ebook img

Philosophy, Ethics, and Public Policy: An Introduction PDF

241 Pages·2015·1.145 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Philosophy, Ethics, and Public Policy: An Introduction

Philosophy, Ethics, and Public Policy What makes a policy work? What should policies attempt to do, and what ought they not do? These questions are at the heart of both policymaking and ethics. Philosophy,EthicsandPublicPolicy:AnIntroductionexaminesthesequestionsandmore. Andrew I. Cohen uses contemporary examples and controversies, mainly drawn from policy in a North American context, to illustrate important flashpoints in ethics and public policy, such as: (cid:2) public policy and globalization: sweatshops; medicine and the developing world; immigration (cid:2) marriage, family, and education: same-sex marriage; women and the family; education and intelligent design (cid:2) justifying and responding to state coercion: torture; reparations and restorative justice (cid:2) the ethics of the body and commodification: the human organ trade; factory farming of animals. Eachchapterillustrateshowethicsofferswaysofprioritizingsomepolicyalternatives and imagining new ones. Reflecting on various themes in globalization, markets, and privacy, the chapters are windows to enduring significant debates about what states may do to shape our behavior. Overall, the book will help readers understand how ethics can frame policymaking, while also suggesting that sometimes the best policy is no policy. Including annotated further reading, this is an excellent intro- duction to a fast-growing subject for students in philosophy, public policy, and related disciplines. Andrew I. Cohen is Director of the Jean Beer Blumenfeld Center for Ethics and Associate Professor of Philosophy at Georgia State University, USA. He is co-editor (with Christopher Heath Wellman) of Contemporary Debates in Applied Ethics (second edition, 2014). This page intentionally left blank Philosophy, Ethics, and Public Policy An Introduction Andrew I. Cohen Firstpublished 2015 byRoutledge 2ParkSquare, MiltonPark,Abingdon, OxonOX144RN andbyRoutledge 711ThirdAvenue,NewYork,NY10017 Routledge isanimprint oftheTaylor &FrancisGroup,aninformabusiness ©2015AndrewI.Cohen TherightofAndrewI.Cohen tobeidentified astheauthorofthiswork hasbeenassertedbyhiminaccordancewithsections77and 78ofthe Copyright,DesignsandPatents Act1988. Allrightsreserved.Nopartofthisbookmaybereprintedorreproducedor utilisedinanyform orbyanyelectronic,mechanical, orothermeans,now knownorhereafterinvented,including photocopyingand recording,orin anyinformationstorageorretrievalsystem, withoutpermissioninwriting fromthepublishers. Trademarknotice:Productorcorporatenames maybetrademarksor registered trademarks,andareusedonlyforidentification andexplanation withoutintenttoinfringe. British LibraryCataloguing inPublication Data Acataloguerecordfor thisbookisavailablefromtheBritishLibrary LibraryofCongress Cataloging inPublication Data Cohen,AndrewI. Philosophy,ethics,andpublicpolicy :anintroduction /AndrewI.Cohen. pagescm Includesbibliographical referencesandindex. 1.Policysciences--Moraland ethicalaspects.2.Socialpolicy--Moral andethical aspects.3.Economicpolicy--Moralandethical aspects. 4.Publicwelfare--Moral andethicalaspects. I.Title. H97.C6242015 172’.2--dc23 2014015473 ISBN:978-0-415-81416-4 (hbk) ISBN:978-0-415-81417-1 (pbk) ISBN:978-1-315-77201-1 (ebk) Typeset inGaramond byTaylor&FrancisBooks Contents Acknowledgements vi Introduction 1 1 Sweatshops 15 2 Pharmaceuticals and the developing world 37 3 Immigration 59 4 Same-sex marriage 81 5 Women and the family 104 6 Education and “intelligent design” 127 7 Torture 144 8 Reparations and restorative justice 161 9 Markets in human body parts and tissues 181 10 Factory farming of animals 202 11 Conclusion 224 Index 227 Acknowledgements For comments, conversation, or suggestions about various chapters, I thank Nigel Ashford, Jessica Berry, Bob Brecher, Andrew Jason Cohen, Maxine Eichner, Christie Hartley, Tim O’Keefe, Peter Lindsay, George Rainbolt, James Stacey Taylor, Peter Vallentyne, Kit Wellman, Larry Wilkerson, and Matt Zwolinski. I am grateful for the guidance and encouragement of my editors at Routledge, Tony Bruce and Adam Johnson. Several anonymous reviewers for Routledge were generous to offer extensive and constructive feedback. Many students were kind to comment on various chapters. Among them were Mason Arline, Cameron Boone, Maria Caruso, Chelsea Coleman, Harold Crowe, Alexander Davis, Darla Greaser, Matthew Hiltman, Callie Hollander, Jess Hullinger, Taylor Jones, Judith Kim, Ayesha Kirk, Alexis Koutrelakos, Ryan Le, Joshua McCormack, Caitlin McCoyd, Jamie Moon, Taylor Mumford, BaoChau Nguyen, Maryum Rabia, Evelyn Richardson, Joseph Shively, Leman Tatari, Kevin Thurston, Sarah Vogt, Andrew Weyant, and Anastasiya Yashchuk. My thanks to Carson Young for research assistance, and to Megan Hiatt for careful and patient copyediting. I am especially grateful to Elizabeth Dwyer for immensely helpful research assistance and copy- editing. In many ways, I can trace this book to Anthony Pennino, who inspired many people with his contagious passion for ideas. A special thanks for the love and support of J, S, & M: almost done! Introduction Discussions of public policy often consider how policies are made, how well they connect to intended goals, and how to evaluate their effects. A proper understanding of public policy would then require close attention to how the world works and to how things became the way they are. Who are the relevant actors? What institutions are in place to achieve various goals, and how well do they function? Why are institutions designed the way they are, and why do they work as well—or as poorly— as they do? Policy theorists and other social scientists devote their careers to investigating these and related issues. They sometimes propose various models for understanding the motives of policymakers, the content of the policies, and how to assess the consequences. Their work is complex and often controversial. Even the most highly regarded experts disagree about the causes of events and policies, what is currently happening, what might happen, and how best to proceed. Asifsuchcomplexityanduncertaintywerenotenough,policydiscussions sometimes fail to make clear what it should mean for a policy to “work” and how to understand which consequences count when considering what a policy does. Sometimes we lose sight of what policies may attempt to do or what they ought to do. Approaching policy disputes without a sense of the legitimate scope of political action may then miss a vital part of the discussion. This is not a question of effectiveness, though that is crucial to policy discussions. It is a particular type of normative issue: It is a matter of understanding the moral possibilities available to anyone considering competing policy proposals. A central function of ethical principles is to indicate what we may do alone or together through institutions. These principles can also tell us what we ought or ought not to do. Ethical principles guide our behavior, constraining or marshaling our conduct by offering special reasons that encourage or discourage (or, more forcefully, compel or forbid) our actions. Ethics is then that part of philosophy that considers, among other things, what makes for a good human life, what people owe to one 2 Philosophy, Ethics, and Public Policy another, and how human beings ought to behave. The institutions we create and inhabit crucially shape what sorts of lives we lead. Since ethics guides our actions, it offers a framework for evaluating the merits of rules, norms, or institutions. Ethics can indicate how to construct, change, or assesskeysocialandpoliticalinstitutions.Asapartofphilosophy,ethicsalso helps us to explore deeply held commitments and traditions. It urges us to expand our imaginations to consider morally enriching possibilities. It can then be a crucial part of the policy theorist’s toolkit for at least two reasons. First, people care about doing the right thing. Second, despite disagreements, ethics can be a way of framing policy disputes and possible institutional responses in a way that might achieve greater consensus. Policy theorists care about what ethics has to say. People who act withinandforpublicinstitutionscare.Ofcourse,ordinarycitizenscare,too. We all care because we want to be sure to support and do the right things. Often it is not entirely clear just what that right thing is. Some- times there are many possible right things to do. Even though there is sometimes uncertainty and disagreement about many fundamental ethical questions, ethics can still help us in part by making a bit clearer what is at stake in policy disputes. It can deepen our appreciation of what matters and why. This book uses philosophical ethics to lend clarity to policy disputes and to help us determine what constitutes good reasons in policymaking. Bringing ethics to policy might seem an uneasy marriage. After all, policy is concerned with getting things done. Ethics may just threaten to get in the way. That might be why some people would be suspicious of ethics. It seems to stand for the parent wagging a finger at us, admon- ishing us to stop doing something we like doing or to make us do something we really do not want to do. Perhaps this worry has something to it. Perhaps ethics sometimes is a chore. However, it might also help us to understand what our values are, what they could be and should be, and how to go about realizing them. It can even help us to understand together what our shared values are or should be. Ethics might then be an important part of understanding and shaping policy. What is public policy? Let us back up a second. Think for a moment about public policy. What is it? It is tempting to think that a public policy is anything a state does. But that definition is too broad. Think about why. States, through their governments, do many things that are either not public or not a policy. When a county government decides to lower the speed limit on a local road, it sends out a county employee in a county vehicle to install a new sign. When Chris, the county employee, removes the old sign and installs Introduction 3 the new one, Chris acts on behalf of the county government. Acting through Chris, the county does many things, including some that seem inconsequential. When Chris tightens the bolt on the new speed limit sign, that action is not a public policy. But tightening the bolt is some- thing the county does (through Chris). So, “public policy” cannot be anything a state does. When Chris the county employee installs the new road sign, plenty of public policies are still afoot. The lowering of the speed limit is a (new) policy. It was enacted through procedures that are set out in various public policies,such asthosegoverning openmeetings,public hearings, the election and appointment of officials, and rules defining what makes something a traffic regulation. Chris also drove a county vehicle as part of official county business to the place where the sign is posted. Chris had tools that belong to the county and used them to install the new sign. The existence of county vehicles and tools, and the existence of funds to purchase a new sign, are all licensed by various public policies. There are rules that describe how to raise the revenue to do such things. There are rules, norms, and institutions for holding, allocating, and dispersing such funds. There are also rules regarding the maintenance of county property. There are many other rules regarding how someone such as Chris can have a job working for the county and who can tell Chris what to do. Therefore, public policy can be defined as any institution, norm, or rule that the government of a state upholds to guide people’s behavior. States, through their governments, have many tools for guiding behavior, such as laws, regulations, various norms and procedures, budgets, regulatory directives, executive orders, and so forth. These are all ways of making people do things, or not do things, by providing or signaling reasons to act or not to act in certain ways. What makes a public policy public? What makes policies public and what makes them policies? Consider first the public part. Public policies are not private preferences or choices, even if they reflect, encourage, or celebrate private choices. Suppose Pat is a vegetarian. Even if Pat is very public about this dietary choice, it is not a public policy. Pat is not the government. Even if Pat were the president or prime minister, Pat’s vegetarianism would not be a public policy. Being a vegetarian is something Pat does as a private citizen. If, however, Pat were the head of state and somehow issued and enforced an order that everyone must become a vegetarian, then vegetarianism would be a public policy. The choices and policies of privately held companies are not public policies. Coca Cola’s policy to keep Coke’s formula a trade secret is not a

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.