ebook img

Philosophy Outside-In: A Critique of Academic Reason PDF

257 Pages·2013·0.85 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Philosophy Outside-In: A Critique of Academic Reason

PhilosoPhy outside-in A Critique of ACAdemiC reAson Christopher Norris Philosophy Outside-In A Critique of Academic Reason Christopher Norris NNOORRRRIISS 99778800774488668844555577 PPRRIINNTT..iinndddd ii 1199//0077//22001133 0077::4411 © Christopher Norris, 2013 Edinburgh University Press Ltd 22 George Square, Edinburgh EH8 9LF www.euppublishing.com Typeset in 11/13 Sabon by Servis Filmsetting Ltd, Stockport, Cheshire, and printed and bound in Great Britain by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon CR0 4YY A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 978 0 7486 8455 7 (hardback) ISBN 978 0 7486 8456 4 (webready PDF) ISBN 978 0 7486 8457 1 (epub) The right of Christopher Norris to be identifi ed as author of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. NNOORRRRIISS 99778800774488668844555577 PPRRIINNTT..iinndddd iiii 1199//0077//22001133 0077::4411 Contents Introduction 1 1 How Not to Defeat Scepticism: Why Anti-realism Won’t Do the Trick 33 2 Great Philosophy: Discovery, Invention and the Uses of Error 61 3 Under Which King, Bezonian? Experimental Philosophy versus Thought Experiment 95 4 Outside the Box: On the ‘Extended Mind’ Hypothesis 124 5 Inaesthetics and Transitory Ontology: The Case of Political Song 150 6 Speculative Realism: An Interim Report 181 7 Provoking Philosophy: Shakespeare, Johnson, Wittgenstein, Derrida 205 Index 250 NNOORRRRIISS 99778800774488668844555577 PPRRIINNTT..iinndddd iiiiii 1199//0077//22001133 0077::4411 For Shelley Campbell NNOORRRRIISS 99778800774488668844555577 PPRRIINNTT..iinndddd iivv 1199//0077//22001133 0077::4411 Introduction I This book is aimed squarely against the kinds of ultra-specialist interest or ultra-professionalised narrowing of focus that have been such a prominent and – to my mind – such a damaging feature of much recent philosophical work. It seems to have come about largely through the idea that philosophy could best lay claim to academic respectability by pushing as far as possible in its emulation of the physical sciences, or determining to tackle only those well-defi ned technical problems that were sure to have some likewise well-defi ned technical answer. Such was Thomas Kuhn’s description of how ‘normal science’ typically carried on during those periods of relative calm between great ‘revolutionary’ shake-ups when it was business as normal for most working scientists since any paradigm- threatening obstacle – any discrepant data or empirical anomaly – could always be put down to some observational error, imperfection in the measur- ing apparatus or questionable choice of auxiliary hypotheses. I don’t at all wish to go along with the popular misreading of Kuhn which ignores his stress on the comparative rarity of full-scale scientifi c revolutions and fi nds little or nothing of interest in the notion of science as making progress through a placidly constructive engage- ment with manageable problems. Still I would venture to say that the discourse of present-day academic philosophy, at least in the analytic mainstream, is ‘normal’ to the point of intellectual stagnation and that this has chiefl y to do with the effect of an overly specialised professional culture and an over-concentration on issues that lend themselves to quasi-scientifi c formulation. So one central aim is to recommend a more Aristotelian approach to philosophy, or the idea that philosophers shouldn’t be so keen to advertise themselves as philosophers of or experts in some closely specifi ed subject domain. It may be replied, and justifi ably enough, that we nowadays know a lot more than Aristotle knew about all NNOORRRRIISS 99778800774488668844555577 PPRRIINNTT..iinndddd 11 1199//0077//22001133 0077::4411 2 Philosophy Outside-In those multifarious topics (the natural sciences included) that he took as falling within his investigative purview. Philosophers had much better pick their specialism with an eye to current trends and should defi nitely not – on pain of ignorance or amateurism – lay claim to anything remotely like an Aristotelian breadth of interests. On this view philosophy started out as a universal discourse of (purported) knowledge and truth but was thereafter subject to a long history of rifts, separations or independence-movements whereby its erstwhile component disciplines achieved intellectual maturity and, along with it, a new-found sense of autonomy. Probably the last one to go was psychology, at least to the extent that empirically minded psycholo- gists increasingly defi ned their discipline so as to exclude all reference to epistemology or philosophy of mind, while philosophers were just as keen to reciprocate by disavowing any taint of vulgar ‘psycholo- gism’.1 At any rate there is general agreement that the exponential growth of human knowledge across so many fi elds of enquiry has produced a situation in which, for better or worse, it is no longer pos- sible for anyone to claim expertise – or even a decent level of compe- tence – in more than one such specialist corner of one such specialist fi eld. This applies all the more in the case of philosophy since here, so the argument goes, there is a standing temptation for some prac- titioners (in particular philosophers of science) to issue large claims on the basis of a knowledge that is often simply not up to the mark in terms of the latest research. After all, if scientists themselves have learned to respect these disciplinary markers – even as regards areas of closely convergent interest such as molecular biology, organic chemistry and genetics – then surely philosophers will be best advised not to tread on such specialist turf. Or again, they should have the proper modesty to do so only under expert guidance and without any thought – heaven forefend! – of helping scientists to a better under- standing of conceptual problems on their own turf. As I have said, my book sets out to challenge that view of things and put the case for thinking of philosophy as a discipline of thought that can and should have useful things to say across a great range of topics by way of addressing and (on occasion) resolving just such problems. This connects with my second purpose which is basically to offer a sequence of essays in philosophy that are also essays on diverse topics which, for various mainly non-professional reasons, have come to exert a special interest or fascination. In fact the two purposes are really one and the same since it is a part of my argument here that the problem of over-specialisation, or the cult of misplaced NNOORRRRIISS 99778800774488668844555577 PPRRIINNTT..iinndddd 22 1199//0077//22001133 0077::4411 Introduction 3 expertise, has typically gone along with a depersonalised approach to philosophy where assured command of ‘the literature’ associated with some given topic has taken the place of anything resembling a per- sonal and deeply felt involvement with it. This is everywhere appar- ent in the choices of topic (narrowly prescribed), the tone of address (briskly effi cient), the presumed readership or audience (a small peer-group of like-minded specialists) and above all the manifest aim (to move things forward by just so much as to make one’s distinctive mark but not so much as to run the risk of offending one’s colleagues or the academic community at large). That tendency is reinforced by the periodic scourge of a research assessment exercise that encour- ages savvy types to focus their efforts on short-term, ‘manageable’ projects of a suitably conformist, professionally sanctioned and often intellectually unambitious kind. Moreover, it maintains an incentive structure whereby those who have most thoroughly internalised such habits of thought are then strongly placed, as subject panellists, to ensure its effective passing on to the rising generation. This is, to the say the least, a depressing scene and one that belies the constant stress on ‘research’ in an academic culture where any genuinely innovative work – any that raises a signifi cant challenge to communal norms of belief, not to mention established reputations – amounts to the equivalent of letting the side down (in this case one’s departmental colleagues) in a crucial qualifying match. Meanwhile the philosopher-specialists are apt to play themselves off the fi eld, as did the logical positivists and logical empiricists before them, by imitating science in a different fi eld of endeavour and thus inevita- bly lagging behind by any measure of substantive (as distinct from merely notional or intra-peer-group) contribution to knowledge. This is nowhere plainer to see than in the current exchange of hostili- ties – my topic in Chapter 3 – between ‘experimental philosophers’ who want to put things on a third-person empirical or observational basis and thus eschew all appeals to apodictic or fi rst-person epis- temic warrant and their opponents, the unreformed thought experi- mentalists, who cleave to precisely those traditional (and, they would say, philosophically indispensable) modes of enquiry. It also takes the form of that perceived imperative, among philosophers of an ana- lytic bent, to hitch their professional-academic wagons to the star of what counts (again in their own specialist community) as a properly scientifi c method. Just as the positivists mortgaged their enterprise to the formal sciences on the one hand and the physical sciences on the other – through their programmatic refusal to recognise as truth-apt NNOORRRRIISS 99778800774488668844555577 PPRRIINNTT..iinndddd 33 1199//0077//22001133 0077::4411 4 Philosophy Outside-In any statements other than logical tautologies or empirical observa- tions – so philosophers in the present-day ‘core’ disciplines strive to come up with results that would invoke either rational self-evidence or else some kind of natural-scientifi c warrant. Hence the unfortu- nate impression often given by exercises in, for example, philosophy of mind or philosophy of perception that these are somehow hoping to bootstrap their way by sheer analytical acuity to discoveries of the sort more typically (and aptly) claimed by disciplines like neuro- physiology or cognitive science. Hence also, more disturbingly, the tendency among analytic philosophers in various specialist fi elds to adopt a pseudo- or (somewhat less unkindly) a quasi-scientifi c rheto- ric in order to dismiss any line of argument that fails or on principle refuses to comply with currently prevailing philosophical modes of thought. This practice has been the stock-in-trade of analytic philosophers since the heyday of logical positivism when its exponents delighted in facile demolition-jobs on sundry ‘continental’ (i.e. typecast wild- and-woolly-minded) philosophers and when standards for this kind of knock-down rejoinder were, if anything, even less demanding than today. Still there is a need to muster some resistance when received ideas – or existing institutional mechanisms for preserving them – are so heavily weighted toward the maintenance of a profes- sional (rather than critical-philosophical) status quo that effectively excludes or massively discounts anything too much out of kilter with its own in-house norms of reputable discourse. The effect of this is to render philosophy peculiarly impotent or tongue-tied against the imputation of those, like Stephen Hawking in a recent polemic, who proclaim its demise or chronic obsolescence in the face of giddying scientifi c (or techno-scientifi c) progress. Hawking fl uttered the academic dovecotes by writing – and repeating to an eager company of interviewers and journalists – his opinion that philosophy as practised nowadays was a waste of time and philoso- phers a waste of space.2 More precisely, he wrote that philosophy was ‘dead’ since it hadn’t kept up with the latest developments in science, especially theoretical physics. In earlier times – Hawking conceded – philosophers not only tried to keep up but sometimes made real scientifi c contributions of their own. However, they were now, in so far as they had any infl uence at all, just an obstacle to progress through their endless going on about the same old issues of truth, knowledge, inductive warrant and so forth. Had they just paid a bit more attention to the scientifi c literature they would have NNOORRRRIISS 99778800774488668844555577 PPRRIINNTT..iinndddd 44 1199//0077//22001133 0077::4411 Introduction 5 gathered that these were no longer live issues for anyone remotely au fait with the latest thinking. Then their options would be either to shut up shop and cease the charade called ‘philosophy of science’ or else carry on and invite further ridicule for their head-in-sand attitude. Predictably enough, the journalists went off to fi nd themselves a media-friendly philosopher – not hard to do nowadays – who would argue the opposite case in a suitably vigorous way. On the whole the responses, or those that I came across, seemed overly anxious to strike a conciliatory note, or to grant Hawking’s thesis some measure of truth as judged by the standards of the natural-scientifi c community while tactfully dissenting with regard to philosophy and the human sciences. I think the case needs stating more fi rmly and, perhaps, less tactfully since otherwise it looks like a forced retreat to cover internal disarray. Besides, there is good reason to mount a much sturdier defence on principled grounds. These have to do with the scientists’ need to philosophise and their proneness to philosophise badly or commit certain avoidable errors if they don’t take at least some passing interest in what philosophers have to say. Hawking had probably been talking to the wrong philoso- phers, or picked up some wrong ideas about the kinds of discussion that currently go on in philosophy of science. His lofty dismissal of that whole enterprise as a useless, scientifi cally irrelevant pseudo- discipline fails to reckon with several important facts about the way that science has typically been practised since its early-modern (sev- enteenth-century) point of departure and, even more, in the wake of post-1900 developments such as quantum mechanics and space-time relativity. First is the fact that it has always included a large philosophical component, whether at the level of basic presuppositions concerning evidence, causality, theory-construction, valid inference, hypothesis- testing and so forth, or at the speculative stage where scientists ignore the guidance offered by well-informed philosophers only at risk of falling into various beguiling fallacies or fi ctions. Such were those ‘idols of the theatre’ that Bacon warned against in his New Organon of 1620, and such – albeit in a very different philosophic guise – those delusive ideas that, according to Kant, were apt to lead us astray from the path of secure investigation or truth-seeking enquiry. This was sure to happen, he warned, if the exercise of pure (speculative) reason concerning questions outside and beyond the empirical domain were mistakenly supposed to deliver the kind NNOORRRRIISS 99778800774488668844555577 PPRRIINNTT..iinndddd 55 1199//0077//22001133 0077::4411

Description:
Christopher Norris raises some basic questions about the way that analytic philosophy has been conducted over the past 25 years. In doing so, he offers an alternative to what he sees as an over-specialisation of a lot of recent academic work. Arguing that analytic philosophy has led to a narrowing o
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.