ebook img

Pierre Gassendi: From Aristotelianism to a New Natural Philosophy PDF

260 Pages·1987·6.59 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Pierre Gassendi: From Aristotelianism to a New Natural Philosophy

PIERRE GASSENDI SYNTHESE HISTORICAL LIBRARY TEXTS AND STUDIES IN THE HIS TOR Y OF LOGIC AND PHILOSOPHY Editors: N. KRETZMANN, Cornell University G. NUCHELMANS, University ofL eyden Editorial Board: J. BERG, Munich Institute of Technology L. M. DE RUK, University of Leyden D. P. HENR Y, University ofM anchester J. HINTIKKA, Florida State University, Tallahassee B. MATES, University of California, Berkeley J. E. MURDOCH, Harvard University G. PATZIG, UniversityofG6ttingen VOLUME 30 BARRY BRUNDELL Saint Paul's National Seminary, Sydney, Australia PIERRE GASSENDI From Aristotelianism to a New Natural Philosophy D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY A MEMBER OF THE KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERS GROUP DORDRECHTjBOSTONjLANCASTERjTOKYO Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Brundell, Barry, 1939- Pierre Gassendi:From Aristotelianism to a new natural philosophy. (Synthese historical library; v. 30) Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Gassendi, Pierre, 1592-1655. 2. Aristotle-Influence. 3. Epicurus Influence. r. Title. II. Series. B1887.B84 1987 194 86-31348 ISBN-l3: 978-94-010-8187-0 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-009-3793-2 DOl: 10.1007/978-94-009-3793-2 Published by D. Reidel Publishing Company, P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, Holland. Sold and distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada by Kluwer Academic Publishers, 101 Philip Drive, Assinippi Park, Norwell, MA 02061, U.S.A. In all other countries, sold and distributed by Kluwer Academic Publishers Group, P.O. Box 322,3300 AH Dordrecht, Holland. All Rights Reserved © 1987 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st 1987 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner To the memory of Nellie and Rupe. our parents. CONTENTS Preface ix Introduction Pierre Gassendi I Manuscripts and published works 2 Bibliographical survey 5 Chapter I. Sceptical anti -Aristotelianism 15 Chapter 2. Copernican anti-Aristotelianism 30 Chapter 3. Epicurean anti-Aristotelianism 48 Epicureanism as substitute for Aristotelianism 51 I. Matter and its modes 54 2. Eternity of the world 60 3. Infinite space 61 4. Causality 69 5. Celestial motion 76 Chapter 4. Empirical anti-Aristotelianism 83 I. Logical writings: from Aristotelian dialectic to Epicurean canonic 84 2. Cognition: the physical and physiological processes 86 3. Cognition: the 'psychological' processes 91 4. Empirical anti-Aristotelianism 98 5. The 'sceptical crisis' 104 Chapter 5. "A truer philosophy" 108 1. Atoms and the void 113 2. The substance of physical causes 118 3. Obscurity vanquished 133 Conclusion 137 Notes 144 Bibliography 228 Index 246 PREFACE Pierre Gassendi (1592-1655) lived in three civilizations in the span of one life-time: medieval ecclesiastic, Renaissance humanist and modern scientific; and he never cut himself loose from any of them. It is probably because he managed to be at home in all three that history has allocated to him a position somewhere on the fringe of the inner circle of genius in the seventeenth-century scientific revolution. While he was not a front-runner, Gassendi was nevertheless a pioneer of modern corpuscularianism and his influence on the development of empirical science was truly international. It is precisely because Gassendi was a figure of the second rank - a significant but lesser luminary - that we need to examine his work closely, for the less famous contemporaries help us to explain what the great ones do. It might seem that Gassendi has received his share of attention from scholars, even though it is sometimes suggested otherwise. Several full length monographs have been published in the past three decades, and there have been a number of articles in scholarly journals. Yet, despite the indisputable worth of these studies, the picture of Gassendi that has emerged from them has been partial and at times wide of the mark, so that the true story remains to be told. The reason for offering this study, therefore, is that it aims to present, if not the definitively true account, at least a "truer" account than has hitherto been given of the work of this well-known but inadequately understood architect of the mechanical philosophy. Philosopher of the more probable that he was, Gassendi would entirely approve of the aim; one hopes that he would also approve of the conclusions. This book should be of interest to scholars and students of the history and philosophy of science, and to anyone who has an interest in the intellectual history of the seventeenth century. The focus of the study is Gassendi's design to bring about what amounted to a revolution in natural philosophy, and the cultural background of the late Renaissance and early modern era are presented as the context which goes far towards making his radical ambitions intelligible. The aim has been to study Gassendi's work in the light of his own avowed goals. To achieve that aim a new effort has been made to interpret his almost completely neglected early manuscripts. Particular attention has been paid to some of the more significant developments and modifications of his philosophical positions that are to be discerned by comparing the ix x PREFACE contents of the manuscripts with the later, published version of his philosophy. The conclusions reached by these efforts amount to a new interpretation of Gassendi and his philosophy: Gassendi was not a philosopher who made Epicureanism respectable; nor was he a materialist malgre lui; nor was he a collaborator with Marin Mersenne in resisting a sceptical crisis. He was essentially an anti-Aristotelian promoter of Epicureanism, the philosophy which he deemed more suitable for the needs of the seventeenth century, both for supporting the Christian faith and for enabling philosophers to participate in and contribute to the progress of the new experimental and observational sciences. lowe a debt of gratitude to many people. Many scholars have given generously of their time, advice and support; in particular I wish to thank Dr D.R. Oldroyd, Dr O.R. Bloch, Dr A.C. Crombie and Dr J.A. Schuster for their assistance, and my friends and former teachers in the School of History and Philosophy of Science in the University of New South Wales for providing a community of scholarship. I acknowledge with heartfelt thanks the help that I have received from library staffs in a number of places: at the University of New South Wales, the Bibliotheque Nationale, Paris, the Bibliotheque Municipale, Tours, the Bodleian Library, the University Library and Whipple Library, Cambridge. Finally, I thank my fellow-staff members and the students of St Paul's National Seminary, Sydney, who have given me the space to bring this project to its completion. INTRODUCTION Pierre Gassendi Pierre Gassendi was born in a hill-top village named Champtercier, a few kilometres from Digne in Provence, on the 22nd January, 1592. His father Antoine and mother Francoise were worthy but undistinguished village folk. Gassendi received his early education in the humanities in Digne and Riez, and at the age of twelve years he received tonsure from the Bishop, a rite which signified admission to the clerical state. Thereafter, the rest of his formal education formed part of his training for ordination to the Catholic priesthood and was supervised by the Church authorities. He studied Aristotelian philosophy and Catholic theology for the next eight years (1604-1611) at the college of Aix-en-Provence. Gassendi was a very gifted student. He held the chair of rhetoric at Digne from the age of sixteen, while still completing his own studies. In 1614 he received his doctorate in theology at Avignon, and was thereupon made theologal, or official diocesan teacher of theology and superintendent of theological education. When the chairs of theology and philosophy at Aix fell vacant in the year 1616 Gassendi became a candidate and won both chairs. He chose philosophy. In the same year he was ordained a priest. For the next six years Gassendi occupied the chair of Aristotelian philosophy at Aix. But then his teaching came to an abrupt halt, for the Bishop elected at that time to bring in the Jesuits and to assign the college to their care. This change evidently constituted a tardy implementation of the reform of seminaries decreed by the Council of Trent.1 As a consequence, Gassendi, along with the rest of the academic staff, found himself without a teaching post. The change was effected with some measure of inconvenience according to one account: The Jesuit fathers just came into the town and took over the school. He [Gassendi] was obliged to complete his course ... in the St Ivan quarter [where] his friend M. Bergamon, at that time a Canon of Aix, gave him a large room in his own house for the purpose. 2 Thereafter, Gassendi had no further involvement in the scholastic system of education. Instead he devoted himself to what he termed "genuine" philosophy - of the kind that is cultivated by very few, in obscurity and silence.s His home base continued to be the Chapter of the Cathedral 2 PIERRE GASSENDI ofDigne, of which he had been a member Canon since his student days. He was finally appointed provost of the Cathedral in 1634, after ten years of litigation, and this was to be his official ecclesiastical position throughout the remainder of his life. Gassendi did not need much money: he lived a frugal, possibly even vegetarian4 life-style, and could always depend on the devoted support of wealthy friends. Consequently, he was able to devote himself to a life of study and writing that was relatively free of interruptions. In 1645 Gassendi reluctantly accepted the chair of mathematics at the College Royal upon the insistence of the patron of the College, the Cardinal of Lyons. Ill-health forced Gassendi to leave his chair and the city of Paris after the first academic year. Gassendi died, fortified by the last rites of the Church, in the year 1655, at the age of sixty-three. He was carried off by a pulmonary infection, rendered fatal by a total of fourteen bleedings. Gassendi was much acclaimed during his life, and his influence was considerable in the seventeenth century. Though his star faded thereafter, the town of Digne, with its 'boulevard Gassendi' and a statue of the philosopher in the main square, and the village of Champtercier, with its 'rue Gassendi', keep his memory alive to this day.5 Manuscripts and published works Gassendi's first publication was the Exercitationes paradoxicae adversus Aristoteleos Bk. 1 (1624).6 A second book of the same work was ready for publication in 1624, but was withheld from publication until it appeared posthumously in the Opera omnia which was published in 1658.7 After 1624 Gassendi's working life was predominantly devoted to the task of restoring the philosophy of Epicurus. He first mentioned his studies on Epicurean philosophy in his correspondence in a letter to his patron and friend Peiresc, written in 1626,8 and the fruits of these studies began to appear as manuscript writings on the philosophy of Epicurus a couple of years later,9 though none of these very early manuscripts seems to have been preserved. In 1629 Gassendi made a new translation of Book X of the Vitae philosophorum of Diogenes Laertius, and this translation was published with notes at the head of a work entitled Animadversiones in decimum librum Diogenis Laertii (1649).10 In 1631 Gassendi described in a letter to Peirescll a first version of his Epicurean philosophy which was already more than half finished. It contained an apologia for Epicurus, the De vita et moribus Epicuri, an expanded version of which was published in 1647,12 one book on Epicurean canonic (or logic), and more than two books of a projected four books of physica. The actual manuscripts of this 1631 version have not been preserved. Consequently Gassendi's first version of

Description:
Pierre Gassendi (1592-1655) lived in three civilizations in the span of one life-time: medieval ecclesiastic, Renaissance humanist and modern and he never cut himself loose from any of them. It is probably scientific; because he managed to be at home in all three that history has allocated to him a
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.