ebook img

Philosophical Historicism and the Betrayal of First Philosophy PDF

241 Pages·1990·31.32 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Philosophical Historicism and the Betrayal of First Philosophy

LibraryofCongressCataloging-in-PublicationData Page,Carl, 1957- Philosophicalhistoricismandthe betrayaloffirst philosophy/ CarlPage. p. em. Includes bibliographical referencesandindex. ISBN0-271-01330-3(alk. paper) 1. Philosophy. 2. Historicism. 3. Methodology. I.Title. B61.P34 1995 101--dc20 93-41574 eIP Copyright©1995,ThePennsylvaniaStateUniversity All rights reserved PrintedintheUnited StatesofAmerica PublishedbyThePennsylvaniaStateUniversityPress, UniversityPark, PA 16802·1003 ItisthepolicyofThePennsylvaniaStateUniversityPresstouseacid-freepaperfor thefirst printingofallclothboundbooks.Publicationsonuncoatedstocksatisfythe minimum requirements ofAmerican National Standardfor Information Sciences- PermanenceofPaperfor PrintedLibraryMaterials, ANSI Z39.48-1984. What is thefirst andlastthingthataphilosopherdemands 0/himself? To overcomehis agein himself, to becometimeless. - Friedrich Nietzsche PREFACE Overemphasizing the historical character of human existence ends by betrayingphilosophy, for the necessary timeliness ofdeeds all too easily overshadowsthefragile possibilityofuntimelyspeeches. Dogmaticasser tion ofreason's transcendencebetraysphilosophynoless, foritencourages, first, a disconnection of insight from the caring it takes to cultivate virtueand, subsequently,anallbutirreparablesplitbetweenthetandem moments oftheory and practice, endeavor and insight. In this matter of reason's self-knowledge, the collective mood of contemporary philosophy is swinging toward the former, historicist extre~. What is defined and explicated in this book as philosophical historicism claims that the activity of human reason is totally and necessarilydetermined bythefinite actuality ofhistorical circumstance, that despite the intelligibility ofuniversal, primary, and synoptic cogni- xii Preface tive ideals, in reality human reason is necessarily dominated by the purely contingent. I do not oppose this view with the supposition that history is irrelevant to philosophy or that philosophy does not need to take history seriously. I contend, rather, that contemporary philosophy is becomingso infatuatedwith historicalcontingency thatitthreatensto make nonsense ofthe natural desire to see things whole and clear. With all the good intentions of saving reason from dogmatic pretension and self-delusion, philosophical historicism nonetheless betrays theoretical eros by its insistence that thedesire toget to the bottomofthings, to the bottom of anything, cannot in principle be consummated and must therefore be wholly retrained. Getting to the bottom of things, seeing things whole and clear-these aspirations helpdefine the spirit of"First Philosophy," Aristotle's descriptive designation for the knowledge of things through their ultimate causes and principles, the knowledge whose perfection but not intelligibility philosophical historicism denies. For the sake of paying due respect to the historical situatedness of reason's exercise, historicism thus alienates us from the given form of our yearning to understand. Iam convincedthat this betrayalistoo high apricetopay, despitethe value ofhistoricism's central lesson that the soul, and more particularly the theorizing mind, may not reasonably be indifferent to its historical embodiment. My aim in this book is to show how the meaning of historicity may be preserved without forsaking the natural integrity of theoretical desire and without, therefore, abandoningeitherthe spirit or the tradition ofFirst Philosophy. The readershouldbe warned that IoffernosystematicdefenseofFirst Philosophy's alternative to philosophical historicism. It appears here chiefly as the shadow progenitor against which the latter defines itself. Myimmanentcriticismsaredirectedat thecurrenthistoricistorthodoxy in its own terms. They are grounded in historicism's own explicit aims and self-understanding as well as in tacit constraints common to all modes ofphilosophizing. I have spoken ofthose common constraints in terms ofboth metaphysical and logical (or account-giving) responsibility, phrases whose meanings are explained and whose relevance is justified in the appropriate places. My own commitmentto First Philosophy may, from time to time, distract the historicistically inclined reader, but that commitment alone cannot be held to invalidate arguments I have made every efforttokeepcommensurablewith historicism's ownphilosophical spirit, stated and implied. Preface xiii What follows is a theoretical critique. It addresses philosophical historicism as a teaching about the true situation ofhuman reason. But historicism's growing philosophical popularity represents as much a practical commitment as it does a theoretical one, namely the moral conviction that we have, at last, found the right way to discipline philosophy's hubristic tendency to place itselfabove politics, above the city, above its fellow citizens. From this zeal comes all the contemporary emphasison solidarity. The topicisdeepandcomplex,made particularly difficult by the natural passion for justice. Importance notwithstanding, I havedeliberatelyavoidedalldiscussion ofthis wider, politicallyramify ingcontext. It requires a bookin its own right. Instead I have chosento focus on philosophical historicism's purely doctrinal weaknesses as an interpretation ofhuman reason. The priorityisjustifiedsince, ifhistori cism is theoretically inadequate in the ways I maintain, it cannot possi bly beasuitablebasisfor practical responsibility to the politicaldomain. ABBREVIATIONS BOR Richard Bernstein, BeyondObjectivism andRelativism:Science, Hermeneutics, andPraxis (Philadelphia: University ofPennsyl vania Press, 1983). BT Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, tr. John M'acquarrie and Edward Robinson (Ne·w York: Harper and Row, 1962 [1926]). CIS Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, andSolidarity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989). CP RichardRorty, ConsequencesofPragmatism:Essays, 1972-1980 (Minneapolis: University ofMinnesota Press, 1982). CR Karl Popper, Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth ofScien tificKnowledge, 2d ed. (New York: Basic Books, 1965). xviii Abbreviations "CWM" "CorrespondenceConcerning WahrheitundMethode: Leo Strauss and Hans-Georg Gadamer," Independent Journal ofPhilosophy 2(1978): 5-12. EH Friedrich Meinecke, Die Entstehung des Historismus (Munich: Oldenbourg, 1959 [1936]), translated by J. E. Anderson as Historism (London: Herderand Herder, 1972). Page references are to the English translation. EHO Richard Rorty, Essays on Heidegger and Others: Philosophical Papers, Volume 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991). EN Sections referto G. W. F. Hegel, Enzyklopadiederphilosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1969 [1830]), withEnglishtranslationsfromHegel'sLogic, tr.William Wallace (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975) and Hegel's Philoso phyofMind, tr. A. V. Miller (Oxford: ClarendonPress, 1971). "GS" Hans-Georg Gadamer, "Gadamer on Strauss: An Interview," Interpretation 12 (1984): 1-13. HCE Martin Heidegger, Hegel's Concept ofExperience (New York: Harperand Row, 1970). HK Robert D'Amico,Historicism andKnowledge (New York: Rout ledge, Chapman, and Hall, 1989). "HM" Karl Mannheim, "Historicism," in Essays on the Sociology of Knowledge, ed. Paul Kecskemeti (New York: Oxford University Press, 1952). HP G. W. F. Hegel,Hegel's Introduction totheLecturesontheHistory ofPhilosophy, tr. I M. KnoxandA. V. Miller(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985). IRH Alexandre Kojeve, Introduction totheReadingofHegel: Lectures onthePhenomenologyofSpirit, tr. JamesH. NicholsJr. (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1969). IU Karl Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia, tr. Louis Wirth and Edward Shils (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1936). "KH" Ernst Troeltsch, "Die Krisis des Historismus," Die Neue Rundschau 33 (1922): 572-90. Abbreviations xix KPM MartinHeidegger,KantandtheProblemofMetaphysics, 4thed. (en!.), tr. Richard Taft (Bloomington: University of Indiana Press, 1990[1929]). ORT Richard Rorty, Objectivism, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophi calPapers, Volume 1 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991). OSE Karl Popper, The Open SocietyandIts Enemies, 2vols., 5th ed. (London:'Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1966). "PCR" Jack Meiland, "On the Paradox of Cognitive Relativism," Metaphilosophy 11 (1980): 115-26. PHM Hans-Georg Gadamer, Philosophical Hermeneutics, tr. David Linge (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1976). PMN Richard Rorty, PhilosophyandtheMirrorofNature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979). PPH DavidCarr, PhenomenologyandtheProblemofHistory:A Study ofEdmundHusserl's Transcendental Phenomenology (Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 1974). PR G. W. F. Hegel, Hegel's Philosophy ofRight, tr. T. M. Knox (New York: Oxford University Press, 1952). PS G. W. F. Hegel,Hegel's PhenomenologyofSpirit, tr. A. V. Miller (New York: Oxford University Press, 1977). PVH Karl Popper, The Poverty ofHistoricism, 3d ed. (New York: Harper and Row, 1964). PWF Joseph Margolis, Pragmatism Without Foundations: Recon ciling Realism and Relativism (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1986). RF Erich Streissler, ed., Roads to Freedom (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1969). SL G. W. F. Hegel, Hegel's Science of Logic, tr. A. V. Miller (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanitie's Press, 1969). SWU Joseph Margolis, Science Without Unity: ReconcilingtheHuman andNatural Sciences (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1987). xx Abbreviations TM Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d rev. ed., transla tion revised by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (New York: Crossroad, 1989). TWR Joseph Margolis, Texts Without Referents: Reconciling Science andNarrative (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1989). WH G. W. F. Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of World History: Introduction-Reason in History, tr. H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975). INTRODUCTION HISTORICISM: THE NEW COMMONPLACE Since the middle of the nineteenth century Historismus has been a familiar item in the lexicon ofGerman scholarship. In contrast, only in the latter half of the twentieth century has the kindred (though not equivalent) term historicism appeared as a category in the working vocabulary ofEnglish-speaking academics. Despite this apparently late start on their part, it is now fair to say that historicism is a well-worn, if less than well-understood, pieceoftaxonomic coin. Withinthe lastdecade itsincreasedcirculationintheconversationsofphilosophersinparticular has been especiallymarked. Thesignificance ofthis recent philosophical appropriation ofhistoricism is the subject ofthe present book. Although the upsurge in philosophical use is recent, it has not taken long for the currency to become debased. As a label, historicism may now be found attributed to almost any philosophicalpositionthat makes some approving reference to history, regardless of the specific form in which it should happen to do so. When used in this indefinite way, historicism becomes equally applicable to the views ofHegel and to those of Richard Rorty.Nonetheless, the widespread willingness to

Description:
The recent emergence, among philosophers, of the view that the activity of human reason in all its possible modes must also be historicized, including the activity of philosophizing itself, may be found in writers as diverse as Hans-Georg Gadamer, Richard Rorty, Michel Foucault, and Alasdair MacInty
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.