ebook img

Philosophical Provocations: 55 Short Essays PDF

340 Pages·2017·1.24 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Philosophical Provocations: 55 Short Essays

Philosophical Provocations 55 Short Essays Colin McGinn The MIT Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England © 2017 Massachusetts Institute of Technology All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form by any electronic or mechanical means (including photocopying, recording, or information storage and retrieval) without permission in writing from the publisher. This book was set in ITC Stone Sans Std and ITC Stone Serif Std by Toppan Best-set Premedia Limited. Printed and bound in the United States of America. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Names: McGinn, Colin, 1950-author. Title: Philosophical provocations : 55 short essays / Colin McGinn. Description: Cambridge, MA : MIT Press, 2017. | Includes bibliographical references and index. Identifiers: LCCN 2016046174 | ISBN 9780262036191 (hardcover : alk. paper) eISBN 9780262340083 Subjects: LCSH: Philosophy. Classification: LCC BD41 .M34 2017 | DDC 192--dc23 LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2016046174 ePub Version 1.0 Table of Contents Title page Copyright page Preface I Mind II Language III Knowledge IV Metaphysics V Biology VI Ethics VII Religion Index Preface The essays collected here follow a particular pattern and style. They aim to be pithy, with no padding or extraneous citation. They each address a specific philosophical issue and try to make progress with it as efficiently as possible. There is little discussion of particular authors or “the literature”; my aim is to get down to the issues immediately and state a position. I avoid excessive qualification or self-protection, leaving it to the reader to fill in gaps. Thus: short, sharp, and breezy. The style is intended to contrast with the way academic philosophy tends to be written these days: long, leaden, citation-heavy, and painful to read. This means that the book can be read by someone not expert in the fields covered, though I would not deny that some of the essays are quite demanding—but not I think unnecessarily so. There is room in academic writing for the style I avoid, but there is something to be gained by the direct and unencumbered style I adopt here (I have written my fair share of the other kind of stuff). A great many topics are covered in the book, and I make no attempt to link them.1 Each occurred to me independently of the others, though there are thematic continuities. They often challenge orthodoxy in ways that might seem shocking and put forward views that may be condemned as eccentric. There is nothing safe about these essays—though I do help myself to a dose of common sense when needed. I am self-consciously trying to find new ways to think about old problems. Maybe not all the suggestions will stand the test of further reflection, but I hope they stir people to think in fresh ways—or at least to feel provoked at my audacity. My ideal over the period of writing these essays (2014 to 2016) was to resolve a serious philosophical problem in no more than a page. Needless to say, this ideal was just that—not a realistic prospect. Still, it was a useful guiding principle, because it forced me to extremes of economy in formulation and argument. I ruthlessly excluded all preamble and qualification, knowing that “sophisticated” readers will pounce on certain passages; I tried to get right to the point and state my view with maximum clarity. Admittedly, I did occasionally employ arguments, in the standard style, but I tried to keep them short and sweet. No doubt I’ve sometimes lapsed into prolixity and professionalism, old sweet. No doubt I’ve sometimes lapsed into prolixity and professionalism, old habits being what they are, but I regard that as a fault, not a virtue. If an essay does not raise professional eyebrows at some point, I count it a failure. Colin McGinn Note 1. In fact the essays published here constitute a selection from a larger number of essays written over the same period (one hundred and thirty in all). I hope to publish the remaining essays in a later volume. I Mind The Mystery of the Unconscious Introduction For some time now consciousness has been at the center of discussions of the mind–body problem. We might say that today the mind–body problem is the consciousness–brain problem. But it was not always so. Thomas Nagel felt it necessary to begin his classic 1974 paper “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” with these words: “Consciousness is what makes the mind–body problem really intractable. Perhaps that is why current discussions of the problem give it little attention or get it obviously wrong.” I introduced my 1989 paper “Can We Solve the Mind–Body Problem?” as follows: “The specific problem I want to discuss concerns consciousness, the hard nut of the mind–body problem. How is it possible for conscious states to depend upon brain states? How can Technicolor phenomenology arise from soggy grey matter?” David Chalmers has spoken of consciousness as the “hard problem,” distinguishing it from (relatively) “easy” problems of the mind, and finding in it a uniquely difficult phenomenon to bring within a materialist perspective. And many others have felt that the problem of consciousness is particularly and distinctively deep or profound—as if without it the mind would be far less intractable, perhaps not intractable at all. Consciousness is now thought to be the great enigma of the mind. I think we have all been wrong. I say this not because I believe that consciousness is tractable after all; it is rather that I think it is not uniquely intractable. To be more specific, I think that much the same problems that afflict consciousness also afflict unconsciousness: unconscious mental states are as problematic as conscious mental states, and for essentially the same reasons. The emphasis on consciousness is therefore misplaced, even though the authors cited have been right to discern a deep problem about consciousness. Consciousness is indeed a mystery, but so is the unconscious (hence my title for this essay). The plan of the essay is as follows. First I will explain how the standard arguments against materialism for conscious states carry over to unconscious states. Next I will offer a diagnosis of why it is harder to see this in the case of the unconscious than it is for the conscious. Then I will describe the intimate relations between the conscious mind and the unconscious mind, so that we can see that it is extremely unlikely that the former should be deeply intractable while the latter is relatively plain sailing. It is the mind in its entirety that poses an intractably hard problem for materialism, not just the conscious part of it. Antimaterialist Arguments It is not difficult to see how the standard arguments transpose to the unconscious, once the question has been formulated. I will therefore go over this ground quickly, assuming that the reader is familiar with the arguments in question. I am going to use what I hope is an uncontroversial example of an unconscious mental state—not the Freudian or Jungian unconscious or anything exotic like that. I came to the position to be outlined here in the course of defending innate ideas in the Cartesian sense: these ideas had to be unconscious, given that babies are not born consciously thinking about mathematics or sensible qualities or anything else Descartes took to be innate (rightly, in my view). But I don’t want to enter this controversial territory now; instead I shall discuss a straightforward case of experiential memory. Suppose that yesterday I saw a red bird in my garden and noted its fine plumage. Then I went back to work and didn’t think any more about it. Today I (consciously) remember seeing the bird and wonder if I will see it again: I recall seeing its brilliant red plumage, just as I experienced it yesterday. I have a visual memory of my perceptual experience. Between these two times, evidently, I stored the experience of the red bird in my memory, wherein it resided unconsciously. That is, I was not conscious of the memory between the two times; like most of my memories it existed in an unconscious form, though it was not difficult to bring it to consciousness. The unconscious memory was sandwiched between an act of conscious perception and an act of conscious remembering: but it was not itself conscious. It existed in the unconscious part of my mind. For brevity, call this memory “the memory of red.” Now compare the memory of red with a perceptual experience of red, and consider the standard arguments. The standard arguments against viewing the experience of red as a brain state (or a functional state) are as follows: Nagel’s subjectivity argument, Jackson’s knowledge argument, Kripke’s modal argument, Putnam’s multiple realization argument, Chalmers’s zombie argument, Brentano-inspired arguments from intentionality, Block’s inversion and absence arguments (against functionalism), and the brute primitive intuition that experiences cannot in their very nature be identified with brain states. Each of these arguments purports to show that the experience of red cannot be reduced to a physical state. Thus, Nagel contends, the experience is subjective while the brain is objective: the man born blind cannot know what a subjective experience of red is like, having never had such an experience, though he may grasp the objective nature of the brain states that correlate with that experience. We cannot know what it is subjectively like to be a bat, though we can know the objective physiology of a bat’s brain. Jackson’s Mary could know all about color vision physiology of a bat’s brain. Jackson’s Mary could know all about color vision and not know what it is to see something as red—as is shown by her learning something new when she emerges from her black-and-white room and sees something red for the first time. We can imagine a possible world, Kripke tells us, in which someone has an experience of red but not the usual brain correlate found in the actual world, and equally we can imagine the usual brain correlate associated with a different color experience or no experience at all. Hence there cannot be an identity between the two, since identity is a necessary relation. Putnam argues that the experience of red may have a different physical realization in Martian brains, so it cannot be identified with the brain state humans happen to use to implement it. Chalmers argues that there is no a priori entailment between physical descriptions of the subject and descriptions of her experiences, so that zombies are logically possible, thus refuting the logical sufficiency of brains for conscious minds. Brentano observes that the experience of red has an intentional directedness to the color red, which cannot be found in the physical world. Block conjectures that we can conceive of cases in which an organism has the same functional characterization as an organism experiencing red and yet that organism experiences green (“inverted qualia”) or experiences no color at all (“absent qualia”). And many people instinctively feel that it is just massively implausible to suppose that an experience of red is nothing but a brain state of neurons firing, given how different the two things seem. The question is whether the same arguments can be applied to the memory of red. Suppose a bat uses its sense of echolocation and has the corresponding perceptual experience. Then it stores that experience in memory, perhaps for later use. The memory exists in an unconscious form, but it is an experiential memory. Can we grasp the nature of that memory? Not if we can’t grasp the nature of a bat’s experience, since that is what it is a memory of. To grasp it we would need to occupy the bat’s subjective point of view, as Nagel puts it; but we don’t, so we can’t. We can know all about a bat’s brain, including the memory centers, but that will not tell us the nature of a bat’s memory, since that memory incorporates the bat’s alien sense of echolocation. Yet the memory is unconscious. Note that I did not say that we are unable to grasp what it is like to have that memory, since (being unconscious) there is nothing it is like. What we fail to grasp—because we have no conception of it—is the nature or essence of the memory. The case is just like a blind person trying to grasp what a memory of having a red experience is. He does not grasp that concept, any more than he grasps the concept of a conscious perceptual experience of red. Of course, a memory of a conscious perceptual experience is precisely that—a memory whose content refers to a state of consciousness. But it doesn’t follow from this that it is itself an instance of consciousness. So the memory is problematic

Description:
Pithy, direct, and bold: essays that propose new ways to think about old problems, spanning a range of philosophical topics.InPhilosophical Provocations, Colin McGinn offers a series of short, sharp essays that take on philosophical problems ranging from the concept of mind to paradox, altruism, and
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.