ebook img

Perfecting Justice in Rawls, Habermas and Honneth: A Deconstructive Perspective PDF

257 Pages·2013·0.781 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Perfecting Justice in Rawls, Habermas and Honneth: A Deconstructive Perspective

Perfecting Justice in Rawls, Habermas and Honneth Continuum Studies in Political Philosophy Continuum Studies in Political Philosophy presents cutting-edge scholarship in the field of political philosophy. Making available the latest high-quality research from an international range of scholars working on key topics and controversies in political philosophy and political science, this series is an important and stimulating resource for students and academics work- ing in the area. Titles include: The Concept of Justice, Thomas Patrick Burke Morality, Leadership, and Public Policy, Eric Thomas Weber Nozick’s Libertarian Project, Mark D. Friedman Rawls, Dewey, and Constructivism, Eric Thomas Weber Rousseau and Revolution, edited by Holger Ross Lauritsen and Mikkel Thorup Perfecting Justice in Rawls, Habermas and Honneth A Deconstructive Perspective Miriam Bankovsky Continuum Studies in Political Philosophy Continuum International Publishing Group The Tower Building 80 Maiden Lane 11 York Road Suite 704 London SE1 7NX New York NY 10038 www.continuumbooks.com © Miriam Bankovsky 2012 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. Miriam Bankovsky has asserted her right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as Author of this work. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. e-ISBN: 978-1-4411-2696-2 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Bankovsky, Miriam. Perfecting justice in Rawls, Habermas, and Honneth: a deconstructive perspective/ Miriam Bankovsky. p. cm. – (Continuum studies in political philosophy) Includes bibliographical references (p. 227) and index. ISBN 978-1-4411-9541-8 (hardcover) 1. Justice. 2. Rawls, John, 1921-2002--Criticism and interpretation. 3. Habermas, Jürgen–Criticism and interpretation. 4. Honneth, Axel, 1949– Criticism and interpretation. 5. Deconstruction. I. Title. II. Series. JC578.B35 2011 320.01'1--dc23 2011037474 Typeset by Deanta Global Publishing Services, Chennai, India Contents Acknowledgements vi 1. Perfecting Justice: An Art of the Im/Possible 1 Part One: Justice as Fairness: A Project to Pursue 2. Rawls and the Possibility of ‘Ideal Theory’ 41 3. Rawls and the ‘Undecidability’ of the Original Position Procedure 72 Part Two: Rational Consensus: Open to Contestation in Principle 4. Habermas and the Possibility of Popular Sovereignty 101 5. Habermas and the Perfectibility of Deliberative Outcomes 127 Part Three: Perfecting Recognition Relations 6. Honneth and the Possibility of Mutual Recognition 151 7. Honneth and Moral Progress in the Quality of 178 Recognition Relations 8. Im/Possibility and the Cultivation of Deconstructive 203 Civic Attitudes Notes 221 References 227 Index 241 Acknowledgements In preparing this work, I have received support and assistance from a number of friends and colleagues. Instrumental to its completion was the intellectual and personal generosity of Paul Patton and Catherine Malabou. I also received constructive criticism, editorial suggestions, linguistic assi- stance and strategic advice from Alexandra Bourré, Hervé Bruneau, Rosalyn Diprose, Claudia Gutiérrez, Marc Jones, Paula Keating, Christian Lazzeri and the centre SOPHIAPOL, David Owen and Lasse Thomassen. I am also very grateful to Alexandra Day for her professional editorial, proof-reading and indexing work, as well as her flexibility. This assistance was supported by a grant from the Faculty of Humanities and Social Sciences at La Trobe University. Finally, I thank Continuum for committing to this project. On a personal level, I warmly thank all of my family and friends, particu- larly my parents, Barbara and Yanek Bankovsky. I especially thank Sean Bowden, for his love, friendship and support over the years, in different cities and countries, and I dedicate my first book to him. Chapter 1 Perfecting Justice: An Art of the Im/Possible It is true to say, provided it is rightly understood, that successful politics is always ‘the art of the possible’. It is no less true, however, that the possible is very often achieved only by reaching out toward the impossible which lies beyond it. Max Weber, Selections in translation, 1978, p. 89 Framed by a deconstructive approach to justice, this book examines the theories of justice formulated by John Rawls, Jürgen Habermas and Axel Honneth. Each theorist sketches the content of an ‘art of the possible’, a conception of justice that is realistic and practicable, the standard against which public institutions are to be judged. Designed to respond to the problems that individuals face within their collective lives, each theory assigns a concrete content to the normative idea of justice, allowing the needs, interests and claims of distinct individuals to be compared and assessed through the lens of impartiality. Drawing on Jacques Derrida’s account of justice’s demands, this book develops two positions. Its primary assertion is that justice requires, but is not exhausted by, an ‘art of the possible’. On the one hand, a practical commitment to the possibility of constructing justice is necessary, as Rawls’s rhetorical question suggests: ‘If a reasonably just society which subordinates power to its aims is not possible and people are largely amoral, if not incurably cynical and self-centred, one might ask with Immanuel Kant whether it is worthwhile for human beings to live on the earth’ (Rawls, 1996, p. lxii). Simply put, we cannot pursue the worthwhile ideal of justice without first assuming its possibility. On the other hand, justice is not exhausted by the determined content that Rawls, Habermas and Honneth assign to it. No local determination can ever fully reconcile the conflicting demands that Derrida believes our historical concept of justice includes – namely, responsibility for the unique person and impartiality among all. Deconstruction requires the pursuit of the constructive strategies that Rawls, Habermas and Honneth defend while, conversely, drawing attention 2 Perfecting Justice in Rawls, Habermas and Honneth to the pragmatic implications of the impossibility of exhausting justice’s demands in the form of laws, principles and procedures. The second position of this book is that justice sustains its critical function for the present precisely because it is not exhausted by its determination, however realistic and practicable this might be. As Derrida puts it, this position should not produce insensitivity towards injustice but rather responsibility for the concrete effects of determined accounts of justice (Derrida, 2002a, pp. 228–298). Were justice to be determined and achieved once and for all in a present context, it would no longer play the critical role we want it to fulfil. The inadequacy of the ideal and the actual effectively motivates the ongoing effort to seek justice in the present, a fact that is implicitly recognized by Rawls, Habermas and Honneth alike when acknowledging the revisable, transformable and perfectible character of their accounts of justice. Rawls, for example, comes to affirm that outcomes of the original position procedure are necessarily revisable (Rawls, 2001, p. 86). To his account of rational consensus, Habermas adds the procedural condition that participants affirm that their agreement remains open to contestation in principle (1990a, p. 97). In a similar manner, and to protect his method of reconstructive internal critique from the problems of value relativism, Honneth also affirms the existence of a constitutive gap between historical norms and transhistorical standards, committing to a ‘robust’ conception of moral progress (Honneth, 2002, p. 517; 2001, p. 180; Bankovsky and Honneth, 2012, pp. 36–37). From a Derridean point of view, the non-adequation of the idea of justice with its determined forms is not to be regretted but rather affirmed as the very condition that allows us to call on justice to critique the determinations of the present. Consequently, justice is perfectible, a project to be pursued: the ideal of justice motivates the critique of its determined forms. The theories of Rawls, Habermas and Honneth may be loosely referred to as ‘constructive’ in orientation, although each theorist understands this term in different ways.1 Rawls lays stake to it explicitly, explaining the general features of a constructive approach and the manner in which his theory satisfies these (Rawls, 1999a, pp. 340–358). First, its task is practical: its principles are framed to meet a particular social problem; namely, value pluralism within liberal democracies or the existence of reasonable disagreement between people about the values to regulate their public lives. Second, the method begins with the standpoint of the persons implicated by the practical problem, now considered as agents constructing the solution for themselves. Finally, and a consequence of constructivism’s practical character, its content is coherentist. To respond to its practical task, Perfecting Justice: An Art of the Im/Possible 3 it must generate an appropriate public basis for justification, both cohering with and clarifying the considered reflections of real persons about what is just and unjust. These general features of the constructive orientation also apply to the theories of Habermas and Honneth, although each philosopher successively attempts to complicate Rawls’s understanding of the practical problem. Using the term ‘rational reconstruction’ to define his method, Habermas sets out to resolve the practical problem of disagreement about the moral validity of norms of action in specific contexts (Habermas, 1990a, pp. 94– 98). Consequently, his problem is at once broader than Rawls’s, applying to the problem of general disagreement across all contexts and times, while also narrower in attempting to make sense of specific forms of disagreement dividing people in those local contexts – sporting associations, Churches, unions and so on – that Rawls excludes from consideration (see Chapter 4). Habermas discovers a solution in the rational presuppositions that allow interacting agents to lay claim to moral validity, presuppositions by virtue of which norms are intersubjectively judged to be valid or invalid. For Habermas, these presuppositions themselves comprise the public basis for justification, allowing real persons, in all contexts, to submit their particular moral reasons to the rational judgement of others. Preferring the term ‘normative reconstruction’ or ‘reconstructive internal critique’, Honneth deepens Habermas’s account of the problem still further, making visible deep-seated normative expectations that are rarely articulated in Habermas’s language of rational argumentation or in Rawlsian public reason (Honneth, 2008a; 2008b; 2010, p. 57; 2000, p. 36 & p. 59; see also Rössler, 2000, p. 10). The broad practical problem is, on the one hand, defined as the set of all possible experiences that might prevent people from realizing healthy forms of subjectivity. On the other hand, the problem is only visible in specific forms of social pathology, where certain moral expectations embodied in a particular reality are not satisfied by actual norms. Take, for example, a sentiment of low social esteem experienced by public-service parking inspectors whose valuable contributions are often publicly disrespected. It is with such specific forms of social pathology that Honneth begins, ‘tak[ing] the idea of eliminating obstacles as our starting point’ (Honneth, 2001, p. 188). Again, this reconstructive method begins with the standpoint of those implicated by the problem. After reconstructing the norms implied by the duties and rights that are customarily accepted, one then designates as ‘ethical’ only those that ‘enjoy a sort of reciprocal interaction’, evidence of the mutual realization of individual freedom in intersubjective relations (Honneth, 2000, p. 59). The problem is thus

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.