ebook img

Poetry and Politics PDF

229 Pages·20.457 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Poetry and Politics

POETRY AND POLITICS by MORTIMER J. ADLER INTRODUCTION BY SAMUEL HAZO DUQUESNE UNIVERSITY PRESS PITTSBURGH, PA. Editions E. Nauwelaerts, Louvain, Belgium All rights reserved © 1965 by DUQUESNE UNIVERSITY Selected and revised chapters from a work entitled ART AND PRUDENCE by Mortimer J. Adler originally published in 1937 by Longmans, Green and Co. This revision is published by arrangement with David McKay Co., Inc. Printed in the United States of America Ao PRESS, LTD. Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 65-16137 TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGE I TRODUCTION VII CHAPTER ONE Plato ................................... . CHAPTER TWO ristotle . .. .. . . . . .. . .. . . . .. . .. . .. .. . . . .. .. 19 CHAPTER THREE Christianity . . . .. . . .. . .. .. .. . .. .. . . . . . . .. .. 52 CHAPTER FOUR Democracy . .. . . .. . . . . . .. .. .. . .. .. . . .. . . . .. 91 CHAPTER FIVE Historical Transformations . . .. . .. . .. . . . .. . .. 113 CHAPTER SIX Art and Prudence 143 NOTES ...................................... 172 Introduction Few relations are more complicated and delicate than that of a poet and society. Even the most tentative consideration of the changing nature of this relationship compels us to face anew not only some of the basic questions of art but also those which go beyond art. What is a poet? What is the purpose of poetry? What is the poet's obligation to his fellow man? Is there a way of reconciling the world of art-in which the poet works with the world of prudence-in which the poet lives? Is art merely a cultural or social ornament, or does it proceed from the very fountainhead of the cultural life of man? And if poetry is central to human culture, what are the proper criteria for criticizing and evaluating it? All of these questions underscore the importance of the poet's place in society as well as the problems related to it. One way to begin to understand what is involved is to consider, briefly, the history of this relationship as philosophers, critics and poets themselves have described it. Such a consideration, though valuable in itself for aesthetic reasons, can have other assets since the way in which a poet is regarded, not only by his fellow poets but also by other members of his society, often influences the esteem or disrepute in which poetry itself is held. One of Dr. Adler's central assumptions in Poetry and Politics, which is a revision of a portion of his Art and Prudence published in 1937, is that such an examination can yield more than merely aesthetic conclusions and that the relationship of the poet and the polis should never be confined to aestheticism alone. VII VIII POETRY AND POLITICS Primitive poets, such as the minstrels whom Homer depicted in The Odyssey, were men whose songs were primarily intended to give pleasure; no more than that was asked of or expected from them. On the other hand, the Old Testament prophets faced the need of "fountaining forth" ( as the etymology of the word-prophet-indicates) the conscience of their people -at times to the chagrin of the Israelites and thus to the prophet's occasional personal unpopularity. For Euripides and Aristophanes, despite their obvious differences as playwrights, the aim of the poetic dramatist was to better his fellow man; poetry, therefore, was meant to subserve and even buttress the moral good of the citizen of the state. Plato, who was equally concerned with preserving the moral good of the state, turned his attention to the poet's way of knowing. He claimed that poets were thrice-removed from the real world of ideas and that, at their best, they were merely instruments to relay the divine afflatus to others. Although Plato did respect the power of poetry to sway its hearers, he had to conclude that poets, being in no way responsible for the beauty and power of their utterances, should be excluded from any society of men who respected the primacy of reason. The irony of this position, as Dr. Adler suggests, is that Plato's commitment to rationalism forced him to espouse a view which his temperament and style seemed to oppose. To be sure, Plato subsequently tempered this view by expressing his willingness to admit poets into the Republic if they could prove that their poems had a use as well as a delight. Like Euripides and Aristophanes, Plato attempted to justify poetry in terms of morality, and the same argument with only minor modifications would be resuscitated by Horace, Sidney and others. Poetry's value, according to this tradition, did not derive from the unique and pleasurable knowledge which only it could afford but from its ability to serve an extrinsic good. In brief, poetry was judged primarily by criteria other than its own. It remained for Aristotle to formulate an approach to poetry by which it could be appreciated and judged according to its fidelity to the laws of its own creation. By remaining dispas sionate, Aristotle was able to detect poetic vakes that Plato's INTRODUCTION lX a priori approach simply overlooked. "Aristotle's method is essentially one of examining observed phenomena with a view to noting their qualities and characteristics," wrote David Daiches in Critical Approaches to Literature. "His concern is the ontological one of discovering what in fact literature is rather than the normative one of describing what it should be. He is describing, not legislating; yet his description is so organ ized as to make an account of the nature of literature involve an account of its function, and its value emerges in terms of its function." For Aristotle, therefore, poets were men who, obeying a natural instinct to imitate and an equally strong instinct for harmony and rhythm, represented men acting in fictive situations governed by laws of probability as irrevocable as the laws of possibility in life. The poetic dramatist, by imitating what could naturally and inevitably happen to a particular man in a particular circumstance, could both delight his audience and purge or purify it into what Walter Jackson Bate has called a "harmonious serenity." In brief, therefore, Aristotle's poet obeyed a basic law of his being by becoming a maker, and the plays that he made ( rooted in irony and capable of arousing the cathartic emotions of awe and pity) could create in his audience a unique pleasure as well as an insight into life that was more philosophical and universal than that found in any other form of expression. In any case, Aristotle did not commit Plato's error in judging poetry by purely extrinsic criteria. Instead he viewed it as an activity anrn,erable to its own organic laws. "Plato confused the study of art with the study of morals," R. A. Scott-James wrote in The Making of Literature. "Aristotle, removing the confusion, created the study of aesthetics. We find, then, that Aristotle in the Poetics takes it for granted that a work of art, whether it be a picture or a poem, is a thing of beauty; and that it affords pleasure appropriate to its kind." While Aristotle established the climate whereby poetry could be judged for its own sake, such subsequent critics as Longinus and Horace gave most of their attention to questions of style. They contributed little to a deeper understanding of the poet's role in society. Longinus' essay "On the Sublime" is a study of linguistic excellence and the various tropes by which such ex- X POETRY AND POLITICS cellence can be achieved. Horace's "Epistle to the Pisos" itself the very embodiment of the critical principles it advo cates-is essentially a collection of well-expressed views on poetry, poetic diction, propriety and various poetic genres. Horace, apart from reiterating the Platonic canon that poetry should be beneficial as well as delightful ( utile et dulce), is ultimately a critic's critic, and his synthesis of previous views of poetry anticipated and set the pattern for the style-con scious tracts of many of his critical descendents, such as Vida, Boileau and Sidney, to name only a few. Questions of style meant little to the early fathers of the Church. The critical positions of the patristic writers, as Dr. Adler considers in detail, were essentially censorial. After objecting to the late Roman poetic dramas as licentious and cor rupting, the Church fathers gravitated quickly to the Platonic position of exclusion. Drama per se was suspect. St. Thomas Aquinas would later establish a philosophical accommodation for art within the Christian tradition by insisting on the moral neutrality of art as art and by indicating that the poet's way of knowledge, though not ratiocinative, was nonetheless a valid way of apprehending truth. But St. Thomas' views were lamrntably abbreviated; a fuller exploration of the Scholastic position would have to wait for neo-Thomists like Jacques Maritain and Thomas Gilby in a much later century. Despite this lag in the development of a philosophy of aesthetics, the medieval church gradually did attempt to make its peace with the dramatic medium which the patristic writers had so severely condemned. Little by little the clergy put drama to the service of religion. They originated mimetic representations of various Biblical stories for the edification of the faithful. In essence, this primitive use of art for religious purposes was simply a baptism of the older Hellenic view of art. Out of this would grow the cycles of York, Townely, Chester and Coventry, the morality plays, the interludes, early English comedies like "Gammar Gurton's Needle" and "Ralph Roister Doister," Seneca-like tragedies such as "Gorboduc" and "The Misfor tunes of Arthur," and ultimately the full flowering of Renais sance poetic drama from Lyly, Peele, Greene, Kyd and INTRODUCTION XI Marlowe to Chapman, Dekker, Heywood, Ben Jonson and, at the apogee, Shakespeare himself. Although the early church dramas were the seed out of which the great dramas of the Renaissance grew, the rudimen tary views of Aquinas on the nature of art and poetic knowl edge did not spawn a similar aesthetic evolution. Among Renaissance critical documents, for example, Sir Philip Sidney's "Apology for Poetry" recast the old notion of the poet as a moral teacher as a defense against the dismissive attacks of such early humanists as Roger Ascham and Stephen Gosson. The echoes in Sidney are Platonic, Aristotelian and Horatian rather than Thomistic, and most of the other Renaissance critics wrote in a similar vein. Following the profuse but often repetitive Renaissance specu lations on poetry and poetic diction and aside from the subse quent judiciousness of a Dr. Samuel Johnson or the critical flexibility of John Dryden, no new and formidable insights into the relation of the poet and society appeared in English letters until the end of the eighteenth century. It began when William Wordsworth wrote that a true poet was a man speak ing to other men and that there was a moral dignity derivable from the pleasure of poetry. Other romantic apologists went further. For Coleridge-and, a few years afterward, for Shelley as well-the poet was not only a maker or a man speak ing to other men but a seer, a visionary. Coleridge called artistic creation "a repetition in the finite mind of the eternal act of creation in the infinite I Am." Shelley would subse quently identify poets as "the unacknowledged legislators of the world," implying that men in possession of the divinizing power of the imagination were the true and ultimate spokesmen and shapers of their societies-not in a geographical, partisan or social sense, but spiritually. Similarly, when Keats cham pioned a life of "sensations" rather than of "thoughts," he was extolling every romantic poet's way of seeing the world. Aubrey De Selencourt put the matter tersely by stressing that poetry for Keats and his fellow romantics "was a way of pene trating to the ultimate mystery of human life-not a garland to adorn it, but a power to mold it." Such a view, rather than condemning the poet as a pariah or tolerating his poems as Xll POETRY A TD POLITICS sugarcoated presentations of religion, ethics or civics, placed him at the very center of the life of society. Moreover, for Coleridge and the other romantics, poetry was not merely what issued in belles lctlres; rather it was the source of all vital manifestations of culture and civilization, i.e., architecture, music, government, philosophy, literature and so forth. As the nineteenth century progressed, Matthew Arnold, who advocated a similar view of poetry as both the soul and leaven of social life, looked to poets to reveal life's "high seriousness," and he urged critics to educate the rapidly burgeoning English middle class to the beauty of poetry which, more than religion, could raise the level of social life. This was not an echo of Plato's insistence in the Laws that poetry serve a utilitarian purpose in order to be admitted into the Republic; this was an affirmation of poetry's redemptive and educative possibilities in, of and by itself. To put it in other words, as T. S. Eliot did in The Use of Poetry and the Use of Criticism, "poetry is not religion, but it is a capital substitute for religion." The effect of this was that the experience of poetry, according to Arnold, was essentially the very means by which gradually urbanizing societies could insure and maintain their civilization. In America, Ralph Waldo Emerson and Walt Whitman espoused the same view; their writings were more overtly influ enced by transcendental and romantic thought, but the social role ascribed to the poet in a democratic society was not far different in its ultimate effect from the Arnoldian vision. In our own time the dialectic continues. I. A. Richards has perpetuated some of Arnold's theories and embellished them with h:s affective, semantic and psychological dicta. T. S. Eliot, who in 1928 in The Sacred J,V ood called poetry a "superior amusement," had for years insisted upon a reading of poetry with closer attention to words, techniques, metrics and so forth in order that the total experience of the poem might result in a "development of sensibility." For Eliot the poet is pri marily an artist, and the poem's value emanates from the reader's experience of it per se and in the context of a poetic tradition that it is meant to further. John Dewey, whom Dr. Adler considers at some length in Chapter IV, took the position that poetry is a means of "social education," and this inevi- INTRODUCTION Xlll tably places him in a tradition that begins with Aristotle and continues to Arnold and Eliot, although Dewey can never be considered as profound a critic as they. Concerning the poet's role in society, there is a rich literature in several traditions. Dr. Adler, who writes more as a political philosopher than a literary critic, has prudently concentrated on those dominant traditions around which the key opinions have pola~ized. If he has chosen to examine the political and social implications of a problem that many literary critics have slighted in favor of aesthetic considerations, these same critics should consider his inquiries as beneficial supplements to their own. Certainly, poetry's social echoes are as unmistakable now as they have been in the past. Many of the supra-aesthetic problems raised by Greek and Shakespearian tragedy are again raised by the poetry of today as it is manifested in verse, fiction or the contemporary film. Dr. Adler has proceeded where most literary critics would, with aesthetic justification, stop, but, by proceeding, he has shown that all the questions that should be asked of and about poetry need not be exclusively aesthetic. SAMUEL HAzO

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.