Perception This page intentionally left blank Perception Essays After Frege Charles Travis 1 3 GreatClarendonStreet,Oxford,ox26dp, UnitedKingdom OxfordUniversityPressisadepartmentoftheUniversityofOxford. ItfurtherstheUniversity’sobjectiveofexcellenceinresearch,scholarship, andeducationbypublishingworldwide.Oxfordisaregisteredtrademarkof OxfordUniversityPressintheUKandincertainothercountries #inthisvolumeCharlesTravis2013 Themoralrightsoftheauthorhavebeenasserted FirstEditionpublishedin2013 Impression:1 Allrightsreserved.Nopartofthispublicationmaybereproduced,storedin aretrievalsystem,ortransmitted,inanyformorbyanymeans,withoutthe priorpermissioninwritingofOxfordUniversityPress,orasexpresslypermitted bylaw,bylicenceorundertermsagreedwiththeappropriatereprographics rightsorganization.Enquiriesconcerningreproductionoutsidethescopeofthe aboveshouldbesenttotheRightsDepartment,OxfordUniversityPress,atthe addressabove Youmustnotcirculatethisworkinanyotherform andyoumustimposethissameconditiononanyacquirer BritishLibraryCataloguinginPublicationData Dataavailable ISBN 978–0–19–967654–5 PrintedbytheMPGPrintgroup,UK LinkstothirdpartywebsitesareprovidedbyOxfordingoodfaithand forinformationonly.Oxforddisclaimsanyresponsibilityforthematerials containedinanythirdpartywebsitereferencedinthiswork. Contents Introduction 1 1. TheSilencesoftheSenses 23 2. Frege,FatherofDisjunctivism 59 3. ViewingtheInner 90 4. Reason’sReach 118 5. TheInwardTurn 144 6. AffordingustheWorld 178 7. IsSeeingIntentional? 198 8. UnlockingtheOuterWorld 223 9. DesperatelySeeking(cid:2) 259 10. ThePreserveofThinkers 313 AppendixtoThePreserveofThinkers 352 11. ThatObjectofObscureDesire 364 12. WhileUndertheInfluence 391 Bibliography 413 Index 417 This page intentionally left blank Introduction What appears here is not a monograph but a connected series of essays, each succeedingonelargelyforeseeninwhatprecedesit,andcontinuingoneortwo lines of thought already found there. The essays have two primary concerns. Thefirstistoidentifythemostfundamentaldifferencesbetweenperceptualand cognitive, or conceptual, awareness of the world we inhabit—a difference between awareness of the world, being as it is (or the world’s being the way it is) and awareness of the world being some of the particular ways it is; a difference,too,atleastonthewhole,betweenawarenesswhichisencounter- ing, or witnessing, or being presented with things being as they are, and awareness which is bringing this under, or recognizing it as falling under, one oranothergenerality.Thesecondistoworkouttheramifications,forpercep- tual experience, of that essential publicity, or shareability, of thought, corres- pondingly the publicity of its objects, on which Frege insisted. The first concerncrystallizes, inone way,in issuesas towhether perceptualexperience hasrepresentationalcontent.Thesecondcrystallizes,inoneway,inissuesover a view (or family of views) known as disjunctivism. But to work my way into theseconcerns,Ibeginwithastory. In the spring of 1966 Herbert Feigl came to UCLA to give a talk. Rudolf Carnap,thenprofessoremeritus,wasintheaudience.Feigl’stopicwas‘central state materialism’. The gist of his talk was that, while he was sure central state materialismwascorrect,therewasaresidualproblemhedidnotyetknowhow to deal with. This was the problem of ‘raw feels’, as they were then called. In thediscussionthatfollowedCarnapremarkedthathethoughthehadasolution forFeigl’sproblemofrawfeels.Feigl’sinterestwasaroused.HeaskedCarnap, withsomeexcitement,totellhimthissolution.Carnapreplied,‘Well,Herbert, IthinkthesolutiontoyourproblemofrawfeelsistheÆ-factor’.Feiglappeared still more excited. ‘Tell me, Carnap’, he asked, ‘What is the Æ-factor?’ ‘Well, Herbert’, Carnap answered, ‘You tell me what a raw feel is, and I’ll tell you whattheÆ-factoris’. I was first provoked to write on perception, thirty-three years later, by the casualandwidespreadassumptionthatperceptionhadrepresentationalcontent: 2 INTRODUCTION that perceptual experience(s) represent(s) the world as being ‘a certain way’. Philosophy seemed to have taken a step backwards—a retreat from Austin, as I first thought of it, as I now see it also a retreat from, or simple rejection of, Frege.Whenitcomestoperception,anditsrelationtothought,Fregewasfar ahead of his time (a time, perhaps, yet to come). He has inspired much in the linesofthoughtcontainedhere.Hencethedoubleentendreofatitlehere:essays post-Frege,essaysfollowing(sofarasIcan)inhisfootsteps. In the beginning I did not appreciate that for many who saw perceptual experience as engaged in representing-as, the content thus assigned it was to be Carnap’s Æ-factor. Representational content (harbouring somewhere in perceptual processing or states) was to replace, or just be, Feigl’s raw feels—in current parlance, ‘qualia’. Or anyway, a perceptual experience’s having the ‘phenomenal character’ it did—looking, sounding, and so on, as it did to the experiencer—was to reduce to the (supposed) representational content of something or other (presumably sub-personal). Phenomenal character would atleastthenbenobarriertoFeigl’s‘centralstatematerialism’. I had not foreseen that Feigl’s problem would fascinate so enduringly, or at this late date motivate much of anything. Subsequent essays in this series, notably 5 and10, are aimed, inter alia, at correcting this initial oversight. The second, ‘The Preserve of Thinkers’, undertakes what most needs doing. If, in the case of perceptual experiences, the Æ-factor turns out to be some state of something sub-personal—perhaps a visual system or processing device—if it consistsinthatdevice,oritsissue,representingthingsasbeingthusandso,there is no obvious reason why this should be recognizable to the experiencer, so no reason for a vehicle which makes this representing recognizable to him. One might then think that if there is such representing-as, this is for science to discover. If it is coherent to suppose what belongs to the sub-personal (for example, a visual system or processor) to engage in representing-as, this reflection might smooth the way to accepting that such actually occurs. The bestprophylactictothislineofthoughtwouldbetoshowthattheantecedent of this last conditional is false. The best way to do that would be to show, with as much generality as possible, just what the limits are on engaging in representing-as. Such is what Essay 11 undertakes. It aims to show that (and why)representing-asisanaccomplishmentavailableonlytoathinker.Ifthatis right,thentheÆ-factor,whateverelseitmightturnouttobe,couldnotbethe bearingofrepresentationalcontentbyonethingoranother. AfeltneedforCarnap’sÆ-factorisnottheonlymotiveforholdingpercep- tual experience to indulge in representing things as some way (or to ‘contain’ suchrepresentations).Myinitialconcernwaswithanother,prominentinsome of the most important recent writings on perception and its links to thought. 3 INTRODUCTION Essays 1,4, and 8 are aimed centrally at it. Before elaborating, though, I note that not every representationalist as per above is motivated, or at least clearly motivated, in either of the ways I mention, or certainly in the one way rather than the other. Some are simply unclear as to what, or where, the relevant representingistobe,or,notably,onwhetheritisrepresentingtotheperceiver, orsimplywithinsomeinternalprocessingorstates.Somemaysimplybemoved, wittinglyornot,bytheideathatallthatprocessingmustyieldsomethingother than the perceiver’s surroundings for him to be aware of—a Lockean idea of objects of perception as representing, hence as other than, things in those surroundings. Such themes are also touched on in these essays. Still, I attach specialimportancetothemotiveIamabouttomention. The roleassignedrepresentation in thesecondmotivation Iwill mentionis tooccupyacertainplaceinananswertoaquestionwhichIcallthefundamental questionofperception.Thatquestionis:Howcanperceptualexperiencemakethe worldbear(rationally)fortheperceiveronwhatheistothinkanddo?Theanswer inbroadoutlineis,ofcourse,bymakingrecognizabletotheperceiverwhat,in fact,bearsonquestionsofwhattothinkanddo.Inparticular,ifthequestionis whether to do such-and-such (for instance, to turn left here), then to make recognizable to the perceiver the obtaining of what are in fact determinate reasonstoturn,ornottoturn—forexample,ofthepresenceorabsenceofhis destinationtotheleft,orofaprideoflionsstraightahead. What a perceiver gains, for example, by looking, one would hope, is thus (inter alia) awareness of what stands in rational relations to the proposition that turningleftisthethingforhimtodo—forexample,ofitsbeingsothatthereisa pride of lions to his left. What burden does it put on perception to insist that such gains are what it must provide for? Such depends on what you think a rational relation is, or, again, on just what you think falls within reason’s ambit.Here,Ithink,recentphilosophyhasencouragedsomemythologiesand misperceptions. For which, once again, Frege is the most effective antidote. Hence,again,thepresenttitle. ThekeypointinFregeforpresentpurposeisadistinctionhedrawsbetween what I have called the ‘conceptual’ and the ‘non-conceptual’, though I now favourtheterms‘conceptual’and‘historical’.Wecanthinkofrepresenting-as as a three-place relation: in the first place, a representer (some agent, or some itembywhichherepresents,or,perhaps,someitemwhich,insomeotherway, bearscontent);inthesecondplace,whatisrepresentedassomethingorother; inthethirdplace,awayforwhatoccupiesthesecondplacetoberepresentedas being. So thinking, the distinction I have in mind here is between what occupiesthethirdplace(the‘conceptual’), andwhat occupiesthe second(the ‘historical’).
Description: