ebook img

Philoponus : on Aristotle on the soul 2.1-6 PDF

193 Pages·2005·1.027 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Philoponus : on Aristotle on the soul 2.1-6

PHILOPONUS On Aristotle On the Soul 2.1-6 This page intentionally left blank PHILOPONUS On Aristotle On the Soul 2.1-6 Translated by William Charlton Duckworth LONDON(cid:2)(cid:222)(cid:2)(cid:48)(cid:39)(cid:57)(cid:2)(cid:38)(cid:39)(cid:46)(cid:42)(cid:43)(cid:2)(cid:222)(cid:2)(cid:48)(cid:39)(cid:57)(cid:2)YO(cid:52)(cid:45)(cid:2)(cid:222)(cid:2)SYDN(cid:39)(cid:59) Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published in 2005 by 50 Bedford SquGaerreald Duckworth & Co. L1td38.5 Broadway L9o0nd-9o3n Cowcross Street, London EC1NMe w6B YFork WC1B 3DP NY 10018 Tel: 020 7490 7300 UK USA Fax: 020 7490 0080 [email protected] www.ducknet.co.uk Bloomsbury is a registered trade mark of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc Preface © 2005 by Richard Sorabji FTirrastn psulabtliisohne da nind 2N00o5te bsy © G e2r0a0ld5 Dbuyc Wkwilolritahm & C Choa. Lrlttdo.n (cid:51)(cid:68)(cid:83)(cid:72)(cid:85)(cid:69)(cid:68)(cid:70)(cid:78)(cid:3)(cid:72)(cid:71)(cid:76)(cid:87)(cid:76)(cid:82)(cid:81)(cid:3)(cid:192)(cid:85)(cid:86)(cid:87)(cid:3)(cid:83)(cid:88)(cid:69)(cid:79)(cid:76)(cid:86)(cid:75)(cid:72)(cid:71)(cid:3)(cid:21)(cid:19)(cid:20)(cid:23)(cid:3) All rights reserved. No part of this publication Preface © 2005 by Richard Sorabji mTayra bnesl aretiporno adnudc eNdo,t esst o©r e2d0 0i5n bay rWetirlliieavma lC shyasrtlteomn, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, Richard Sorabji manedc hWainlliicaaml ,C phhaortltoocno phyaivneg a,s rseecrtoerdd itnhegi ro rri gohthtse ruwndiseer ,the Copyright, (cid:39)(cid:72)(cid:86)(cid:76)(cid:74)(cid:81)(cid:86)(cid:3)(cid:68)(cid:81)(cid:71)(cid:3)w(cid:51)(cid:68)it(cid:87)h(cid:72)(cid:81)o(cid:87)u(cid:86)t(cid:3)(cid:36) t(cid:70)h(cid:87)e(cid:15)(cid:3) (cid:20)p(cid:28)r(cid:27)i(cid:27)o(cid:15)r(cid:3)(cid:87) (cid:82)p(cid:3)e(cid:69)r(cid:72)m(cid:3)(cid:76)(cid:71)i(cid:72)s(cid:81)si(cid:87)o(cid:76)(cid:192)n(cid:72) (cid:71)o(cid:3)f(cid:68) t(cid:86)h(cid:3)(cid:87)e(cid:75) (cid:72)p(cid:3)(cid:36)u(cid:88)b(cid:87)li(cid:75)s(cid:82)h(cid:85)e(cid:86)(cid:3)r(cid:82).(cid:73)(cid:3)(cid:87)(cid:75)(cid:76)(cid:86)(cid:3)(cid:90)(cid:82)(cid:85)(cid:78)(cid:17) All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any A catalogue record for this book is available form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or from the British Library any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. ISBN 0 7156 3235 3 No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or refraining from action as a result of the matAerciakln ino wthlies dpgubelmicaetniotns can be accepted by Bloomsbury Academic or the author. The present translations have been made possible by generous and British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data imaginative funding from the following sources: The National En- A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. dowment for the Humanities, Division of Research Programs, an independent federal agency of the USA; the Leverhulme Trust; the ISBN HB: 978-0-7156-3235-2 British Academy; the Jowett Copyright Trustees; the Royal Society (cid:3) (cid:51)(cid:37)(cid:29)(cid:3) (cid:28)(cid:26)(cid:27)(cid:16)(cid:20)(cid:16)(cid:23)(cid:26)(cid:21)(cid:24)(cid:16)(cid:24)(cid:26)(cid:26)(cid:21)(cid:16)(cid:27) (UK); Centro Internazionale A. Beltrame di Storia dello Spazio e del (cid:3) (cid:72)(cid:51)(cid:39)(cid:41)(cid:29)(cid:3)(cid:28)(cid:26)(cid:27)(cid:16)(cid:20)(cid:16)(cid:23)(cid:26)(cid:21)(cid:24)(cid:16)(cid:19)(cid:20)(cid:20)(cid:26)(cid:16)(cid:21) Tempo (Padua); Mario Mignucci; Liverpool University; the Leventis Foundation; the Arts and Humanities Research Board of the British Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Academy; the Esmée Fairbairn Charitable Trust; the Henry Brown A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. Trust; Mr and Mrs Egon; the Netherlands Organisation for Scien- tific Research (NOW/GAcWk)n;o wthlee dCgeumlteunrtasl Attaché of the Greek EmTbhaes psyre sienn tL tornandsolnat. ioTnhse h aevdei tboere nw misahdees p otoss itbhlea nbyk gSenaerraohu sB arnodadie, iPmaamgienlaat iHveu fbuyn,d Pinhgi lfirpom va tnhe d feorll oEwijikn,g Dsoounracelds: RTuhes sNeallt,i oannadl EDnadvoiwd mSeidnetr for theirf ocro mthme Henutmsa, naintide sI, nDnivai sKiounp orfe Reevsae afrocrh p Prreopgararimnsg, athnis volume for ipnrdeespse.ndent federal agency of the USA; the Leverhulme Trust; the British Academy; the Jowett Copyright Trustees; the Royal Society (UK); Centro Internazionale A. Beltrame di Storia dello Spazio e del Tempo (Padua); Mario Mignucci; Liverpool University; the Leventis Foundation; the Arts and Humanities Research Board of the British Academy; the Esmée Fairbairn Charitable Trust; the Henry Brown (cid:55)(cid:85)(cid:88)(cid:86)(cid:87)(cid:30)(cid:3)(cid:48)(cid:85)(cid:3)(cid:68)(cid:81)(cid:71)(cid:3)(cid:48)(cid:85)(cid:86)(cid:3)(cid:40)(cid:74)(cid:82)T(cid:81)y(cid:30)(cid:3)p(cid:87)(cid:75)e(cid:72)s(cid:3)e(cid:49)t(cid:72) b(cid:87)(cid:75)y(cid:72) R(cid:85)(cid:79)a(cid:68)y(cid:81) (cid:71)D(cid:86)(cid:3)a(cid:50)v(cid:85)i(cid:74)e(cid:68)s(cid:81)(cid:76)(cid:86)(cid:68)(cid:87)(cid:76)(cid:82)(cid:81)(cid:3)(cid:73)(cid:82)(cid:85)(cid:3)(cid:54)(cid:70)(cid:76)(cid:72)(cid:81)(cid:87)(cid:76)(cid:192)(cid:70) ResearcPhr (iNntOeWd /aGnWd) ;b tohuen Cdu ilntu Grarl eAattt aBcrhiét aofi nth bey Greek Embassy in LBoniddodnle. sT hLet ded, iKtoirn wg’iss hLeysn ton ,t hNaonrkf oSlakrah Broadie, Pamela Huby, Philip van der Eijk, Donald Russell, and David Sider for their comments, and Inna Kupreeva for preparing this volume for press. Typeset by Ray Davies Printed and bound in Great Britain Contents Preface vii Translation 1 Notes 129 English-Greek Glossary 149 Greek-English Index 162 Subject Index 183 This page intentionally left blank Preface Richard Sorabji Philoponus in the sixth century AD is writing a commentary on On the Soul 2.1-6, where Aristotle gives a very different account of the soul from Plato’s. Aristotle talks of the soul in a sense that we all recognise as something we possess. The soul is the life-manifesting capacities that distinguish living things, and explain their behaviour. This clarifies his initial definition, which ties soul closely to body as its form. He defines soul and life by reference to the capacities for using food to maintain structure and reproduce, for perceiving and desiring, and for rational thought, the first available even to plants, the second distinguishing animals and the last available only to humans. Capacities have to be defined by their active operation, and their active operation by reference to the objects to which it is directed. The five senses are defined by reference to their objects, as perception of colour, sound, etc., but it is by perceiving these objects that one also perceives other objects by more than one sense – size, shape, etc. Thirdly, we perceive physical objects. Later he will speak of facts too as being perceived. In perceiving, Aristotle says, we receive perceptible forms, e.g. col- ours, without matter. On one interpretation, the eye jelly takes on patches of colour, but not material particles, from the scene perceived. But Philoponus interprets otherwise. The reception of perceptible form, he says, is not a physiological change, e.g. in the eye jelly, but only a cognitive reception (gnôstikôs), 303,5-6; 309,15-29. Moreover, ‘without matter’ is not designed to exclude reception of particles, but rather to say that sense does not act like wax receiving an imprint, because it does not act as matter to the sensible qualities that it receives, but receives them non-physically. Franz Brentano understood Aristotle in a similarly non- physiological spirit, as anticipating here the seminal idea that things perceived are only, in the medieval terminology which he has made familiar,intentional objects. They do not have to exist in reality in order to serve as objects. Some scholars agree in endorsing a non-physiological interpretation and take Philoponus as their patron. Myles Burnyeat has the most powerful arguments for a version of it. But Sorabji has argued that the commentators were slowly forced to reinterpret Aristotle’s mean- viii Preface ing, as they found that his physiological story ran into difficulties over the collision of different perceptible forms as they were received.1 Given that Aristotle ties the soul so closely to the body, it comes as a surprise when he says at On the Soul 2.1, 413a8-9, that it is not yet clear whether the way in which the soul is the actuality (entelekheia) of the body is like the way in which the sailor actualises the defining functions of the ship. Surely, we think, the sailor, unlike Aristotle’s soul, can exist quite independently of what he is in. Perhaps that is why the last great commentator of the Aristotelian school, Alexander, who wrote around AD 200, substitutes ‘art of navigation’ for ‘sailor’ at DA 15,10, when he denies the possibility of such independent existence for the soul. But other commentators, Themistius in DA 43,30-5, ‘Simplicius’ in DA 96,3-10 and Philoponus in DA 224,28-37 (cf. 241,27-8; 242,18-19) allow independent existence and think that Aristotle’s concession concerns the intellectual part of the human soul as surviving bodily death. Nonetheless, Philoponus must allow that there is for Aristotle some unclarity about the independence of the intellect. Philoponus explains that the intellect is like the navigator. As one who is exercising the activities of navigator, he cannot exercise those in separation from the ship, but at the same time as a human, he is something separate from the ship and can separate himself from it. Similarly with the human intellect. I mentioned that Aristotle allows perception to grasp facts and physical objects. At Nicomachean Ethics 3.10, 1118a20-3, the lion per- ceives that the ox is near. But Aristotle wants animals to be able to do this without possessing a faculty of reason. He is opposed to the view of Plato, Theaetetus 186B-187A that being (ousia) has to be grasped not by perception, but by reason and belief.2 That is why Philoponus, faithful to Aristotle at 317,25-32, says that the dog recognises its master by perception, not reason, because it knows its master not as a being (ousia, line 30, Plato’s word in the Theaetetus), but as such and such a friendly shape. He adds to Aristotle not only the reference to friendli- ness and hostility as what is stored, but also to the imagination (phantasia) as the place where the imprints are stored. Philoponus knew Alexander’s work very well. One sign of this is his allowing into the interpretation of Aristotle Alexander’s anti-Platonic account of universals as constructs of the mind, 307,35, reflecting Alexander DA 90,2-11; Quaestio 2.28 (78,18-20; 79,16-18). These are just a few of the highlights of this part of Philoponus’ commentary. Notes 1. Richard Sorabji, ‘From Aristotle to Brentano: The development of the concept of intentionality’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy suppl. vol. 1991, 227-59. 2. Richard Sorabji, Animal Minds and Human Morals, London & Ithaca, N.Y. 1983, ch. 2. PHILOPONUS On Aristotle On the Soul 2.1-6 Translation

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.