ebook img

Philosophers in Exile: The Correspondence of Alfred Schutz and Aron Gurwitsch, 1939-1959 PDF

379 Pages·1989·29.98 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Philosophers in Exile: The Correspondence of Alfred Schutz and Aron Gurwitsch, 1939-1959

Philosophers in Exile Studies in Phenomenology and Existential Philosophy GENERAL EDITOR JAMES M. EDIE CONSULTING EDITORS _David Carr William L. McBride EdwardS. Casey J. N. Mohanty Stanley Cavell Maurice Natanson Roderick M. Chisholm Frederick Olafson Hubert L. Dreyfus Paul Ricoeur William Earle John Sallis J. N. Findlay George Schrader Dagfinn F0llesdal Calvin 0. Schrag Marjorie Grene Robert Sokolowski Dieter Henrich Herbert Spiegelberg Don Ihde Charles Taylor Emmanuel Levinas Samuel J. Todes Alphonso Lingis Bruce W. Wilshire Philosophers in Exile of The Correspondence Alfred Schutz and Aron Gurwitsch) 1939-1959 Edited by Richard Grathoff Translated by J. Claude Evans Foreword by Maurice Natanson INDIANA UNIVERSITY PRESS <• BLOOMINGTON AND INDIANAPOLIS © 1989 by Indiana University Press The German edition of .this correspondence was published as Alfred Schutz, Aron Gurwitsch: Briefwechsel, 1939-1959, © 1985 Wilhelm Fink Verlag All rights reserved No part of this book may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying and recording, or by any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. The Association of American University Presses' Resolution on Permissions constitutes the only exception to this prohibition. Manufactured in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Schutz, Alfred, 1899-1959. [Alfred Schutz, Aron Gurwitsch. English] Philosophers in exile : the correspondence of Alfred Schutz and Aron Gurwitsch, 1939-1959 I edited by Richard Grathoff ; translated by J. Claude Evans ; foreword by Maurice Natanson. p. cm.-(Studies in phenomenology and existential philosophy) Translation of: Alfred Schutz, Aron Gurwitsch. Bibliography: p. Includes index. ISBN 0-253-32627-3 1. Schutz, Alfred, 1899-195~orrespondence. 2. Gurwitsch, Aron Correspondence. 3. Husserl, Edmund, 1859-1938.4. Phenomenology. 5. Philosophers-United States-Biography. I. Gurwitsch, Aron. II. Grathoff, Richard. Ill. Title. IV. Series. B945.S354A4 1989 193-dc19 [B] 88-46037 CIP 1 2 3 4 5 93 92 91 90 89 CONTENTS vii FOREWORD BY MAURICE NATANSON xiii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS xv INTRODUCTION BY RICHARD GRATHOFF 1 2 The Riders of the Apocalypse The Strange and the Stranger (August 5, 1939-0ctober 9, 1941) (November 8, 1941-July 16, 1944) 2 42 3 4 Context as a Problem of Order Oh, Holy Mannheim! (June 11, 1945-July 17, 1949) (January 26, 1950-March 16, 1951) 73 113 5 6 The Field of Consciousness From the Theory of Action to the (June 24, 1951-March 17, 1952) Theory of Science 134 (April4, 1952-September 5, 1953) 171 7 8 Concepts of the Life-World lnve$tigation of the Life-World vs. (October 2, 1953-January 1, 1956) Transcendental Constitutional 215 Analysis (February 22, 1956-April25, 1957) 248 VI CONTENTS 9 Parting (June 6, 1957-May 16, 1959) 267 321 AFTERWORD BY J. CLAUDE EVANS 327 BIBLIOGRAPHY 334 INDEX Foreword MAURICE NATANSON This book presents the remarkable correspondence between Alfred Schutz and Aron Gurwitsch, both European Jews born at the tum of the century, both philosophers deeply influenced by Edmund Husserl, both exiled more than once (the two first met in Paris in the mid-thirties, at the suggestion ofHusserl), both ultimately seminal figures in the establishment of phenomenology in the Uni.ted States. The dates of the Schutz Gurwitsch correspondence-1939-1959-provide a focus for but not an explanation of the scope of this exchange. The correspondents were strongly entrenched in the history of their times, but their intellectual and cultural roots were defined humanistically by the classical gymnasia that they attended, by the Continental universities at which they studied, by their immersion in philosophy (Edmund Husserl's phenomenology, in particular), and by their compre hension of the grounding of the social as well as the natural sciences in a logic whose terms relate profoundly to the world ofd aily life-the ambience of human experience as it is lived in immediacy by all of us. But more than being intellectual products of a certain European tradition, Schutz and Gurwitsch were historically located at a savage juncture of world events: they were Europeans compelled to leave their cultural homes to become exiles not only from their lands but also from the European tradition itself-a tradition which, far from ridding itself of what it deemed undesirable "elements," splintered into the shards of irratio nalism, genocide, and historical disgrace. A central part of what makes this correspon dence remarkable is that Schutz and Gurwitsch understood the chaos of the events of their times and yet in the midst of their own personal losses comprehended the loss of that European humanism which wounded itself beyond recovery. Tliese refugees did not escape the Europe that made them possible; that Europe no longer existed. What remained was the world that Schutz and Gurwitsch constituted in their corre spondence and personal meetings-perhaps above all through the philosophical papers which they wrote, sent to each other faithfully, and discussed with the deepest critical care and philosophical urgency-as well as in the no less important personal concern that they showed for each other, for their families, and for their friends. Paradoxically, theirs was not a private but a universal world. What, then, makes this correspondence "remarkable"? To the reasonable question: What, essentially, is the Schutz-Gurwitsch correspon dence about? no simple response is possible. It is correct to say that the entire correspon dence is, au fond, a reflection of the relationship between two extraordinary individuals that the correspondence is essentially a human document. But being correct is not always enough. In this instance, it must also be said that though the correspondence is a mirror of a transcendent friendship and of a world shared by exceptional relations and friends, it is at the same time a philosophical venture by Schutz and Gurwitsch to work out their ideas through and with each other, to determine whether their fundamentally resonant but more than occasionally divergent views could achieve clarity and resolution. The image used by the correspondents is that of a "tunnel" that they are digging from different ends and which may or may not ''meet." The tunnel is being dug "together''; whether the diggers finally "meet" is of vital importance to them; but the image has its Vll Vlll FOREWORD limits. The phenomenological theme of the correspondence is the practice of philosophy: the nature of that practice, its implications for the practitioners, and the transformation of both self and world in the course of what might be called a genuine philosophical existence. In a way, the correspondence is about itself, for both partners are self consciously and overtly aware of the activity of philosophy which is engendered by their reports to each other, their exchanges, their arguments, and their reliance on each other for the expert understanding and unqualified honesty in theoretical as well as practical matters which are so rarely found in combination. From a different vantage point, one may say with confidence that, depending on where one samples these letters, a variety of themes provides legitimate (if partial) an swers to the question of what this correspondence is about. A strong part of the book is concerned with problems of what has come to be known as the subject of "refugee scholars" in the United States in the 1930s and 1940s. What is different about the Schutz-Gurwitsch exchange when viewed under the rubric of "refugee scholars" is the internal-or better, interior--character of a sustained discussion between such scholars themselves rather than by their observers in the literature devoted to what is now a "research" subject. Ironically, perhaps, Max Weber's notion of the actor's interpretation of the meaning of his own act-the "subjective interpretation of meaning"-so well known to Schutz and Gurwitsch, became particularized in the actuality of the lives of the correspondents. They were refugee scholars who not only knew their sociological place ment but who were also concerned with its philosophical implications. We have a dou bling effect: refugee scholars who were professionally concerned with some of the most fundamental aspects of the situation of which they are prime examples. But the meaning of the "refugee scholar'' would be lost in its deepest aspect with regard to Schutz and Gurwitsch if it were not recognized that for them the "refugee" problem had its own history, its own "sedimentation of meaning" (to use Husserl's language), for the "prob lem" is closer to Socrates than to Hider. The force of events in 1939 cannot be wished away by invoking the ancient history of the "refugee"; neither can the historical scene of 1939 be comprehended fully without access to what lies so anciendy behind it-not in a causal but in a humanistic sense. What identifies the essence of humanism in this context is the recognition that "history'' is primarily not what happened but what keeps happen ing. The last historical event looks back to its origins not out of nostalgia but by virtue of an integral philosophic effort which human beings may make to grasp the meaning they bear in a "preinterpreted" world. Still another feature of the correspondence is the intensive discussion of phenomenology-of a considerable number of phenomenological problems, to be more precise-which for the two men was a fire fed by the exchange of their writings. This discussion will be precious to the reader acquainted with philosophy in general and phenomenology in particular; approached in the wrong way, it may very well lead the reader who is not especially interested in phenomenology to conclude that whatever the problems at issue are, they are intended only for readers ofHusserl. What possible change in approach can alter this circumstance? What would an approach "in the right way" mean? What is at issue in the discussions of phenomenological problems in the correspon dence between Schutz and Gurwitsch is not textual in character; that is, neither correspon dent is primarily concerned with what Husserl meant by a particular point made in a particular passage. The task of the correspondence is not the ¢:plication or the exegesis of the writings of Edmund Husserl. · Early in the exchange, Schutz (in his letter of August 19, 1939) wrote: "As you know, for me the question concerning the 'correct,' namely orthodox, Husserl interpre tation is always secondary to the question concerning the true states of affairs." Of course, the proper understanding of Husserl and his texts was of major importance to the friends. Of much greater significance was what Husserl sought: an immensely thorough-philosophically stubborn-description, analysis, and comprehension of "the MAURICE NATANSON ix true states of affairs," the "things themselves." Still, more than a rigorous discussion of phenomenological problems, the correspondence shows itself to be a sophisticated but, in a powerful way, raw specimen of philosophizing of the most searching order regard ing the meaning of perception, action, intersubjectivity, objectivity, the ego, conscious ness, knowledge of the Other, the proper station of social science, and the limits of symbol, relevance, and even "limit" itself in "lived experience": the place of transcen dence (to paraphrase one ofWolfgang Kohler's titles) in a world of finitude. To say that a considerable part of the correspondence consists in the discussion of philosophical problems is, once again, the ''wrong'' way of reading this book. The state ment is true but banal. Rather, the discussion of philosophical problems by Schutz and Gurwitsch is perhaps the most incisive exchange of views in the course of a twenty-year correspondence in recent philosophy. If the number of members of the class of outstand ing philosophers who have sustained a twenty-year intellectual correspondence is small, it is all the more important testimony to the unusual character of this book and all the more clarification of what "remarkable" means here: The correspondence is alive with the swift current of deeply consonant and yet strongly independent and sometimes antagonistic views; these pages present philosophical thinking in process and in the presence of another mind at once profoundly congenial and committed only to the truth that philoso phers have traditionally heralded but seldom lived by. Yet the philosophical correspondence cannot be taken at surface value. It is extremely telling that the discussion between Schutz and Gurwitsch deepens our understanding of phenomenology in quite specific ways. For example, take the different interpretations and emphases that the two men gave to Husserl's conceptions of the noetic and the noematic polarities of intentional experience; that is, the way in which consciousness builds up the unities of meaning and those unities taken as accomplished, as presented to the perceiver-in phenomenological terms, "as meant." Schutz has been called a "noetic'' phenomenologist and Gurwitsch has been termed a "noematic" phenomenologist. What the correspondence reveals, however, is that both sides of the perceptual process, the "subjective" and the "objective" sides, are issues which are very far from being phenome nologically settled; to the contrary, they remained for the two writers "problem children" a5 well as "problem adults" in the house of phenomenology. For both parties to the discussion, it was not enough to think through or to argue out what Husserl meant by these fundamental concepts; the still deeper demand they made of each other was the achievement of full clarity about the philosophical grounds of phenomenological issues. In this correspondence, phenomenology is philosophy in process, not philosophy be come but philosophy becoming. A still further way of taking the "right approach" to the distinctively phenomenologi cal discussions in this book is to recognize as soon as possible what is revealed as the years of the correspondence pass: that the philosophizing together of Schutz and Gurwitsch is unthinkable without Husserl but is distorted if their letters are regarded as restricted either to Husserl, to Bussed's phenomenology, or to matters which are somehow all derivative from Husserlian thought. The two thinkers were thoroughly acquainted with the history of philosophy from Sextus Empiricus (Carneades) to work done in recent times. Both men shared a profound interest in the thought of Leibniz; both men could justifiably take for granted a detailed grasp of Plato and Aristotle; both men had read their Kant; and perhaps most important of all, they had unequal backgrounds in certain . domains: Gurwitsch had devoted himself deeply to the study of Gestalt psychology; Schutz was saturated with the literature of the social sciences. Gurwitsch taught mathe matics and physics; Schutz had an impressive knowledge of musicology as well as of the philosophical problems relating to music. For work on .the foundations of arithmetic, one turns to Gurwitsch; for an essay such as "Mozart and the Philosophers," one turns to Schutz. Their differences are as important as their similarities in coming to terms with what

Description:
This book presents the remarkable correspondence between Alfred Schutz and Aron Gurwitsch, emigre philosophers influenced by Edmund Husserl, who fled Europe on the eve of World War II and ultimately became seminal figures in the establishment of phenomenology in the United States. Their deep and las
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.