Much in- genuity over two and a half millennia has been devoted to fi nding a way of putting this belief in a form which hides its essentially mythological structure and makes it seem like a sober and cognitively well-grounded assessment of the world. At some point in the past, this story acquired an imaginative competi- tor. Instead of deriving solace from the idea that everything will always “really” remain the same, so that violations of “natural justice” will right themselves and all will be as it was, people begin to think of doing some- thing themselves to improve the future, and they begin to derive consola- tion from the fact that no matter how diffi cult things seem now to be, they can imagine that things will get better, or at any rate they could get better if everyone pulled together in the right direction. It isn’t the thought of the basic invariability of the world that gives solace, but the fantasy of its plasticity, of a potentially infi nite process of change and improvement, of the unlimited transformation of the world into something more perfect and more to our taste. How much of reality can, however, be changed? To jump ahead from the sixth-century BC to the beginning of the twenty-fi rst century, we see that we still have no settled attitude on the limits of the malleability of reality. In 2002 a reporter interviewed a high-ranking but unnamed aide to U.S. president George W. Bush. Let us call this aide “Anonymos.” Anonymos is reported to have said that journalists were part of the “reality-based community . . . people who believe that decisions emerge from your judicious study of discernible reality. . . . That’s not the way the world works anymore. . . . We’re [i.e., the United States] an empire now, and when we act, we create our own reality. And while you’re studying that reality—judiciously, as you will— Man sagt mir: Iß und trink du! Sei froh, daß du hast! Aber wie kann ich essen und trinken, wenn Ich dem Hungernden entreiße, was ich esse, und Mein Glas Wasser dem Verdurstenden fehlt? Und doch esse und trinke ich. This poem does not yet express a fully developed ecological consciousness, because in 1938 hunger and thirst were “merely” a political problem of distribution, and not a pro- blem of absolute depletion. Finally to ecology: see George Monbiot, “Is the Pope Gay?” in Bring on the Apocalypse (Grove Atlantic, 2008), p. 17. PREFACE ix we’ll act again, creating other realities, which you can study too, and that’s how things will sort out. We’re history’s actors. . . . and you, all of you, will be left to just study what we do.”4 This statement draws attention to a suffi cient number of extremely important features of all human politics to merit some further consider- ation. As the young Heidegger noted, human beings are always “ahead of themselves”;5 our lives are constituted by uncompleted projects, and anyone with no concernful tasks outstanding, anyone with no unfi nished business in the world, would not be alive at all. Vixit. My relation to my own future, and our relation to our future, is always “open” and to some extent “ungrounded.”6 I don’t have conclusive reasons for the projects I have—they are neither fully explicable nor fully “justifi able” by my antecedent beliefs and desires—nor are any of my projects fully under my own power, but rather they are always at the mercy of external circumstances and events over which I have little control. To act is in an important sense always to create something new, an object, a change in an existing situation, a new reality. Politicians, in particular, are sup- posed to deal with emergencies as they arise and to ward off threats to those aspects of the status quo that are particularly valued, but they are also sometimes supposed to change the way things are, to create new facts. Margaret Thatcher saw this very clearly when she embarked on her policy of rejecting “consensus politics” in favor of trying to bring into ex- istence new brute realities with which all other politicians would have to learn to deal, one way or the other, and Anonymos put some similar im- portant points in a salutarily provocative way. Any organized attempt at improvement of our situation will include some at least minimal exercise of the imagination, in that it will require agents to think of ways in which their environment or modes of acting could be different from what they now are. What is provocative about Anonymos’s statement is not the claim about creating new facts, but the suggestion that the government of the United States was so limitlessly powerful it could successfully con- jure a completely new reality into existence without regard to antecedent conditions. This, of course, is the point at which Heidegger,7 and most of the rest of us, I trust, would part company from Anonymos. This collection puts together essays I have written during the past few years that deal with several issues concerning the nature of the imagina- tion and its role in politics. These issues include such questions as: What 4 Ron Suskind, “Faith, Certainty, and the Presidency of George W. Bush,” in New York Times Magazine,17 October 2004. 5 Heidegger, Sein und Zeit (Niemeyer, 1963), §§31–32, 41, 68a. 6 Ibid.,§58. 7 Ibid., §§29, 31, 38.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.