ebook img

Philoponus: On Aristotle on the Soul 1.1-2 PDF

232 Pages·2005·1.8 MB·English
by  Eijk
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Philoponus: On Aristotle on the Soul 1.1-2

PHILOPONUS On Aristotle On the Soul 1.1-2 This page intentionally left blank PHILOPONUS On Aristotle On the Soul 1.1-2 Translated by Philip J. van der Eijk Bristol Classical Press Ancient Commentators on Aristotle LOSNeDrOiNe(cid:2)s(cid:222)(cid:2) (cid:48)e(cid:39)d(cid:57)i(cid:2)t(cid:38)o(cid:39)r(cid:46):(cid:42) R(cid:43)(cid:2)(cid:222)i(cid:2)c(cid:48)h(cid:39)(cid:57)ar(cid:2)YdO (cid:52)S(cid:45)o(cid:2)(cid:222)r(cid:2)aSYbDjNi(cid:39)(cid:59) PublisheBd lboyo mBrsbisutoryl CAlcaasdsiecmali cPress 2012 An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc Bristol Classical Press, an imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square 1385 Broadway London Bloomsbury Publishing Plc New York WC1B 3DP 50 Bedford Square NY 10018 UK London WC1B 3DP USA www.bloomsburyacademic.com www.bloomsbury.com Preface copyright © Richard Sorabji 2005 Bloomsbury is a regInisttreodreudct itorna,d Ter amnasrlakt ioofn Balnodo Nmostbesury Publishing Plc copyright © Philip J. van der Eijk 2005 First published in 2005 by Gerald Duckworth & Co. Ltd. First pu(cid:51)b(cid:68)l(cid:83)is(cid:72)h(cid:85)(cid:69)ed(cid:68) (cid:70)b(cid:78)y(cid:3)(cid:72) G(cid:71)(cid:76)e(cid:87)r(cid:76)a(cid:82)(cid:81)ld(cid:3)(cid:192) D(cid:85)(cid:86)u(cid:87)c(cid:3)k(cid:83)w(cid:88)(cid:69)o(cid:79)r(cid:76)t(cid:86)h(cid:75) (cid:72)&(cid:71) (cid:3)C(cid:21)o(cid:19).(cid:20) L(cid:23)(cid:3)td. 2005 The authors have asPserretfeadc et h©e iRr ircihgahrtds Suonrdaebrj it h2e0 0C5opyright, Designs and IntrPoadtuecnttiso nA,c Tt r1a9n8s8l attoi obne aidnedn Nti(cid:192)oteeds a©s Pthheil aipu tJh. ovrasn o df ethr iEs iwjko 2rk0.05 Richard Sorabji and Philip JI.S vBaNn :d 9e7r8 E 0ij 7k1 h5a6v3e3 0a6ss 9erted their rights under the (cid:38)(cid:82)(cid:83)(cid:92)(cid:85)(cid:76)(cid:74)(cid:75)(cid:87)(cid:15)(cid:3)(cid:39)(cid:72)(cid:86)(cid:76)(cid:74)(cid:81)(cid:86)(cid:3)(cid:68)(cid:81)(cid:71)(cid:3)(cid:51)(cid:68)(cid:87)(cid:72)(cid:81)(cid:87)(cid:86)(cid:3)(cid:36)(cid:70)(cid:87)(cid:15)(cid:3)(cid:20)(cid:28)(cid:27)(cid:27)(cid:15)(cid:3)(cid:87)(cid:82)(cid:3)(cid:69)(cid:72)(cid:3)(cid:76)(cid:71)(cid:72)(cid:81)(cid:87)(cid:76)(cid:192)(cid:72)(cid:71)(cid:3)(cid:68)(cid:86)(cid:3)(cid:87)(cid:75)(cid:72)(cid:3)(cid:36)(cid:88)(cid:87)(cid:75)(cid:82)(cid:85)(cid:86)(cid:3)(cid:82)(cid:73)(cid:3)(cid:87)(cid:75)(cid:76)(cid:86)(cid:3)(cid:90)(cid:82)(cid:85)(cid:78)(cid:17) A CIP catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means,A eclekcntroownilce odrg memecehnatnsical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in The present translations wharivtein bge efrno mm atdhee ppousbsliibslhee brsy. generous and imaginative funding from the following sources: the National Endowment for the NHou rmesapnointiseisb,i Dlitiyv ifsoiro nlo osfs Rcaeusesaerdc tho Parnoyg rinamdisv,i dauna iln odre opregnadneinzta tfeiodne raaclt iangge noncy o orf refrainthineg U frSoAm; tahcet iLonev aesr hau rlemsue lTt rouf stth; et hmea Bterritiaislh i nA tchaidse pmuyb;l itchaet iJoonw ceatnt Cbeo paycrciegphtte d by Bloomsbury Academic or the author. Trustees; the Royal Society (UK); Centro Internazionale A. Beltrame di Storia dello Spazio e del Tempo (Padua); Mario Mignucci; Liverpool University; the British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data Leventis Foundation; the Arts and Humanities Research Board of the British A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. Academy; the Esmée Fairbairn Charitable Trust; the Henry Brown Trust; Mr and Mrs N. Egon; the Netherlands Organisation for Scienti(cid:192)c Research (NWO/ ISBN HB: 978-0-7156-3306-9 GW); Dr Victoria Solomonides, the Cultural Attaché of the Greek Embassy in (cid:3) (cid:51)(cid:37)(cid:29)(cid:3) (cid:28)(cid:26)(cid:27)(cid:16)(cid:20)(cid:16)(cid:23)(cid:26)(cid:21)(cid:24)(cid:16)(cid:24)(cid:26)(cid:26)(cid:26)(cid:16)(cid:22) London. The editor wishes to thank Matthias Perkams, Pamela Huby, Robert (cid:3) (cid:72)(cid:51)(cid:39)(cid:41)(cid:29)(cid:3)(cid:28)(cid:26)(cid:27)(cid:16)(cid:20)(cid:16)(cid:23)(cid:26)(cid:21)(cid:24)(cid:16)(cid:19)(cid:20)(cid:21)(cid:26)(cid:16)(cid:20) Todd and William Charlton for their comments, John Sellars for preparing the volume for press, and Deborah Blake at Duckworth, who has been the publisher Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data responsible for every volume in the series since the beginning. A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. Typeset by Ray Davies Acknowledgements Printed and bound in Great Britain by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croyden, CR0 4YY The present translations have been made possible by generous and imaginative funding from the following sources: the National Endowment for the Humanities, Caution Division of Research Programs, an independent federal agency of the USA; the All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced in any form Leverhulme Trust; the British Academy; the Jowett Copyright Trustees; the Royal or by any means – graphic, electronic or mechanical, including information Society (UK); Centro Internazionale A. Beltrame di Storia dello Spazio e del Tempo storage and retrieval systems – without the prior written permission of (Padua); Mario Mignucci; Liverpool University; the Leventis Foundation; the Arts Bloomsbury Publishing Plc. and Humanities Research Board of the British Academy; the Esmée Fairbairn Charitable Trust; the Henry Brown Trust; Mr and Mrs N. Egon; the Netherlands This book is produced using paper that is made from wood grown in managed, (cid:50)(cid:85)(cid:74)(cid:68)(cid:81)(cid:76)(cid:86)(cid:68)(cid:87)(cid:76)(cid:82)(cid:81)(cid:3)(cid:73)(cid:82)(cid:85)(cid:3)(cid:54)(cid:70)(cid:76)(cid:72)(cid:81)(cid:87)(cid:76)(cid:192)(cid:70)(cid:3)(cid:53)(cid:72)(cid:86)(cid:72)(cid:68)(cid:85)(cid:70)(cid:75)(cid:3)(cid:11)(cid:49)(cid:58)(cid:50)(cid:18)(cid:42)(cid:58)(cid:12)(cid:30)(cid:3)(cid:39)(cid:85)(cid:3)(cid:57)(cid:76)(cid:70)(cid:87)(cid:82)(cid:85)(cid:76)(cid:68)(cid:3)(cid:54)(cid:82)(cid:79)(cid:82)(cid:80)(cid:82)(cid:81)(cid:76)(cid:71)(cid:72)(cid:86)(cid:15)(cid:3)(cid:38)(cid:88)(cid:79)(cid:87)(cid:88)(cid:85)(cid:68)(cid:79) sustainable forests. It is natural, renewable and recyclable. The logging and Attaché of the Embassy of Greece in London. The editor wishes to thank Alan Lacey, manufacturing processes conform to the environmental regulations of the Ian Mueller, Christopher Taylor, and Rosemary Wright for their comments, Inna country of origin. Kupreeva and John Sellars for preparing this volume for press, and Deborah Blake who has been Duckworth’s editor for all volumes in the series since the beginning. Typeset by Ray Davies Printed and bound in Great Britain Contents Preface vii Acknowledgements x Introduction 1 Deviations from the Text of M. Hayduck 11 Translation 13 Prooemium 15 Chapter 1 36 Chapter 2 82 Notes 115 Bibliography 145 English-Greek Glossary 163 Greek-English Index 177 Index of Names 207 Subject Index 209 Index of Passages 215 This page intentionally left blank Preface Richard Sorabji The commentary by Philoponus on Aristotle On the Soul is taken from the seminars of his teacher, Ammonius, with additions of his own. This opening volume contains an important overview in the Prooemium, which first distinguishes the different faculties of the soul and then argues for the soul’s incorporeality, but also analyses its relation to fleshly and non-fleshly bodies. I shall concentrate on the Prooemium, because it makes a number of striking points. At 4,22, Philoponus explains Aristotle’s idea at An. Post. 1.31, 88a12- 17; 2.2, 90a26, that one might be able to recognise from a single observation that all lunar eclipse is due to the earth’s shadow, or that all glass is transparent because it contains pores. Philoponus takes the example of inferring from the sphericity of the moon that all heavenly bodies are spherical. But what he adds is that it requires knowing that they all have the same essence and then using discursive reason (dianoia). At 5,16, it is no accident that Philoponus talks in a commentary on Aristotle of opinion being reminded (anamnêsthênai) by seeing a single instance that all members of a given species have two feet. For he ascribes to Aristotle Plato’s theory that we are reminded, or recollect, what we knew before birth, when he says in De Intellectu p. 40,36 Verbeke, that the child’s potential intellect has innate knowledge sup- pressed by the process of birth. At 5,3, Philoponus makes opinion (doxa) project concepts (proballein logous) that it retains within of perceptible objects. This was already postulated by Proclus as the method by which opinion recognises the essences of sensible things, in Tim. 1, 251,4-9, a reference I owe to Matthias Perkams. Elsewhere Proclus describes the projection of concepts onto the screen of imagination as like projection of images onto a mirror, rather in the manner of the modern cinema, in Eucl. 1, 121,1-7; 141,2-19. In Philoponus, we find the Platonist tendency to blur Aristotle’s sharp distinction between intellectual and perceptual functions. At 5,34-6,10, he equates imagination, which receives impressions (tupoi) from the senses, and which Aristotle treats as a perceptual faculty, with passive intellect. This blurring of the perceptual and intellectual was already present in an earlier commentator Themistius, who at in DA viii Preface 98,35-99,10, made potential intellect into a storehouse of impressions from perception. And Proclus already reports that passive intellect and imagination had been equated, in Eucl. 1, 51,10-52,20. Turning to the practical faculties, at 5,24-33, Philoponus evinces an attitude to deliberate choice (proairesis) closer to that of the Neoplaton- ist Iamblichus than to Aristotle’s. For Aristotle, deliberate choice had been the centrepiece of his ethics. The human being had been equated with this faculty, EN, 6.2, 1139b5. By Iamblichus, by contrast, deliber- ate choice is criticised precisely because it can turn either way (rhepein pros amphotera is like Philoponus’ epamphoterizein), and so side against reason. It is useful only in the world of becoming, and, unlike the wish for the good (boulêsis), of which Philoponus also speaks, it would be shed by the purified soul, Iamblichus On the Mysteries of the Egyptians, 1.10, 36,1-5; 1.12, 41,3-4. The incorporeality of soul is argued partly on the basis that sight has to receive opposite qualities, both black and white, and no physical object can at the same time receive opposites in the same place, 12,34- 13,20. The gradual dematerialisation of the senses by Aristotle’s commentators, because of the need to avoid collision of opposites like black and white, started with an earlier commentator, Alexander, and has been traced in my ‘From Aristotle to Brentano: The Development of the Concept of Intentionality’.1 Self-awareness also depends on the incorporeality of some faculties. At 14,31-2, Philoponus uses a term for self-awareness that is already found in the Stoic Epictetus, epistrephesthai, to turn in on oneself, and he refers to the point made by the Neoplatonist Porphyry, Sentences 41, 52,7-53,5, that a body cannot engage in this self-penetration. The only faculties which can do so are rational faculties, because they can operate independently of body. At 14,36ff., Philoponus gives as a reason for believing that rational faculties are self-aware the same reason as was given by Aristotle DA 3.4, 430a2-4; Metaph. 12.7, 1072b19-21, and repeated by Alexander DA 86,14-23 and Plotinus 5.3 [49] 5 (42-8). According to Aristotle, the thinking intellect is identical with the objects of its thought as they act upon it. So the objects which it thinks are, in a way, itself. Hence it is self-thinking. Philoponus says in 14,33-5 that it is the rational soul that is aware of our perception, whereas Aristotle had said it was the central perceptual faculty,On Sleep 2, 455a15-22, called by the commentators the common sense. The preference for reason had started among Platonists before Philoponus. It is found in Plutarch of Athens ap. ‘Philoponus’ in DA 3, 464,24-465,31 (I have sought to explain divergent reports in The Phi- losophy of the Commentators, 200-600 AD, vol. 1, Psychology, 4(c) [London & Ithaca, NY 2004]); Proclus in Tim. 1, 254,31-255,20. In a final twist, Philoponus’ contemporaries in Athens combine the idea that the common sense is responsible with the idea that a rational faculty is responsible for self-awareness, by blurring Aristotle’s distinction of the Preface ix perceptual and the intellectual further, and making Aristotle’s common sense into a rational faculty; Priscian, On Theophrastus 21,32-22,23; ‘Simplicius’ (who I now incline to think was Priscian) in DA 187,27- 188,35; 173,3-7. Philoponus tells us in 17,19ff. about the Platonist theory that the soul is housed not only in our fleshly body, but also in two finer bodies, called vehicles, which interpenetrate the fleshly body and outlast it. The idea of a vehicle for the soul comes from Plato, Phaedrus 247B, Phaedo 113D, and Timaeus 41D-E. A vehicle for the soul is needed, according to Philoponus, to permit punishment after death (a problem for Christian accounts of Purgatory), and to permit the materialisation of ghosts and demons. The coarser pneumatic vehicle could be shed by a purified soul, but not the luminous vehicle, as Proclus had already said, in Tim. 3, 236,31ff.; 298,12ff.; ET 196; 207-9; PT 3.5. Proclus reports, however, that there had been other views on the impermanence of the pneumatic vehicle, in Tim. 3, 234,8-235,9. Our need to keep our soul vehicles healthy is said by Philoponus at 19,27 to have implications for diet. Philoponus shows himself aware of medical developments since Aris- totle. In 19,19ff., unlike Aristotle, he is aware that the brain, not the heart, is the seat of consciousness, and he knows about its membranes and about the suppression of consciousness by pressure on the mem- branes, and about the optic nerve. He may have known about this through the works of the great doctor, Galen, but later in the commen- tary he opposes some of Galen’s physicalistic conclusions. Galen has a treatise called That mental states follow the states of the body. Philo- ponus, like Alexander before him, objects to the talk of following (hepesthai) and of being a result (apotelesma). Borrowing a word used by Alexander he says that mental states merely supervene (epigines- thai) on bodily states, 51,13-52,1. Philoponus finishes the Prooemium by saying that Aristotle in On the Soul, just as in the Physics and Metaphysics, concludes his treatise by moving to the highest principles, in this case to the immortal rational soul, 20,31ff. Philoponus was a Platonist, but also a Christian and an expounder of Aristotle. What strikes me about this Prooemium is how much it is the Platonism that comes to the fore, including the repeated Platonist reinterpretation of Aristotle. One would not predict from reading this Prooemium on its own that Philoponus would later launch a whole book attacking the pagan Platonist, Proclus, on behalf of Christianity. This may reflect the extent to which the Prooemium represents the views of Philoponus’ teacher Ammonius. Note 1.Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, supp. vol. 1991, 227-59.

Description:
Until the launch of this series over ten years ago, the 15,000 volumes of the ancient Greek commentators on Aristotle, written mainly between 200 and 600 AD, constituted the largest corpus of extant Greek philosophical writings not translated into English or other European languages. Over 30 volumes
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.