ebook img

Philosophy and the 'Dazzling Ideal' of Science PDF

348 Pages·2019·3.241 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Philosophy and the 'Dazzling Ideal' of Science

Philosophy and the ‘Dazzling Ideal’ of Science Graham McFee Philosophy and the ‘Dazzling Ideal’ of Science Graham McFee Philosophy and the ‘Dazzling Ideal’ of Science Graham McFee University of California Fullerton Riverside, CA, USA ISBN 978-3-030-21674-0 ISBN 978-3-030-21675-7 (eBook) https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-21675-7 © The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive licence to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are solely and exclusively licensed by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. Cover illustration: Panther Media GmbH / Alamy Stock Photo This Palgrave Macmillan imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Switzerland AG The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland P reface This monograph begins from the assumption that philosophy is possible and explores the kinds of creatures we must be, if that is to be true. Yet why might the possibility of philosophy be doubted? A pervasive image, or ideal, drawn from science provides the primary reason discussed here, an image generating scientism, whereby the successes of science seem to leave little or no room for philosophy. And, as Thomas Nagel (2012, p. 7) puts it, “almost everyone in our secular culture has been browbeaten into regarding the reductive research program as sacrosanct, on the ground that anything else would not be science”—just the kind of reductive con- ception against which this text presents a sustained argument. But more important, in practice, is our endorsement of the power of reason. For opposition to scientism—to the over-valuing of models of knowledge and understanding from science—can sometimes generate, or seem to gener- ate, a rejection of science; and then, potentially, a rejection of the concept of truth; or of the distinction between truth and falsehood. Such rejec- tions, too, must be set aside. Rather, the power of a certain image of sci- ence must be recognized, an image based on the achievements of the natural sciences in both explaining the world, and offering opportunities for prediction and control. Yet that image becomes pernicious if taken as an ideal of explanatory achievement, one stressing both the inexorability characteristic of causal explanation within science and its completeness: nothing sublunary escapes that explanatory power. The worry throughout is that, “dazzled by the ideal” as Wittgenstein (PI §100) put it, our bedaz- zlement obscures, or leaves obscure, our conception of the ‘rights and v vi PREFACE responsibilities’, the powers and capacities, of philosophy: perhaps even rendering philosophy impossible. This project grew out of another, to sketch an account of the philoso- phy of action consonant with a plausible philosophical aesthetics of dance (McFee, 2018). There, the worry coalesces around attempts to explain the artworks of dance in terms, roughly, of the neurobiology of dancers. But some issues raised are pervasive. Hence, there, elaborating explanatory frameworks for persons and their powers and capacities required consoli- dating that project in the light of my granting that “[e]rror and supersti- tion have causes just as much as correct cognition” (Frege, [1918] 1984, p. 351). Thus, my interest in some of those frameworks in their own right was piqued—or rekindled—since they often involve various scientistic conceptions that, with Frege, I was keen to oppose: the view that persons were nothing but causal structures (therefore lacking agency, and hence responsibility); that minds were nothing but a kind of complicated com- puter; that imagining kinds of robot or android was an informative way to think about minds; that our psychologies were fixed by our biology. As a result, this book intersects with that one, like the circles of a Venn dia- gram: indeed, there is some overlap in content. So this monograph has, as it were, two agenda items: first, to defend the claims of philosophy against those seeking to minimize either its pos- sibility or its importance by contrasting it with natural science; where such a defence of the claims of philosophy (especially its claims to truth, at least in principle) also permits granting to natural science (properly under- stood) its truth-generating power. Then, second, to show what this defence says about persons (as agents). In this light, some readers may think it odd that what might strike them as a key question remains unaddressed; indeed, unconsidered. For this text contains little or nothing about how the materialism I endorse here (on which we persons are wholly composed from matter, in the sense that there is no ‘mind-stuff’) ever generates the kinds of purposes and values that I repeatedly refer to throughout this text: how can such materialism lead to the kinds of teleology I find for people without involving some radically different kind of ‘thing’ or substance? This question clearly besets both Thomas Nagel (2012, pp. 4–5), who usually appears as a hero of this text’s theses, and Michael Ruse (2017, pp. 48–49), who might have played a similar role—had I discovered his book On Purpose (2017) before I had basically finished writing this one. PREFACE vii For me, though, that whole line of enquiry is ill-formed: it represents exactly the tendency that, as we will see, Ludwig Wittgenstein (OC §471) warned us against as aiming to “go further back” beyond the appropriate starting point. A parallel to bring out the problem, perhaps, concerns the suggestion that the world rests on the back of a huge tortoise: anyone who accepts this as a legitimate attempt to answer a legitimate question must then surely ask on what the tortoise rests. Obviously, if such an initial foundation can legitimately be requested, or the kind of question it repre- sents granted to be well formed, no answer will be possible—any ‘level’ chosen simply allows that the question be repeated at a lower ‘level’. And then those who regard the initial question as legitimate cannot really urge that it is tortoises all the way down! Ruse (2017, p. 182) offers another appropriate comparison: the cookbook recipe that begins, “first take ingredient X…”, does not typically consider practical questions about where such ingredients come from; addressing that issue—when it is an issue—is not the business of cookery. Similarly, beginning (as here: see below) from the possibility of philosophy requires having drawn a line that determines the structure of our investigation. We cannot then enquire how to explain the mere possibility of the prerequisites for what is already presupposed, much less hunt for some yet deeper origination, without independent reasons being provided. With respect to the text’s ‘pitch’, I must apologize both to those friends who advised that it should be more technical and scholarly (“Put in more on Kant, Sellars, and philosophy of science!”), and to those who urged that I remove scholarly detail (“None of that stuff on Sellars, Kant, and philosophy of science; and less quotation!”). In trying to strike a balance, I hope this version retains enough scholarly material to make the connec- tion to the rest of philosophy, without leaving too many “hostages to fortune” in the form of unsupported claims requiring either expansion or omission. Certainly, in some places, there is perhaps more quotation than is consistent with the demands of style. But it is important to acknowledge the degree of dependence of this text on—as well as the degree of its response to—the ideas of others. Quotations and extensive cross- referencing remain efforts to acknowledge such concerns, and some of the repetition should illustrate the recurrence of similar issues, and their treatments. The admiring mention René Descartes receives intermittently through- out reflects a commitment to scientific truth going back at least to my first entering university as a physics student. For Descartes was, of course, viii PREFACE appropriately concerned with “the method of rightly conducting one’s reason and seeking the truth in the sciences” (the subtitle of his Discourse on the Method: CSM I, p. 111). But it is also partly an homage to my late friend Gordon Baker, whose work (with Katherine Morris) revolutionized the interpretation of Descartes in philosophy—or should have. Also, Descartes’ recognition of the value of, and need for, education in learning to distin- guish truth from falsity is salutary here: A good man is not required to have read every book or diligently master everything taught in the Schools. It would, indeed, be a kind of defect in his education if he spent too much time on book learning … But he came into the world in ignorance, and since the knowledge which he had as a child was based solely on the weak foundation of the senses and the authority of his teachers, it is virtually inevitable that his imagination should be filled with enumerable false thoughts before reason could guide his conduct. So later on he needs to have a great natural talent, or else the instruction of a wise teacher, in order to rid himself of the bad doctrines that have filled his mind. (CSM II, p. 400) Given that one’s teachers and colleagues are so important, it becomes crucial not to surround oneself with either the self-deceived (say, the cen- tral figure in an alt-right ‘news’ website) or with sycophants. In the cur- rent climate in the USA, this requirement seems given an additional urgency by those who would deny the most obvious facts either about the world (“fake news”) or about science—say, by denying evolution or cli- mate change. Here, while avoiding denying truth (of kinds the natural sciences can generate), one must also avoid over-rating science. It is therefore important to reinforce our commitment to science as a source of truth; and to insist that our criticism here is directed at an image of science, one extracted by others from the real achievements of genuine scientists. Before discussing the truth of such theses, they must be charac- terized accurately, especially as regards their scope. And many scientists have been alive to the possibility of misperception (or its probability, since its regular occurrence is a thesis of this text): thus, Freud ([1905] 1966, p. 267) comments tartly on the impact of popularization on his own works (see Chap. 9, Sect. 2), where: … qualifications and exact particularisation are of little use with the general public; there is very little room in the memory of the multitude; it retains only the bare gist of any thesis and fabricates an extreme version which is easy to remember. PREFACE ix Freud’s complaint is that something inexact is taken from his theoretically precise accounts of human beings, with that inexactness following from how his works are presented to a general audience. For, of course, such a process might inflate any claim. In this vein, Darwin ([1859] 1993, p. 637) wrote that, “great is the power of steady misrepresentation”: if one’s views are standardly misrepresented, the general public may take for one’s claims something very different from them. Now, Darwin ([1859] 1993, p. 637) optimistically concludes that “the history of science shows that fortunately this power does not long endure”. Let us hope he was right about this, as about so much; but it is hard to match his optimism, as I write this, living in the USA under President Donald J. Trump. Riverside, CA Graham McFee April, 2019 BiBliograPhy Darwin, C. ([1859] 1968/1993). Origin of Species (1st edn., J. W. Burrow, Ed.). Harmondsworth: Penguin; (5th edn.). New York: Random House (Modern Library Edition). Descartes, R. (1984). The Philosophical Writings of Descartes (3 Vols.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [cited as “CSM I” and “CSM II”]. Frege, G. ([1918] 1984). Thoughts. In Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic and Philosophy (pp. 351–372). Oxford: Blackwell. Freud, S. ([1905] 1966). On Psychotherapy. In The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud (Vol. 7, pp. 257–270). London: Vintage Classics. McFee, G. (2018). Dance and the Philosophy of Action. Alton, Hants: Dance Books. Nagel, T. (2012). Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature Is Almost Certainly False. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ruse, M. (2017). On Purpose. Princeton, NJ: University of Princeton Press. Wittgenstein, L. (1953/2001/2009). Philosophical Investigations (G.  E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell, [50th Anniversary (3rd edn.); 4th Rev. edn., P. M. S. Hacker & J. Schulte, Eds.]. [cited as “PI”]. Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On Certainty (D. Paul & G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell. [cited as “OC”]. a cknowledgements As usual, this text overall reflects the impact of discussions with my friends; especially with the late Gordon Baker, with Katherine Morris, and with Terry Diffey. Many themes here were discussed with my late friend, Jeff Mason. Leon Culbertson kindly read closely the whole text, offering detailed comments on specific themes, and his contribution also includes many long discussions on these and related topics over the years. Similarly, some were discussed in detail, and profitably, with Nick McAdoo. Finally, my wife Myrene not only read the text, offering comments on substance and on proof-reading matters, but also supported me emotionally during these two years of its composition, during which writing and revisions were fitted-in around teaching and marking, radiation treatments, chemo- therapy, and autologous stem cell transplant. Permissions The following chapters contain material from, or are revised versions of, other works for which I am the copyright-holder. The original locations are as follows, and their publishers are hereby thanked for permission to include this material: • Chapter 2—a full redraft, with extensive additions and omissions, of my Dance and the Philosophy of Action (Dance Books, 2018) pp. 58–81; • Chapter 3—a full redraft, with extensive additions and omissions, of my Dance and the Philosophy of Action (Dance Books, 2018) pp. 27–46; xi

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.