PHILOSOPHY AND SIMULATION By the same author: Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy A New Philosophy of Society Also available from Continuum: Being and Event, Alain Badiou Conditions, Alain Badiou Infi nite Thought, Alain Badiou Logics of Worlds, Alain Badiou Theoretical Writings, Alain Badiou Theory of the Subject, Alain Badiou Cinema I, Gilles Deleuze Cinema II, Gilles Deleuze Dialogues II, Gilles Deleuze Difference and Repetition, Gilles Deleuze The Fold, Gilles Deleuze Foucault, Gilles Deleuze Francis Bacon, Gilles Deleuze Kant’s Critical Philosophy, Gilles Deleuze Logic of Sense, Gilles Deleuze Nietzsche and Philosophy, Gilles Deleuze Proust and Signs, Gilles Deleuze Ant-Oedipus, Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari A Thousand Plateaues, Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari Seeing the Invisible, Michel Henry Future Christ, François Laruelle Philosophies of Difference, François Laruelle Essay on Transcendental Philosophy, Salomon Maimon After Finitude, Quentin Meillassoux Time for Revolution, Antonio Negri Politics of Aesthetics, Jacques Rancière Of Habit, Félix Ravaisson The Five Senses, Michel Serres Art and Fear, Paul Virilio Negative Horizon, Paul Virilio PHILOSOPHY AND SIMULATION The Emergence of Synthetic Reason Manuel DeLanda Continuum International Publishing Group The Tower Building 80 Maiden Lane 11 York Road Suite 704 London SE1 7NX New York, NY 10038 www.continuumbooks.com © Manuel DeLanda, 2011 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN: HB: 978-1-4411-7028-6 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data De Landa, Manuel. Philosophy and simulation: the emergence of synthetic reason / Manuel Delanda. p. cm. ISBN: 978-1-4411-7028-6 1. Emergence (Philosophy) 2. Science–Philosophy. I. Title. Q175.32.E44D4 2010 003–dc22 2010020325 Typeset by Newgen Imaging Systems Pvt Ltd, Chennai, India Printed and bound in India by Replika Press Pvt Ltd Contents Introduction Emergence in History 1 Chapter One The Storm in the Computer 7 Chapter Two Cellular Automata and Patterns of Flow 22 Chapter Three Artifi cial Chemistries and the Prebiotic Soup 36 Chapter Four Genetic Algorithms and the Prebiotic Soup 48 Chapter Five Genetic Algorithms and Ancient Organisms 65 Chapter Six Neural Nets and Insect Intelligence 80 Chapter Seven Neural Nets and Mammalian Memory 94 Chapter Eight Multiagents and Primate Strategies 111 Chapter Nine Multiagents and Stone Age Economics 128 v CONTENTS Chapter Ten Multiagents and Primitive Language 146 Chapter Eleven Multiagents and Archaic States 166 Appendix Links to Assemblage Theory 184 Notes 204 Index 223 vi INTRODUCTION Emergence in History The origin of the modern concept of emergence can be traced to the middle of the nineteenth century when realist philosophers fi rst began pondering the deep dissimilarities between causality in the fi elds of physics and chemistry. The classical example of causality in physics is a collision between two molecules or other rigid objects. Even in the case of several colliding molecules the overall effect is a simple addition. If, for example, one molecule is hit by a second one in one direction and by a third one in a different direction the com- posite effect will be the same as the sum of the two separate effects: the fi rst molecule will end up in the same fi nal position if the other two hit it simultaneously or if one collision happens before the other. In short, in these causal interactions there are no surprises, nothing is produced over and above what is already there. But when two molecules interact chemically an entirely new entity may emerge, as when hydrogen and oxygen interact to form water. Water has proper- ties that are not possessed by its component parts: oxygen and hydro- gen are gases at room temperature while water is liquid. And water has capacities distinct from those of its parts: adding oxygen or hydro- gen to a fi re fuels it while adding water extinguishes it.1 The fact that novel properties and capacities emerge from a causal interaction was believed to have important philosophical implications for the nature of scientifi c explanation. In particular, the absence of novelty in physical interactions meant that explaining their effects could be reduced to deduction from general principles or laws. Because deductive logic simply transfers truth from general sentences 1 PHILOSOPHY AND SIMULATION to particular ones without adding anything new it seemed like an ideal way of modeling the explanation of situations like those involv- ing rigid collisions. But the synthesis of water does produce some- thing new, not new in the absolute sense of something that has never existed before but only in the relative sense that something emerges that was not in the interacting entities acting as causes. This led some philosophers to the erroneous conclusion that emergent effects could not be explained, or what amounts to the same thing, that an effect is emergent only for as long as a law from which it can be deduced has not yet been found.2 This line of thought went on to become a full fl edged philosophy in the early twentieth century, a philosophy based on the idea that emergence was intrinsically unexplainable. This fi rst wave of “emergentist” philosophers were not mystical thinkers but quite the opposite: they wanted to use the concept of emergence to eliminate from biology mystifying entities like a “life force” or the “élan vital.” But their position toward explanation gave their views an inevitable mystical tone: emergent properties, they said, must be accepted with an attitude of intellectual resignation, that is, they must be treated as brute facts toward which the only honest stance is one of natural piety.3 Expressions like these were bound to make the concept of emer- gence suspect to future generations of philosophers. It was only the passage of time and the fact that mathematical laws like those of classical physics were not found in chemistry or biology—or for that matter, in the more historical fi elds of physics, like geology or clima- tology—that would rescue the concept from intellectual oblivion. Without simple laws acting as self-evident truths (axioms) from which all causal effects could be deduced as theorems the axiomatic dream eventually withered away. Today a scientifi c explanation is identifi ed not with some logical operation but with the more creative endeavor of elucidating the mechanisms that produce a given effect. The early emergentists dismissed this idea because they could not imagine any- thing more complex than a linear clockwork mechanism. But there are many other physical mechanisms that are nonlinear. Even in the realm of human technology we have a plurality of exemplars to guide our imagination: steam engines, thermostats, transistors. And outside technology the diversity is even greater as illustrated by all the differ- ent mechanisms that have been discovered in chemistry and biology. 2 EMERGENCE IN HISTORY Armed with a richer concept of mechanism the emergent properties of a whole can now be explained as an effect of the causal interactions between its component parts. A large portion of this book will be dedicated to describe the wide variety of mechanisms of emergence that have been elucidated in the decades since the original emergentists fi rst wrote. Thus, what is different today from the early twentieth century views is the epistemological status of emergence: it does not have to be accepted as a brute fact but can be explained without fearing that it will be explained away. What has remained the same is the ontological status of emergence: it still refers to something that is objectively irreducible. But what kinds of entities display this ontological irreduc- ibility? The original examples of irreducible wholes were entities like “Life,” “Mind,” or even “Deity.” But these entities cannot be consid- ered legitimate inhabitants of objective reality because they are noth- ing but reifi ed generalities. And even if one does not have a problem with an ontological commitment to entities like these it is hard to see how we could specify mechanisms of emergence for life or mind in general, as opposed to accounting for the emergent properties and capacities of concrete wholes like a metabolic circuit or an assembly of neurons. The only problem with focusing on concrete wholes is that this would seem to make philosophers redundant since they do not play any role in the elucidation of the series of events that produce emergent effects. This fear of redundancy may explain the attach- ment of philosophers to vague entities as a way of carving out a niche for themselves in this enterprise. But realist philosophers need not fear irrelevance because they have plenty of work creating an onto- logy free of reifi ed generalities within which the concept of emer- gence can be correctly deployed. What kinds of concrete emergent wholes can we legitimately believe in? Wholes the identity of which is determined historically by the processes that initiated and sustain the interactions between their parts. The historically contingent identity of these wholes is defi ned by their emergent properties, capacities, and tendencies. Let’s illus- trate the distinction between properties and capacities with a simple example. A kitchen knife may be either sharp or not, sharpness being an actual property of the knife. We can identify this property with the shape of the cross section of the knife’s blade: if this cross section has 3