PHILOSOPHY AND THE BELIEF IN A LIFE AFTER DEATH LIBRARY OF PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION General Editor: John Hick, Fellow of the Institute for Advanced Study in the Humanities, University of Birmingham This series of books explores contemporary religious understandings of humanity and the universe. The books contribute to various aspects of the continuing dialogues between religion and philosophy, between scepticism and faith, and between the different religions and ideologies. The authors represent a correspondingly wide range of viewpoints. Some of the books in the series are written for the general educated public and others for a more specialised philosophical or theological readership. Selected titles ISSUES IN CONTEMPORARY JUDAISM Dan Cohn-Sherbok ISLAM IN A WORLD OF DIVERSE FAITHS (editor) MORAL SCEPTICISM Clement Do re GOD, SUFFERING AND SOLIPSISM PROBLEMS IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF Harold Hewitt RELIGION (editor) J. Kellenberger INTER-RELIGIOUS MODELS AND CRITERIA Carl Olson THE THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY OE ELIADE Alan G. Padgett GOD, ETERNH Y AND THE NATURE OF TIME Joseph Runzo IS GOD REAL? (editor) WORLD VIEWS AND PERCEIVING GOD Arvind Sharma A HINDU PERSPECTIVE ON HE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION Norman Solomon JUDAISM AND WORLD RELIGION Melville Y. Stewart THE GREATER-GOOD DEFENCE Jonathan Sutton THE RELIGIOUS IT IILOSOPHY OF VLADIMIR SOLOVYOV Roger Teichmann ABSTRACT ENTITIES Donald Wiebe BEYOND LEGITIMATION Richard Worsley HUMAN FREEDOM AND THE LOGIC OF EVIL Philosophy and the Belief in a Life After Death R. W. K. Paterson Formerly Senior Lecturer in Philosophy University of Hull w First published in Great Britain 1995 by MACMILLAN PRESS LTD Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire RG21 6XS and London Companies and representatives throughout the world A catalogue record tor this book is available from the British Library. ISBN 0 333 61633-2 First published in the United States of America 1995 by & ST. MARTIN'S PRESS, INC., Scholarly and Reference Division, 175 Fifth Avenue, New York, N.Y. 10010 ISBN 0-312-12838-X Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Paterson, R. W. K. (Ronald William Keith) Philosophy and the belief in a life after death / R. W. K. Paterson p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-312-12838-X 1. Future life. 2. Future life—Controversial literature. 3. Immortality (Philosophy) 4. Immortality (Philosophy)- -Controversial literature. I. Title. BL535.347 1995 129—dc20 95-23638 CIP ©R.W.K. Paterson 1995 All rights reserved. No reproduction, copy or transmission of this publication may be made without written permission. No paragraph of this publication may be reproduced, copied or transmitted save with written permission or in accordance with the provisions of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, or under the terms of any licence permitting limited copying issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency, 90 Tottenham Court Road, London WIP 9HE. Any person who does any unauthorised act in relation to this publication may be liable to criminal prosecution and civil claims for damages. 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 04 03 02 01 00 99 98 97 96 95 Printed and bound in Great Britain by Antony Rowe Ltd, Chippenham, Wiltshire Contents 1 Philosophy, Belief and Disbelief 1 2 Problems of Post-Mortem Identity 21 3 The Mental and the Physical 59 4 General Arguments for the Immortality of the Soul 103 5 The Evidence from Psychical Research 131 6 The Concept of an Afterlife 191 Notes and References 213 Index 221 v 1 Philosophy, Belief and Disbelief By engaging in philosophy we are agreeing to put our beliefs to the test of logic. We are demonstrating our willingness to subject the concepts which figure in our beliefs to logical analysis, to an intensive scanning for hidden inconsistencies, obscurities, or ambiguities; and we are accepting that the grounds on which we hold our beliefs need to be logically evaluated, fallacies in reasoning detected, concealed premises identified, and different forms of relevance established. Actually, we have no option. An incoherent belief is not a belief at all, but merely a jumble of words or perhaps of muddled impressions and feelings. And although we may indeed hold beliefs for which we have no good grounds, we must then expose ourselves to the wholly justified charge of childishly sheltering in private fantasies. Some of the issues tackled by philosophers are purely philosophical in character. Examples of these are problems about universals, the justification of induction, the ontological argu ment for the existence of a God, or about the general notion of identity. Such problems centre entirely on the possible logical relations between concepts and involve only arguments of a purely formal character, with no admixture of any empirical content whatsoever. But there are many other problems, in which philosophers have a major interest, which are intellec tually composite. That is, in addition to strictly philosophical elements, these kinds of problem also involve reference to various types of claimed empirical fact. Hence a complete solution to these problems would require answers to both the 1 2 Philosophy and the Belief in a Life after Death logical and the factual questions of which they are composed. The distinctive contribution of philosophy in these cases is thus absolutely necessary, but (perhaps subject to a qualification which we shall later note) is by no means sufficient. Examples of such intellectually composite problems are the free will/ determinism controversy, the nature of the relation between mind and brain, and the religious problem of evil. Another example is the problem of whether or not human personality survives bodily death. Admittedly there are a few celebrated arguments for the immortality of the soul which are of a purely philosophical kind because they depend entirely on drawing out the logical implications of concepts like 'unity', 'destruction', and so on. These will be examined in due course. Mainly, however, the present work will be concerned, not with the concept of immortality or endless life, but with the more limited concept of a life after death. No doubt many people believe that, if they were to survive bodily death, this would be a sure sign that they were immortal, perhaps on the not completely unreasonable principle that 'il n'y a que le premier pas qui coute'. However (to say the least) this is a question which must not be begged. At any rate if a person did not survive his bodily death for an initial finite time, it seems clear that he could not survive his death for an endless time.1 Because survival of death is clearly a necessary condition of personal immortality, this alone would justify us in examining the many philosophical objections to the former concept, since if these objections have adequate force they will necessarily rule out the latter concept. It need hardly be added that, if it should turn out that there were no adequate objections to the concept of a life after death, this philosophical conclusion would in no way establish that there is a life after death. Nevertheless such an outcome would be of the first importance. For if it could be shown that a life after death was not a priori impossible, we should then be mandated to collect, sift, and weigh up the many varieties of evidence which putatively bear upon this question, in the hope that empirical inquiry would progressively enable us to make a reasoned assessment of the relative probability or improbability of survival. Now because philosophy (like pure mathematics) is an a priori inquiry, its conclusions, if correct, are held to be necessarily Philosophy, Belief and Disbelief 3 correct. What these conclusions assert is the only possible state of affairs, and all alternative states of affairs are logically impos sible. And if something is logically impossible, it cannot be. Because empirical beliefs, however improbable, may be true, it is always a meaningful exercise to investigate the chances of their being true. Thus there might be a golden mountain in the jungles of Brazil, but there cannot be a spherical golden cube anywhere on earth, and it is quite useless for explorers to hunt for one. As a consequence we can, I think, detect a certain professional tendency among philosophers who have addressed the intellec tually composite types of problem I have mentioned. They have tended to seek answers to the philosophical elements in the overall problem which, consisting of necessary truths, will decisively rule out various classes of solution to the whole problem. For example, many philosophers have argued that the notion of a 'free acf is logically incoherent, or that interactionist dualism is literally inconceivable because mental processes, endowed with no physical energy, could not possibly be thought of as producing changes in a physical brain. If these findings were valid, they would absolutely rule out all beliefs in free will or in interactionist dualism as a theory of mind and body, thus demonstrating any empirical research into these hypotheses to be a complete waste of time. Such an outcome, though seemingly negative, would be an immense achievement, serving to focus research efforts on truly worthwhile problems.2 Of course philosophers might alternatively conclude that some a priori arguments for free will, or immortality, or the existence of a Creator, were formally valid. In that case, whatever the apparent evidence against these beliefs, it would be a necessary truth that we were free, or immortal, or the creatures of a God, and all empirical research into the opposite hypotheses would have been shown to be useless and wasteful. Finally, philosophical analysis might show that free will, mind- brain interaction, or the existence of a Creator, are logically coherent notions but that there are no sound arguments which can either demonstrate or refute them a priori. Unless they produced further grounds to show that such great problems are intrinsically incapable of solution and that we must therefore remain forever agnostic on these issues (a possibility we shall later consider), the
Description: