ebook img

Perspectives on Quine PDF

179 Pages·1990·19.903 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Perspectives on Quine

Perspectives on Quine Perspectives on Quine Edited by Robert B. Barrett and Roger F. Gibson Dedicated to the memory of Sir Alfred J. Ayer, one of the century's most unflinching empiricists. Basil Blackwell ~~ I \'E-(Z.. Copyright c 'The Refutation of Indeterminacy', Jerrold Katz 1988 Copyright C ·A Central Problem for a Speech-Dispositional Account of Logic and Language'. Alan Berger 1990 - Copyright 1· 'Meaning. Truth and Evidence', Donald Davidson 1990 Copyright c 'A Backward Look at Quine's Animadversions on Modalities', Ruth Barcan Marcus 1990 · Contents Copyright f' all other material, Basil Blackwell 1990 First published 1990 Basil Blackwell, Inc. s ... 3 Cambridge Center ( Cambridge. Massachusetts 02142, USA Basil Blackwell Ltd 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 IJF, UK All rights reserved. Except for the quotation of short passages for the purposes of Notes on Contributors Vil criticism and review, no part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted. in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher. Preface XI Except in the United States of America, this book is sold subject to the condition that Introduction XIII it shall not, by way of trade or otherwise, be lent, re-sold, hired out, or otherwise circulated without the publisher's prior consent in any form of binding or cover other Three Indeterminacies than that in which it is published and without a similar condition including this conditiong being imposed on the subsequent purchaser. W. V. Quine . 2 A Central Problem for a Speech-Dispositional Account of Logic Lihrary of Conyress Cata/01Jin11 in Puh/ication Data and Language 17 Perspectives on Quine/ edited by Robert B. Barrett and Roger F. Alan Berger Gibson Comment on Berger 36 p. cm. 3 Quine on Underdetermination 38 Proceedings of Perspectives on Quine: an International Conference. Lars Bergstrom Apr. 9- 13, 1988, at Washington University in St. Louis, sponsored by the James S. McDonnell Foundation and the Washington University Comment on Bergstrom 53 Faculty of Arts and Sciences and its Philosophy Dept. 4 Carnap, Quine and the Rejection of Intuition 55 Includes bibliographies and index. Richard Creath ISBN 0-631-16135-X Comment on Creath 67 I. Quine, W. V. (Willard Van Orman)--Congresses. I. Quine, W. 5 Meaning, Truth and Evidence 68 V. (Willard Van Orman) II. Barrett, Robert B. Ill. Gibson, Roger F. JV. James S. McDonnell Foundation. V. Washington University Donald Davidson (St. Louis. Mo.). Faculty of Arts and Sciences. VI. Washington Comment on Davidson 80 University (St. Louis, Mo.). Philosophy Dept. 81 6 Quine B945.Q54P47 1989 Burton Dreben 191--dc19 89-30977 96 Comment on Dreben CIP 98 7 Indeterminacy and Mental States British Lihrary Catalo1J11i1111 in Puh/ication Data Dagfinn F0llesdal A CI P catalogue record for this book is available from the British Comment on F01lesdal 110 Library. 8 Rebuilding the Ship while Sailing on the Water 111 Susan Haack 128 Comment on Haack 129 9 Natural Kinds Typeset in I 0 on I I pt Times by P & R Typesetters Ltd, Salisbury, Wiltshire Ian Hacking 142 Printed in Great Britain by Billing & Sons Ltd, Worcester Comment on Hacking VI CONTENTS 10 Immanent and Transcendent Approaches to the Theory of - Meaning Gilbert Harman Comment on Harman Notes on Contributors 11 Quine as a Member of the Tradition of the Universality of Language Jaakko Hintikka Comment on Hintikka 176 12 The Refutation of Indeterminacy 177 - Jerrold Katz Comment on Katz 198 13 Why and How to Naturalize Epistemology 200 Dirk Koppelberg Comment on Koppelberg 212 Alan Berger is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Brandeis University. He 14 Holism and Naturalized Epistemology Confronted with the is the author of several articles on Quine and of a book entitled Terms and Problem of Truth 213 Truth. Henri Lauener Lars Bergstrom was born in Stockholm, Sweden, in 1935, and was educated Comment on Lauener 229 at the University of Stockholm. He has been Professor of Practical Philosophy 15 A Backward Look at Quine's Animadversions on Modalities 230 at the University of Uppsala from 1974 to 1987, and at the University of Ruth Barcan Marcus Stockholm since 1987. He has published books and articles on, for example, Comment on Marcus 244 the logic of imperatives, action theory, the philosophy of social science, 16 Is Existence What Existential Quantification Expresses? 245 utilitarianism, and the foundations of value theory. Alex Orenstein Comment on Orenstein 271 Richard Creath is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Arizona State 17 Genetic Explanation in The Roots of Reference 273 University and editor of the papers of Rudolf Carnap. He writes both on Charles Parsons contemporary issues in philosophy of science and on Carnap. Recently he Comment on Parsons 291 edited Dear Carnap, Dear Van: The Quine- Carnap Correspondence and Other 18 Doing Without Meaning 294 Material, forthcoming from University of California Press. Currently he is Anthony Quinton working on a book, tentatively entitled Analyticity: The Carnap-Quine Comment on Quinton 309 Debate Over the Structure of Knowledge. 19 Two Conceptions of Philosophy 310 Donald Davidson is the the Willis S. and Marion Slusser Professor of P. F. Strawson Philosophy at the University of California at Berkeley. Most of his published Comment on Strawson 319 work is on the philosophy of psychology, particularly the theory of action 20 Quine's Physicalism 321 and the philosophy of language. Barry Stroud Burton Dreben, Edgar Pierce Professor of Philosophy at Harvard University, Comment on Stroud 334 began studying with Quine in 1946. He received his AB degree from Harvard 21 Learning and Meaning 336 in 1949, was a Fulbright Fellow at Magdalen College, Oxford, 1950- 1, a Joseph S. Ullian Junior Fellow of the Society of Fellows, Harvard, 1952- 5, and was an Comment on Ullian 347 Instructor in Philosophy at The University of Chicago, 1955-6. A member Bibliography of Quine's Works Cited in Comments 348 of the faculty at Harvard since 1956, he was Dean of the Graduate School Index 349 of Arts and Sciences in 1973-6, and is Chairman of the Society of Fellows. Professor Dreben was an editor of The Journal ~{Symbolic Logic, 1967- 76. He was a Guggenheim Fellow in 1957- 8, and is a Fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. He is a co-author with Warren D. Goldfarb of The Decision Problem, and is the author of papers in Mathematical Logic and the History of Mathematical Logic. Vil! NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS IX Dagfi_nn Follesdal took ~is PhD with Quine in 1961 ( di~sertation: Referential ( 1975 ), Geneva ( 1977) and Innsbruck ( 1986 ). He is a member of the Institut Opa~·1ty and Modal Logic), taught at Harvard until 1964, when he returned de Ia Methode and of the Institut International de Philosophie. He organizes to his nat1~e Norway where he is Professor of Philosophy at the University the biennial International Colloquia in Biel which has become a traditional of Oslo. Smee 196~ he has also been teaching at Stanford University, from meeting place for analytic philosophers of renown from America and Europe. 1974 as C. I. Lewis Professor of Philosophy. He served as editor of The He is the editor of Dialectica. In spite of the fact that he is opposed to Journal of Symbolic Logic, 1970- 82. His publications are concerned with naturalism - his own position being a kind of pragmatically relativized language, science, action, Husserl, Heidegger and Sartre. transcendentalism - he has written a book on Quine, whom he considers as the most influential American philosopher of our century. S~san Haack is _Professor of Philosophy at the University of Warwick, United Kmg~om. _Sh~ 1s the author of Deviant Logic and Philosophy of Logics, and Ruth Barcan Marcus, Halleck Professor, Yale University was the first person of _articles m Journals and a~thologies on philosophy of logic and language, to develop modal quantification theory. Some results which stimulated epistemology and metaphysics, and pragmatism. subsequent interest concerned the necessity of identity, quantifier- modality permutation ('the Barcan formula'), and the failure of a strong deduction Ian Hacking teaches at the University of Toronto. His books include The theorem for Lewis's strict implication. In the context of the formal studies Emergence of Probability, Why Does Language Matter co Philosophy, and her article 'Modalities and intensional languages' (Synthese, 1961) argued Representing and Intervening. He has just completed a work on information inter alia for a direct reference theory for proper names, the plausibility of and control during the nineteenth century, The Taming of Chance. the necessity of identity, the non-commitment of modal logic to essentialism, Gilbert Harman was a graduate student in philosophy at Harvard in the and the possible uses of substitutional interpretations of quantification. early 1960s w_here his dissertation was supervised by Quine. Harman's Related themes were developed in subsequent articles. She has also published subse9uent p?1l~sophical work is in part a series of sympathetic reactions on topics in epistemology and ethics. Professor Marcus has served the ~o Qume, begmnmg with a two-part essay. 'Quine on meaning and existence' profession in many capacities including that of Chair of the Board of the m ~h_e Review of Meta physics in 1967, continuing through Thought, and American Philosophical Association and President of the Association for arnvmg most recently at Change in View: Principles of Reasoning. Symbolic Logic. She is also a fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. Jaakko ~intikka is Profess?r of Phi~osophy at Florida State University. He has teachmg and research mterests m many areas of philosophy. He is the Alex Orenstein is a Professor in the philosophy program at Queens College author of over 200 hundred articles and over a dozen books. Among the and the Graduate Center of the City University of New York. He is the latte_r are: _Knowledge and Belief An Introduction to the Logic of the Two author of an expository work on Quine's views: Willard Van Orman Quine. N~twns, T1~ne and_ Necessity: Studies in Artistole's Theory of Modality, and Among his other works is the monograph Existence and the Particular (with Mernl B. Hmt1kka) Investigating Wittgenstein. Quantifier and the co-edited volumes Foundations: Logic, Language and Mathematics and Developments in Semantics. Jerrold J. Katz is Distinguished Professor of Philosophy and Linguistics at the Graduate Center of the City University of New York. He is the author of Charles Parsons was at the time of Washington University conference on Semantic Theory, Propos~tiona/ Structure and Illocutionary Force, Language Quine Professor and Chairperson of the Department of Philosophy at am~ Other A_hs~ract C?h1~cts, and Congitations: he recently edited The Columbia University. In July of 1989 he joined the Department of Philosophy P/11losophy of Lmgu1st1cs m the Oxford Essays in Philosophy series. at Harvard University. He is the author of Mathematics in Philosophy and articles on logic and other subjects. Dirk Koppelberg, Assistant Professor of Philosophy at the Ruhr-Universitiit Bochum and visiting sc~olar at the University of California at Berkeley in W. V. Quine was born in 1908 in Akron, studied mathematics at Oberlin, 1988, is the author of Die Aujhenbung der analytischen Philosophie - Quine and proceeded to philosophy at Harvard. In 1936, after four years of als Synthese von _Carnap und Neurath. He has published various articles on post-doctoral fellowships there and abroad, he joined the Harvard philosophy ep1st:mology, philosophy of la~guage, philosophy of science and philosophy faculty. He is now professor emeritus. He served in World War II as lieutenant of m_1~d an_d is now engaged m a study of naturalistic epistemology and commander. Professor Quine has lectured in twenty-four countries, six cogrnt1ve science which 1s supported by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft continents, and six languages. Seven of his books are on logic and eleven are Bonn. more centrally philosophical. Henri Lau_ener, born in 1933, is Professor of Philosophy at University of Lord Quinton taught philosophy in Oxford from 1949 to 1978, at All Bern_e, ~w1tzerland. He has been Visiting Professor at the Universities of Souls College and then at New College. He was president of Trinity College Helsmk1 ( 1969), University of California at San Diego ( 1975, 1980), Lausanne from 1978 to 1987 and since 1985 has been chairman of the British Library x NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS Board. His main publications are The Nature of Things, Utilitarian Ethics, The Politics of Imperfection, and Thoughts and Thinkers a collection of articles. A book on ethics and a second collection of articles 'are forthcoming. Sir Peter Strawson, born in London in 1919 and educated at Oxford served Preface in the Army from 1940 to 1946, returning in 1947 to Oxford where' he has lived and taught ever since. He was professor of Metaphysic~ at Magdalen College, 1968- 87. Author of eight books and many articles, Professor Strawso~ has lectured and read papers at many universities outside England, notably m the United States, India, France, Germany, and China. He is married with four children. Barry Str~ud, Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Berkeley, is the author of Hume and The Significance of Philosophical Scep!icism ~s. well as e.ssays on a variety of philosophical topics. His prev1ou~ wnt.mgs on Qu~ne include dicsussion of naturalized epistemology, During 9- 13 April, 1988, Perspectives on Quine: An International Conference, conventionalism and log1cal truth, and the indeterminacy of translation. convened at Washington University in St Louis under the sponsorship of the James S. McDonnell Foundation of St Louis, the Faculty of Arts Joseph S. Ullian is Professor of Philosophy at Washington University and and Sciences of Washington University, and the Washington University has taught there since 1965. His doctorate is from Harvard where he studied Philosophy Department. Over 300 persons attended the four and one-half under Quine. He has written articles on logic, philosophy' of language, and day conference. the .theory of formal !anguages, ~nd is co-author with Quine of The Web of Each of the conference's 24 speakers was alloted an hour and ten minutes Belief His extracurricular pass10ns include baseball, basketball, running, to present his or her paper and to respond to questions from the audience. music, and theater. No commentators were scheduled. Of course, Professor Quine was in the audience, and on the first day of the conference, after just two papers had been presented, it became clear that those in the audience expected to hear Quine's comments from the floor before offering their own. In the light of this spontaneous development, Professor Quine graciously consented to the proposal that he join each subsequent speaker on stage, where he would have access to a microphone. He also consented to take questions from the audience, after each paper. Quine rose to the occasion: four and one-half days of vintage Quine. The conference, spontaneously, took on a sort of organic unity that is rarely found in philosophy conferences: 24 speakers, 300 interlocutors, and Professor Quine sitting down to talk philosophy. The effect was enthralling: the audience evinced an unspoken awareness that they were not only witnesses to history in the making, but participants to philosophy in the making! The papers selected for publication in this volume are revised versions of papers read at the conference. Most of Professor Quine's comments were recorded, and all those that were recorded were subsequently transcribed. The recordings and transcripts were used by Professor Quine in preparing his written comments. Thus neither the papers nor Professor Quine's comments appear in this volume exactly as they were heard in April. We should like to take this opportunity to thank the following people who were in the conference program: Alfred J. Ayer (Oxford), John Barker (Southern Illinois- Edwardsville), Dorit Bar-On (Rochester), Alan Berger (Brandeis), Lars Bergstrom (Stockholm), John Bruer (James S. McDonnell Foundation), J. Richard Creath (Arizona State), Donald Davidson (California- XII PREFACE Berkeley), William Danforth (Washington-St Louis), Burton Dreben (Harvard), J. Claude Evans (Washington- St Louis), Robert Feleppa (Wichita State), Dagfinn F01lesdal (Oslo), G. N. Georgacarakos (Gustavus Adolphus), Anthony Genova (Kansas), Robert Gordon (Missouri- St Louis), Susan Haack (Warwick), Ian Hacking (Toronto), Lewis Hahn (Southern Illinois Introduction Carbondale), Gilbert Harman (Princeton), David Henderson (Memphis State), Jaakko Hintikka (Florida State), Max Hocutt (Alabama), Daniel Isaacson (Oxford), Martin Israel (Washington- St Louis), Jerrold Katz (CUNY), Dirk Koppelberg (Ruhr Universitiit- Bochum), Lucian Krukowski (Washington- St Louis), Henri Lauener (Bern), Ruth Barcan Marcus (Yale), Alex Orenstein (CUNY), Charles Parsons (Columbia), Lorenzo Pena (Instituto de Filosofia), Anthony Quinton (British Library Board), Mark Rollins (Washington- St Louis), Paul Roth (Missouri- St Louis), Carl Smith (International Center for Epistemology), Peter Strawson (Oxford), Barry Stroud (California- Berkeley), James Swindler (Westminster), Joseph Ullian In this the age of linguistic philosophy, the study of the nature of language (Washington- St Louis), and Hao Wang (Rockefeller). We would also like as such is widely accorded that honored propaedeutic role that the study of to thank the members of the audience for their spirited participation. just the narrowly logical features of language had been assigned by Aristotle. Special thanks are due, of course, to Van Quine for the super-human effort Based on what is learned - or at least surmised - on the basis of such he put into making the conference (and this volume) a success, and to study, explicitly linguistic methods of analysis are spawned, developed and Marjorie Quine for taking the time away from other activities to accompany refined. These methods may then be brought to bear in the articulation, Van to St Louis. clarification and sometimes actual resolution of philosophical issues, even The logistical side of the conference was expertly handled by Ms Dorothy including some that are as old and venerated as the Western philosophical Fleck, Administrative Assistant, and by Ms Debi Katz, Departmental tradition itself. Among the striking sea changes in philosophical subject matter Secretary. The conference would have been virtually impossible without their frequently wrought by these means - indeed no doubt the pivotal upshot of help. Also, our thanks to the Philosophy Department's many graduate the linguistic reorientation of philosophical thought - is the transformation students who contributed to the conference in various unrewarding but of what had long been seen as substantive questions about the world and its essential capacities. nature into questions about the language and its workings. Language Finally, special thanks are due to the James S. McDonnell Foundation, as propaeudeutic to philosophy, language as analytic tool for philosophers, which provided the lion's share of the funding for the conference. even language as the proper philosophical subject matter - these are the trademarks of philosophy gone linguistic. R. B. B. As a feature player in this drama for the past half century, and as the R. F. G. storm-center of much of its controversy for nearly as long, W. V. Quine is the quintessential linguistic philosopher. His own emphases during the years in question may be seen gradually to have shifted from syntax to pragmatics, from logical theory to learning theory, and from a chief preoccupation with the - generally extralinguistic - things our language purposes to address and describe ('ontology'), to a primary concern with the nature of the descriptive apparatus the language uses in describing them ('ideology'). But throughout these adjustments in focus, the grand enterprise has remained the same, that of limning the scope and detailing the form and dynamics of the language in which we characterize the world, and thus divining the character both of that characterization and even, to a more limited extent, of the characterized world itself. The Web of Belief For Quine, then, what we take to be human knowledge is not just codified XIV INTRODUCTION INTRODUCTION xv by, but in a significant sense actually consists in, those individual sentences, As might be hoped, however, the old-line distinction between linguistic integrated clusters of related sentences, and above all theories, that we believe and empirical truths is only partially effaced by Quine's analysis. Loud echoes ~o be true. Or, more strictly, since many of the reasons philosophers study of it persist in the marked contrast between the language as a whole and human_k nowledge' recommend against construing it so broadly as to cover limited-scope theories that draw only on a modicum of its resources. These the fleeting, evanescent, or temporary, the sentences such knowledge embraces theories have languages of their own, to be sure, (the 'language of biochemistry' for Qume exclude the 'occ~sion sen~en_ces' that are applicable today but and whatnot) but such special-purpose languages are scarcely self-contained, defunc_t tomorr~w, and consist rather m JUSt the 'eternal sentences', the ones leech on the parent natural language that provides all but their technical we believe - while we believe them at all - for the long wordly haul. As the vocabularies, and so reach for their foundations well beyond the confines of wh?le composed of all these eternal sentences - or the 'web of belief' as limited-scope theories they couch. Qume and _Joseph Ullian have perspicuously entitled it - our presumptive Prominent traces of the linguistic-truth/empirical-truth distinction also knowledge is ~ va~t bo_dy_o f li?g~is~ic entities. rt is, from this vantage point, remain even for the full-fledged web of belief itself, in certain differences of then,_an extens1~e lmgu1st1cent1ty m its own right, and subject to philosophical degree. For some beliefs in the web are highly resistive to dislodgement by scrutiny by precisely those methods most appropriate to the study of language. counterevidence, others much less so. The former are those whose abandonment must send reverberations all over the web, forcing the revision of countless Reconstruing Language and Theory more beliefs in addition. The surrender of the latter, by contrast, would have only limited impact. The beliefs whose revision would be disruptive on a For all _of this, on_e might still find a major gulf to divide our language from large scale, tend to count as 'linguistic', in that they are generally presupposed our beliefs. _Classically, the la?guage has often been seen as an essentially by users of the language and so regularly invoked in explanations of n~utr~I medium for_the expression of beliefs, with room enough for all possible 'meaning'. They are the nearest thing to the legitimate heirs of analytic truths, d1ve'.s1ty. From this vantage point it is indifferent to one's beliefs in the inheriting a weaker version of the distinctive trait of their progenitors, and precise sense_that the negation of each sentence in the language is also in the thus displaying stout resistance to evidential pressures in lieu of total langua_ge while both are candidates for belief. What we believe, on the other immunity to them. The beliefs that would actually be revised in typical hand, is surely_ selective_. Only s~me of ~hat can be said in the language is counterevidential circumstances count as 'empirical' for that very reason. ~mong o~r beliefs, and 1f we are m any kmd of luck there is no sentence and heirs to the mantle of factuality of their deceased synthetic forebears. As more its _negation. both of which we think true. So the language is a vehicle in or less intractable beliefs shade into more or less tractable ones by degrees, which anything can be said, our beliefs just that limited portion we actually so language shades into theory and in particular the one big language, 'the do (or would)_ say. ~r so it can seem, and has seemed to many. language we speak', into the one sweeping theory Quine sees as our But for Qume things are not this straightforward, and the line between comprehensive 'background theory'. It is thus that while he hasn't by language and theo~y_is a_ blurry one at best. If one way of making the putative any means banished the language/theory distinction, Quine has blurred, language/th_eory d1stmct~on takes the lan?uage as a vast totality of(syntactical restructured and repositioned it on our conceptual map. and semantical) convent10ns and our beliefs as a totality, rather, of what pass for matte.rs of fact, then the language/theory distinction threatens to be a casualty 1f on~ challenges the distinction between convention and fact. This, Empirical Holism ramously, Qume ~oe~. [n an assortment of celebrated articles, (including Trut~ by convent1?n , ( 1936), 'Two dogmas of empiricism', ( 1951) 'Logical At what Quine has spoken of as the 'core' of the language-cum-theory that truth , ( 1956 ), and Carnap and logical truth', ( 1960)) he has raised doubts embodies what we believe, lie stable sentences including the likes of logical ~bout t_he sens~ of such_n otions as 'true by definition', 'true by convention', truths anchoring and giving structure to the whole. The stability of these is _analytic truth , 'meaning_ postulate' and 'true by semantical rule', opting assured in that if contrary evidence threatens, there are numerous alternative instead for _one monotonic bra?d of ~ruth, a single species admitting no changes that can be made without touching them, all less disruptiv_e than ep1stemolog1cally fundaT?ental d1tferent1ae. In the wake of this revolutionary changes in core sentences, and so to be preferred. At what he descnbes as reassessment, t~e erstwhile sharp distinction between truths of the language 'the edges', there occur the empirically most sensitive eternal sentences. These (such as analytic truths or truths by convention) and truths of the theories have ultimately evolved (certainly in Quine's philosophy, and if he's right we accept (our substantive beliefs) is at least eroded, if it doesn't just go by in the language too) as 'observation categoricals ', generalities that affirI? the boards. To a far fuller extent that one may initially have been inclined crude and primitive observable regularities like 'When water turns cold 1t to suppose, the stud~ of the language we speak and the study of what we turns hard.'. They are as unstable as eternal sentences come, in that contrary purport to know_b egm to look rather like alternative facets of one and the evidence - invariably in the form of a case of true antecedent and false same preoccupation. consequent - provides no tolerable alternatives to their abandonment. XVI INTRODUCTION INTRODUCTION XVII Between these extremes are found most eternal sentences, including, among How is philosophical activity to be seen as relating to the web as a whole, others, law-like generalizations, true as well as false ones, iffy ones as well as to its structure and to its content? firmly entrenched ones. These are among the sentences normally designated Traditionally, philosophers have not conceived their activities as irrelevant 'hypotheses'. Since they include only believed or accepted hypotheses, they to what we should beli~ve. They have not fancied themselves as competitors do not exhaust the class; some hypotheses, at least, are merely entertained, only of the poets, artists and creative writers, concerne? to exploi.t the tried out experimentally, or subject to test. But they do include all currently resources of a certain medium for humanistic purposes. Their self-conceit has accepted hypotheses of all scientific theories we now hold. been as cognitive investigators, engaged in the same line of work as that of As a function of its relative proximity to the edge, the force of a hypothesis the scientists, namely the systematic pursuit of literal truth. Yet in the present is in good part empirical. But as a function of its relative closeness to the day, when physics in particular stands as the monumentally impressive source core, it is partially systematic as well. What empirical consequences such a of knowledge about the world that it does, philosophy can easily seem a sentence has, it has only in concert with other components of the theory in laughable anachronism if its practitioners pretend to another way that which it is embedded. It may be surrendered to relevant refutation-bent dispenses with all that scientific stuff - experiment, measurement, co~trolled experiences, since it does in fact have consequences that deny them. But it observation and theoretical teamwork - in favor of sheer reasomng (or has such consequences only in conjunction with other sentences any of which whatever else). So it must seem to Quine, at any rate. The shift of attention may be sacrificed up in its stead. to language, while a step in the right direction, is far from enough to make The status that Quine 's account thus assigns to hypotheses deviates philosophy respectable again, and to restore both relevance a.nd imp?rtance. pronouncedly from a quondam cornerstone of the empiricist tradition to Linguistically oriented philosophers, as easily as the old-fashioned kmd, ~an which he traces his intellectual lineage. In that tradition, what made be guilty of searching out 'another way' to truth about the world, essaymg hypotheses scientific and differentiated them from metaphysical claims, the same slapstick end run around the natural sciences, with as little (except religious doctrine and pseudo-scientific dogma was precisely the fact that ludicrous pratfalls) to show for the attempt. Perhaps n:any ordina.ry la~guage each scientific hypothesis subtended its own special fund of empirical philosophers of the recent past have cast themselves m this trag1com1c role. consequences, every one of which had then to turn out to be true for the Perhaps many formal-constructionists have too. hypothesis to hold. Failure to be scientific in this sense rendered a hypothesis, Quine complements his linguistic orientation with a commitment to for many a twentieth-century empiricist, not just unscientific but actually a naturalism. This is a commitment to accepting natural science and its methods piece of nonsense. as the one sound route to truth that we have, to transforming philosophical Pierre Duhem had already held to the contrary, insisting that a test of a questions - so far as one recognizes their legitimacy - into factual questions scientific hypothesis must invariably invoke the support of 'collateral' or of the sort that science might address, and to pursuing these transformed 'auxiliary' hypotheses as well, any of which might be abandoned, in the event questions by attempting to develop a program that science might follow in of a negative result, to save the hypothesis under test. Unless science itself seeking answers to them. The philosopher is thus t~ regar~ himself. as .a were empirical nonsense, then the traditional understanding had to go. Like partner rather than a competitor of the scientist. P?1~osop~1cal mq~ir.y is Duhem, Quine remains an empiricist while jettisoning the assignment to to be conducted in the light of the methods of empmcal science, w1thm a empirical hypotheses of their own private funds of empirical consequences. framework established by the best current account of the world that science Unlike Duhem, he does not conclude this from the study of actual scientific offers, and with an eye toward future scientific progress and the avenues it theory, but rather derives it from the theory /language synthesis his may thus open up for further philosophical inves~igation. As philosophy. and abandonment of analyticity brings about. The conventional or systematic its problems undergo transformation along these Imes, they come to constitute features analytic sentences were supposed to encapsulate invade each philosophy 'naturalized'. sentence, tying its fate to that of others in ways that preclude piecemeal, Language remains as central as ever, insofar as th.e bett.er reasons. for sentence-by-sentence empiricism. But empirical import is not lost, as holistic linguistic reorientation of philosophy are fully compatible with naturalism. empiricism remains. Such import is only diffused, broadcast to the entire Some of them, in fact, actually stem from it, such as evidence furnished by system of sentences in which a given hypothesis plays a role, extending both psychology that linguistic habits shape perceptual dispositions and contents. over the limited theory to which the hypothesis is indigenous, and even on The sentences in the web of belief continue on as the primary subject matter, out over the rest of the web in which that theory itself is environed. only those that are members of well-entrenched scientific theories loom much more centrally. What is accepted as scientific truth is seen as lying closer to Naturalism the core than would have been the case if philosophy rather than science had won recognition as the highest available court of appeal. In fact, the Just where, now, does philosophy fit into the web? How do philosophical status of scientific beliefs is more exalted yet. They totally dominate the beliefs, if there are philosophical beliefs, stand vis-a-vis empirical hypotheses. web, in that whatever we believe that is not itself to be found in some accepted XVIII INTRODUCTION INTRODUCTION XIX scientific theory must not be in conflict with what is found there. Beliefs among the many, have been sorely in need of clarification. Given the promise respecting what science pronounces on must follow from science, while those of a shift to firmer ground held out by the program of naturalizing philosophy, that concern what science doesn't deal with are the weaker and the more the exciting prospect presents itself, however, that the philosophical study of readily surrendered to even modest counterevidence precisely because of their language itself can be naturalized. Quine selects the terms, methods an_d lack of scientific credentials. This holds as decisively for philosophical beliefs general framework of behavioristic psychology by which to undertake this as for any others in the web. That philosophical inquiry - like every other naturalization. His reasons for doing so are not hard to identify. inquiry of whatever kind on whatever subject matter - must be carried out Of the three broad kinds of approach in psychology, the mentalistic, the within a framework provided and structured by natural science is thus - and behaviorist and the neurophysiological, only the second and third have appeal trivially - a direct consequence of accepting science as the uniquely reliable, to the empiricist. Mentalism, trading as it does in a whole host of unobservable even if fallible, source of human knowledge. 'traits', 'feelings', 'motives' and 'mental activities', must obviously bid fair to introduce more philosophically troublesome notions than it holds out any promise of dispatching. If the philosopher is looking to science for a solider Physicalism and more reliable context in which to embed his subject, this scarcely looks like the answer. It might even be fair to regard mentalistic psychology as In keeping with ~raditional 'heirachies of the sciences' that place physics at more nearly a part of philosophy than of science, and out of bounds on that the top because its concepts, methods and findings are presupposed by all score. Neurophysiological psychology, on the other hand, while certainly as the remaining sciences, chemistry next because its concepts, methods and empirical as one could want, is rather in its infancy. At least_ this was findings are presupposed by all other sciences except physics, and so on undeniably true of it in the late 1940s and early 1950s when Qume beg~n Quine regards physics as the scientia sine qua non. By dint of the position of his efforts at naturalization of philosophical subject matter. Closer to physics physi~s in t~e heirarchy, no ~cience could be more successful or trustworthy. than either of its competitors, neurophysiology will no doubt one day be the And,_m pomt of _fact'. no science seriously rivals it in these regards. Thus, best choice as an explanatory basis for virtually any behavioral and physical explanat10n 1s best explanation, and whatever can be dealt with at behavior-dependent class of phenomena. It is even best today in th?se the present time only in terms of one of the lesser sciences, awaits further scattered pockets where it is sufficiently developed to support such explanation scientific progress that will ultimately bring it under the aegis of physics itself. at all. But as things currently stand, we seem rather far from the day when Our confidence that such progress is actually in the cards is, as Quine sees neurophysiological theory stands ready to describe and explain the general it, not misplaced. The possibility and eventual likelihood of such progress is run of psychological phenomena. underwritte~ by the fa~t that all spatiotemporal phenomena whatever belong A separate reason for supposing that (these days at least) there is much to the domam of physics. Thus, 'every change of any kind involves a change about the language that is best explained in behavioral terms lies in how in physical microstates ', and it is the final responsibility of physics to each of us learns it. We mature in a community of persons already fluent in comprehend all such changes. the language, and have no choice but to acquire it on the basis of our The hegemony of science within the web of belief, then, is far from even experiences, both of the extralinguistic world around us, and of others' handed. All science is better than any non-science, to be sure, but within linguistic behaviour as they interact with one another and th~t world. 1:he science, not every theory is equally strongly credentialed. The special status situation is a behaviorist's dream come true. We learn the nght behav10r of physics sees to that. This is a fact that has some considerable importance (the correct use of the language) just from experience of the recurrent behavior for the would-be naturalistic philosopher. The reconstruction of one's of others. On the plausible supposition that there is nothing to the language philosophical issue or puzzle in terms of some particular science and its (neither meaning, nor reference, nor truth, for example) but what we learn methods must not be so carried out as to trade in parochial features in learning its use, language is nothing but behavior from top t? ?ottom. of the present state of that science. The issue or puzzle must be reconstructed This is the ground of Quine's confidence that a proper behav10nst1c study in such a way that it promises to survive the eventual recasting as physics of language will omit nothing semantical that could possibly be there in the of what now belongs to the province of the lesser science. first place. Learning a Language Behaviorism There are two sustained accounts with a naturalistic-behavioristic orientation In the era of linguistic philosophy, it is something of a paradox that language to language that Quine attempts, both somewhat factually grounde? and itself has remained shrouded in mystery. Such everyday attributes of linguistic somewhat speculative. One is a fanciful description of a young pre~mg~al entities as 'truth', 'meaning', 'name', 'reference', 'statement' and 'translation', child's gradual acquisition of English, the other a sketch of how a field lmgu1st

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.