Philosophy, Sophistry, Antiphilosophy Also available from Bloomsbury Bloomsbury Studies in Continental Philosophy presents cutting- edge scholarship in the field of modern European thought. The wholly original arguments, perspectives and research findings in titles in this series make it an important and stimulating resource for students and academics from across the discipline. Breathing with Luce Irigaray, edited by Lenart Skof and Emily A. Holmes Deleuze and Art, Anne Sauvagnargues Deleuze and the Diagram: Aesthetic Threads in Visual Organization, Jakub Zdebik Derrida, Badiou and the Formal Imperative, Christopher Norris Desire in Ashes: Deconstruction, Psychoanalysis, Philosophy, edited by Simon Morgan Wortham and Chiara Alfano Egalitarian Moments: From Descartes to Rancière, Devin Zane Shaw Ernst Bloch and His Contemporaries, Ivan Boldyrev The Field of Theory: The Rise and Decline of Structuralism in France, Johannes Angermuller Gadamer’s Poetics: A Critique of Modern Aesthetics, John Arthos Heidegger, History and the Holocaust, Mahon O’Brien Heidegger and the Emergence of the Question of Being, Jesús Adrián Escudero Immanent Transcendence: Reconfiguring Materialism in Continental Philosophy, Patrice Haynes Merleau-Ponty’s Existential Phenomenology and the Realization of Philosophy, Bryan A. Smyth Nietzsche and Political Thought, edited by Keith Ansell-Pearson Nietzsche as a Scholar of Antiquity, Helmut Heit Philosophy, Sophistry, Antiphilosophy: Badiou’s Dispute with Lyotard, Matthew R. McLennan The Poetic Imagination in Heidegger and Schelling, Christopher Yates Post-Rationalism: Psychoanalysis, Epistemology, and Marxism in Post-War France, Tom Eyers Revisiting Normativity with Deleuze, edited by Rosi Braidotti and Patricia Pisters Towards the Critique of Violence: Walter Benjamin and Giorgio Agamben, Brendan Moran and Carlo Salzani Philosophy, Sophistry, Antiphilosophy Badiou’s Dispute with Lyotard Matthew R. McLennan Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square 1385 Broadway London New York WC1B 3DP NY 10018 UK USA www.bloomsbury.com BLOOMSBURY and the Diana logo are trademarks of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published 2015 © Matthew R. McLennan, 2015 Matthew R. McLennan has asserted his right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as Author of this work. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication can be accepted by Bloomsbury or the author. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN: HB: 978-1-47257-416-9 ePDF: 978-1-47257-418-3 ePub: 978-1-47257-417-6 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. Typeset by Fakenham Prepress Solutions, Fakenham, Norfolk NR21 8NN Contents Acknowledgements vi Introduction 1 Philosophy’s present 1 Old battle lines redrawn 4 A note on method and sources 5 1 The Thinking of Being 9 Lyotard’s thinking of being 11 Badiou’s thinking of being 29 2 Philosophy in its Relation to Being 49 Lyotard’s metaphilosophy 50 Badiou’s critique of The Differend 55 3 Demarcations: Philosophy, Sophistry, Antiphilosophy 67 Lyotard, sophiste? 70 Badiou, philosophe? 79 Lyotard, antiphilosphe? 87 4 Ethics and Politics 95 Philosophy as ethical and political vocation: Lyotard 98 Philosophy as ethical and political vocation: Badiou 104 A desire for the One 112 Conclusion 121 Notes 129 Bibliography 137 Index 145 Acknowledgements Any book is a team undertaking. Though any inaccuracies and omissions in the text are my own, the success of this project has depended at each step upon the gracious contributions of others. First and foremost I would like to thank my family for their love, support and encouragement. In particular I would like to thank Anna Seifried, Leo McLennan, Susan McLennan, Doreen Richmond, Audrey Lundy, Louise Legault, Pierre Legault, Louise Guay and Christopher Seifried. My gratitude also extends to my greatest philosophical teachers and mentors: Denis Dumas, Jeffrey Reid, Daniel Tanguay, Paul Forster, Brian Keenan, Diane Gall, Karim Dharamsi and George Fulford. I would also like to acknowledge the patience and good will of Bloomsbury editors Frankie Mace and Liza Thompson; the indispensable labours of my assistant Thérèse Barrett, who formatted the manuscript, created the index etc.; the inspiring enthusiasm and insights of Deniz Guvenc, with whom I read Being and Event; the support of my friends, as well as my wonderful colleagues at Saint Paul University; and lastly the contributions of my students, too many to name, who have inspired and challenged me. This work is published thanks to a grant by the Aid to Publication Program at Saint Paul University. I dedicate what follows, with boundless love, to Anna and Leo. Introduction Philosophy’s present Now, as ever, the question of philosophy’s definition is intimately bound to that of its survival. Without pre-deciding the issue, let us assume for now the kind of broad definition of philosophy proffered in undergraduate courses: philosophy is an activity of higher-order questioning, a search after truth. Thus construed, in the present conjuncture philosophy is threatened on two fronts. It is in fact subject to a double bind: if unable to plead its utility, philosophy is existentially threatened; pleading its utility, it is threatened no less. In the first place, philosophy as pure pursuit of truth is widely considered impractical or useless, and its claims to the intrinsic value of its labours tend to fall on deaf ears. But this is nothing new; Thales, traditionally considered to have been the first Western philosopher, was already subject to the ridicule of the Thracian maid when he fell in a well while gazing at the stars. More inter- esting is the fact that philosophy also and increasingly flirts with absorption into the very discourse of economic efficiency that undermines it. It finds a place at the table by pleading its utility, as training for the flexible, lateral thinking often said to be essential to economic and professional success. Philosophy may also be tapped for its therapeutic value, to the effect that the wisdom of the great philosophers alongside yoga and other techniques helps to cultivate the contentment, health and productivity of economic contributors. Moreover, the philosopher increasingly finds a role in practical ethics training, an explosive growth field by which she contributes not only to genuine ethical deliberation, but to the alibis of institutions and the individuals who populate them. This economic operationalization of philosophy is of course part of a global trend with much wider implications. Where the economic winners in a globalized post-Fordist system see flexibility, dynamism and opportunity, the vast majority of Earth’s labourers – adjunct philosophy faculty included – see precariousness, pressure, displacement and the permanent threat of obsoles- cence. Frequently, formally educated labourers must retrain midstream to stay 2 Philosophy, Sophistry, Antiphilosophy swimming, and the increasingly irrational demands on one’s time and one’s spatial locations push many to top up their credentials with night classes and online certification. Less and less frequently one locates the philosopher in the comfort of the ivory tower, pursuing pure research. It is increasingly common to find her on the adjunct treadmill, or at the intersection of diverse digital applied humanities courses in programmes targeting non-philosophical professionals. To this extent the philosopher becomes more than ever a facilitator who helps others – the real producers, the real drivers of the economy, it is said – to think differently; to look at alternative points of view; to cultivate intuition, under- stood as an openness to unthought-of solutions to practical impasses (and it goes without saying that such solutions are – at least on paper – to be ethically sensitive if not ethically sound). In sum, philosophy – where tolerated – is increasingly tapped for its productive potential rather than its millennia-old and, arguably, essential link to truths. In a general way, this poses with a new urgency the question of philosophy’s survival. But it also raises a more focused question: whether or not present conditions, by insisting on economic efficiency, encourage philosophy to distance itself from the standard, broad definition and even, perhaps, to slide into sophistry. Why sophistry? Compare Socrates to Protagoras. It is widely known that Socrates took no money for his philosophical craft, and that ultimately he martyred himself for the truth. Though arguably he was Socrates’s intel- lectual equal, the craft of Protagoras was linked in perhaps an essential way to economic and political survival and flourishing. In Plato’s Protagoras (1992a) – tendentious though we may assume it to be – the character Protagoras pulls shy of the anti-democratic conclusions to which he is pushed by Socrates’s rigorous questioning. He thereby demonstrates a political savvy placing him squarely and ably in the realm of doxa, mere opinion. He is no partisan of truth, but seeks above all to cause effects with language, and this with a view to human flourishing. Certainly, high-quality philosophical work in the Socratic/Platonic tradition of fidelity to truth continues to be produced internationally. But the existence of a hungry, desperate intellectual underclass – the army of adjunct faculty and the reserve army of underemployed and unemployed philosophy graduates seeking a toehold in the academy – favours the unmooring of philosophical technē from this fidelity. Since philosophy is tied to money through the university, it is at any rate fair to question whether or not this tends to corrupt it at the pedagogical level. Adjunct philosophical under-labourers are more competitive Introduction 3 to the extent that they can balance the demands of challenging, even titillating their millennial students, with the demands of telling the latter what they want to hear. To be safe, one usually assumes a basically liberal-democratic framework for discussion, in which thought experiments are brought out to show instinctively liberal-democratic students the minute inflections of applied liberal-democratic thought. One challenges, but only mildly; acts the benev- olent eccentric, the clown even, the fondly remembered philosophy professor, within this familiar space. On a cynical reading, one does so to gain favourable student evaluations by which to secure one’s incumbency, and with which to pad one’s portfolio in pursuit of increasingly rarer tenure-track positions. The razor-thin difference between Socrates and Protagoras has perhaps never been so important, since it is precisely by Protagorean political instinct and flattery, not through fidelity to truth, that the professional philosopher increasingly wins and keeps her place at the table. The question of philosophy’s survival, then, is tied up with its potential slide into sophistry, broadly construed as the politically astute practice of creating effects with language for a fee. But this poses anew the ancient question of whether the definitions of philosophy and sophistry here assumed are sound, and to what extent the line between the two can or should be drawn in any rigorous way. Indeed, not all thinkers in the ballpark of philosophical practice agree that sophistry should be quarantined from philosophy; Hegel notably assimilated sophistry to the history of philosophy and Heidegger, far from defending philosophy against sophistry, charged sophistry rather with provoking the fall of Greek thought into philosophy. In a more contemporary vein, Keith Crome has drawn attention to the crucial distinction between sophos, sophistēs and philosophos, roughly wisdom, sophistry and love of wisdom. His indispensable Lyotard and Greek Thought: Sophistry is a promising reflection on the possibility of a positive definition of sophistical intelligence, as distinct from both pre-Socratic sophos and Platonic–Aristotelian philosophos (Crome 2004). And not only the rich written corpus, but also the very career trajectory of Barbara Cassin, troubles any neat distinction between the craft of the philosopher and that of the sophist (Cassin 2014). The standard definition of philosophy is, in other words, question-begging according to some scholars on the grounds that it degrades, implicitly or otherwise, sophistical intelligence either by assimilating it to a stop on the road to philosophy, or to the status of a lesser rival. Is the story of sophistry parasitical upon that of philosophy? Is sophistry essentially autonomous? Or is the distinction between the two insuf- ficiently nuanced to begin with?
Description: