OXFORD university press Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6dp “ a department of the University of Oxford, To the memory of Louk Hulsman and education by scholarship, Oxford New York Audd^d Cape Town Dares Salaam Hong Kong Karachi With offices in SomhKora, Sw.ue,]a„d Haitad Turkey IW ST 0/Oxford Univmily Pros ui me UK and m certam other countries ^ Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York © Vincenzo Ruggiero 2010 T^e moral ri^te of the author have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) U01P0000148 with the permission of OPSI and the Queen’s Printer for Scotland First pubhshed 2010 Jnd vT* book in any other binding or cover and you must impose the same condition on any acquirer Bntish Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Ruggiero, Vincenzo. Penal^olitionism:acelebration/Vincenzo Ruggiero. T ^jT^P^cndon studies in criminology) references and indS^ ISBN 978-0-19-957844-3 (hardback) justice, AdnSS^of-Ewope^' f ^ imprisonment-Europe. 3. Criminal HV9344.A5R84 2010 ' 364.6*8094—dc22 2010014008 Typeset by ^ Limited, A Macmillan Company Pnu»du.d.eUKbyd.eMPGBuobGro„pfB<Liua„dKi„g-,Ly„u ISBN 978-0-19-957844-3 13579 10 8642 X Contents 6. Social Christians and Mercy Equality and Solidarity 1 Forging One’s Religion ^ The Monarch’s Mercy Introduction Mysterious Iniquity Liberating Theology Pietas 124 Abolitionism has been described as a flag under which ships of 7. Abolitionist Praxis 129 varying sizes sail carrying varying quantities of explosives. Whether The Judge and the Bum-Bailiff ^ ^ ^ accompanied by deflagration or not, abolitionism posits that the The Unfinished and Action Research ^3^ criminal justice system as a whole constitutes a social problem The Abolitionist Stance in itself and that the only adequate solution to this problem is its Law and Conflict total suppression (De Folter 1986). In order to stave off images 147 and sounds of explosions, however, it may be more appropriate 8. Mutual Aid and Cordiality to suggest that abolitionism is not merely a programme, but also Law and Authority .an approach, a perspective, a methodology, and most of all a way ^ 155 of seeing. Surely, there is an abolitionist stance in the proposition Tightly Knit Societies 158 that the state centralized administration of penal justice should be The Business of Pain replaced by decentralized forms of autonomous conflict regula No More Prisons ^ tion. Echoes of abolitionism are also heard when critics warn that, Cumulative Anticipation ^ if we want to reform the penal system, we have to start a process of collective conversion away from the traditional and conven 9. Participation, Conciliation, and Mourning yjS tional grammar that characterizes it. Abolitionism, finally, may Participatory Disputes also be a source of inspiration for those who want to do away The Tyranny of Public Opinion ^ ^ ^ with concepts such as ‘seriousness’, ‘dangerousness’, ‘culpability’, arid with the very dichotomy underlying the distinction between Knowledge, Proximity, and Dialogue . ‘good’ and ‘evil’. But we need a larger conceptual vault if we are Victims to grasp the different components of abolitionism as a school of Making Amends 18^ thought in its widest sense. It has been noticed, in this respect, 189 Shaming and Peace that a ‘fully-fledged abolitionist theory, which encompasses all 193 the characteristics of the different abolitionist approaches to the 10. Conclusion criminal justice system does not exist’ (ibid. 40). This book is the 199 Against Antinomian Thinking outcome of a similar awareness, and while steering far away from Surrogate Victims of the Law the purpose of providing a unifying, totalizing, theory of abo litionism, it examines the multiple frameworks and backdrops, The Disease of the Hangman within philosophy, social theory, politics, or theology, wherein Abolitionism as Public Sociology 2Q5 abolitionism can be located. One has only but to rejoice at the impossibility of precisely pinning down ‘the’ theoretical or politi References 211 cal source of abolitionism; fortunately, its multifaceted nature is Index inclusive rather than exclusive, allowing anyone endowed with a 227 2 Introduction Introduction 3 critical spirit to detect in it at least a minor aspect of their own its members, and by sending them to prison, it breaks them up, thought. crushes them, physically eliminates them. Then According to one of the most representative figures of this multi faceted school of thought, abofitionism is a manifestation of The prison eliminates them by ‘freeing’ them and sending them back to society; the state in which they come out insures that society will eliminate the general human urge to do away with and to struggle against those them once again, sending them to prison. Attica is a machine for elimina phenomena or institutions of a social, political or religious nature that at a tion, a form of prodigious stomach, a kidney that consumes, destroys, given time are considered to be unjust, wrong or unfair. (Bianchi 1991: 9) breaks up and then rejects, and that consumes in order to eliminate what The ‘general human urge’ in the definition provided by Bianchi is it has aheady eliminated. (Simon 1991:27) the same urge that gave strength to the ancestors of contemporary Against this strategy of elimination, the primary challenge for abolitionists, namely the women and men who fought against penal abolitionists may well be ‘to construct a political language slavery, and later the campaigners who battled, and continue to and theoretical discourse that disarticulates crime from punish do so, for the abolition of the death penalty. But the battle also ment’ (Davis 2008: 3). However, in order to be effective, such continues on other fronts. As Anton Chekhov (2007: 23) argued strategy will have to be accompanied by alternative conceptu often the correctional measures which have replaced the death alizations of crime, critical analyses of law, and radical thinking penalty still continue to bear its most significant aspect. One does around the very nature, function, and philosophy of punish not have to visit Siberia, as he did, to realize that imprisonment ment. Perhaps, only a similar multi-pronged theoretical effort may avoid the pitfalls that Bianchi (1986,1991) identifies in the very history of abolition. For example, abolitionists of torture to remove an offender from the normal milieu; and a person commit were in favour of prison construction. European philanthropists ting a serious crime is considered to be dead just as much as in the times when the death penalty held sway ... the death penalty has not been and benefactors studied the prison system of the United States, sSsMtie^^*^ merely clothed in another form less repugnant to human admiring its humanity: ‘the gentle eye of the new middle class no longer accepted confrontation with visible cruelty, and preferred the indoor cruelty of imprisonment’ (Bianchi 1986: 149). But Following Chekhov’s observation, imprisonment appears also the expected benefits of imprisonment failed to materialize, as as a logical extension and a new form of slavery. In this respect inmates were not turned into law-abiding, productive, or respect see the hmpid analysis of Angela Da^ys, where prisons are seen as able citizens. nieans for the management of former slaves and as power mecha- msms which tend to re-create conditions of slavery. The very construction and type of building used for imprisonment pro duced an annual output of wretched and destitute people, criminalised One has a ^eater chance of going to jail or prison if one is a young black and stigmatised, who apart from a few exceptions, were no longer fit for man than if one is actually a law-breaker. While most imprisoned young normal civil life. (Ibid. 150) black men may have broken a law, it is the fact that they are young black men rather than the fact that they are law-breakers which brings them As de Tocqueville (1956) noted, offenders remained among into contact with the criminal justice system. (Davis 1998:105) humans, but they lost their rights to humanity; people fled them as impure, and even those who beheved in their innocence aban ^gela Davis (1971, 2003) fights against our ‘racial democracy’ doned them. Once released, they could go in peace, with their life for an abolition democracy’, in a situation in which ‘the idolatry generously left to them, but a life worse than death. of liberty co-exists so promiscuously and comfortably with the It took abolitionists almost three generations to recover and privation of freedom’ (Mendieta 2007a: 293). muster the energy for new initiatives. A propitious chance pre Abolitionism also fights against the ‘curious mechanism of cir sented itself, towards the end of the nineteen^ century, with the cular elimination’ identified by Foucault during his visit to Attica emergence of the medical model, when psychiatry and psychology where he noted that society excludes certain specific types of seemed to offer an alternative not only to imprisonment, but to 4 Introduction Introduction 5 all other forms of punishment. Prisons could be turned into thera- Aristotle’s thought is just the first coordinate that may help us peutic communities. Howevei; this model of treatment entailed the localize abolitionism, but we need many more. While in Aristotle it supjpression of prisoner’s rights and the correspondent expansion is inequality that hampers the flourishing of societies, in Rousseau of the power of scientists of the mind. (1973) it is competition that, in generating deception and violence, In the old days before the medical model, a prison sentence was a prison prevents humans from leading a good life. Competition contrib sentence, and the inmate knew his fate exactly. In many countries though, utes to the loss of feelings of security among humans, and this the enthusiasm for prison as a therapeutic community had produced the leads to a decHne in public morals, hence the growth of artificial mdetermmate sentence, making it possible for a delinquent who behaved means of behaviour control. Abolitionists, here, would be as anti- badly in prison to face the possibility of a much longer stay in prison than Hobbesian as Rousseau himself, in that where Hobbes indicates the seriousness of his crime warranted. (Bianchi 1986: 150) that human anxiety and strife may be overcome through a social contract giving shape to a state, Rousseau advocates the return During the course of the twentieth century, after the initial enthusi- to pre-competitive, natural human interactions. This is the second asm for what appeared to be a process of decarceration, aboHtion- coordinate that may help locate the abolitionist position. ists realized that alternatives to custody were destined to become A third coordinate may be found in Hegel’s (1952) distrust for alternatives to freedom. the development of commodity exchange, which according to Abohtionism merely addressed to imprisonment may produce the German philosopher destroyed a form of ethical totality as it such unmtended effects. As de Haan (1990) has argued, mild penal must have existed under natural conditions or in ancient Greece. climates are, at least in part, the result of the judiciary’s deeply Individuals, isolated and competitive, become excluded from the rooted conviction that long-term imprisonment produces damag- public sphere and learn to lose feelings of obligation to others, mg effects. And if bad conscience makes it relatively hard to justify thus becoming increasingly atomized (Taylor 1979). The resulting punishment at all, a politics of bad conscience should be pursued social pathology or ‘misdevelopment’ leads to the shaping of buff and maintained, making it just as difficult to justify the existence ered selves, where individuals mark their area of intimacy and dele of prisons. Such politics, however, need not be polarized on pun gate to the authority the solution of social problems (Taylor 2007). ishment, but include alternative views and conceptualizations of Once they have appointed the guardians of morality, individuals crime and the criminal justice system as a whole. The chapters that can then devote themselves to their own material interests, and follow present and discuss such conceptualizations as elaborated while allowing pimitive notions to grow among them, success will by abolitionists. be increasingly celebrated and failure increasingly stigmatized. H the activist ancestors of abolitionism are the men and women There is nothing utopian in attempts to redress ‘remediable who fought against slavery and the death penalty, their philosophi injustices’: abolitionists do not pursue perfect justice; rather, they cal ancestors are harder to identify with precision. For now, I would aim at enhancing justice. Their focus on social interactions rather ask I’eaders to be content with a general, preliminary characteriza than institutions, on precise settings in which people five rather tion. Abolitionists, I would submit, are grounded in a variety of than official norms and extraneous professionals, locates them in social philosophies which are primarily concerned with discussing a specific political and philosophical tradition. According to a dis processes of social development that can be viewed as pathological tinction suggested by Amartya Sen (2009), there are contractarian or as ‘imsdevelopments’ (Honneth 2007). Among these philoso approaches and comparative approaches to the idea of justice. The phies are those expressmg the view that societies should support a former establish general, universal, principles of justice and are rich plurality of activities, each valuable in its own right, and that concerned with setting up ‘just institutions’. For such institutions each person should be treated as an end, not as a mere means to to function, total compliance of people’s behaviour is required. the ends of others. This Aristotelian view would deny ‘that a soci The latter assess the different ways in which people lead their lives, ety can be flourishing as a whole when some members are doing actually behave and interact. A contractarian approach is described extremely badly’ (Nussbaum 2000a: 106). by Sen as ‘transcendental institutionalism’, in that it searches for Introduction 7 6 Introduction How did abolitionist views take shape? Where in social theory, the ideal institutions capable of forging a perfectly just society. By pohtics, and philosophy are their foundations? contrast, a comparative approach is led by the search for social As already alluded to, abolitionism is not only a strategy, or a set arrangements that satisfy people in their concrete collective life. of demands, aimed at the reduction (or suppression) of custody, it When people across the world agitate for more global justice—and I is also a perspective, a philosophy, an approach which challenges emphasise here the comparative word ‘more’—they are not clamouring conventional definitions of crime. Chapter 2 discusses the contri for some kind of‘minimal humanitarianism’. Nor are they agitating for a bution of abolitionist thinking to the analysis of key definitional ‘perfectly just’ world society, but merely for the elimination of some out issues. A seminal article by Louk Hulsman, published m Contem rageously unjust arrangements to enhance global justice. (Ibid. 26) porary Crises in 1986, is the starting point, and his arguments are supplemented by more recent analyses provided by other aboli Comparison entails information, which in turn presupposes prox tionists. This chapter includes some suggestions about the phdo- imity to the actors involved in the process of forging ideas of jus sophical underpinnings of the abolitionist argument, its radical tice. Abolitionists lean towards this type of approach. anti-Platonism, namely its rejection of conventional distinrtions Some forms of human suffering may be unavoidable, and per between good and evil and its implicit critique of Plato’s notion of haps cannot be remedied in some particular place or at some par virtue as knowledge. In the chapter it is also suggested that more ticular time. Correspondingly, however, there are also forms of suitable philosophical fathers for aboUtionism would be Aristotle suffering that are needless at particular times and places. Accord (1977), for his distinction between justice and equity, but particu ing to Gouldner (1975), it is the sociologist’s job to give special larly Baruch Spinoza (1959), for his heretical view that nothing attention to the latter. Penal suffering is avoidable, particularly can be bad or wrong, as everything is an aspect of the infinity of if its ineffectiveness can be proved, and the prisoners’ standpoint deserves to be heard not because they have any special virtue and God or nature. , j , • u* * Juridical equality may be described as everybodys right to not because they alone live in a world of suffering. mobilize state institutions for the protection and safeguard of their A sociology of the underdog is justified because, and to the extent that, well-being. In this perspective, it is, therefore, the right to inutual his suffering is less likely to be known and because—by the very reason of coercion. Disrespect for the liberty of others amounts to the demal his being imderdog—^the extent and character of his suffering are likely to of their freedom. The state intervenes to deny that denial ^d contain much that is avoidable. (Ibid. 37) restore the initial situation. Coercion is therefore legitimate in t at it denies an act which has denied the freedom of others (Ferrajoli Similarly, Nils Christie often reminds us that all he wants to do is to 2007). Abolitionists would retort that such arguments mi^t only reduce the amount of suffering in the world: ‘I have never known be suitable for societies in which equal access to the law is com someone who wants to increase it’ {personal communication). plemented with equal access to resources. Their critique of the law Christie may have been particularly fortunate in his encounters, and the criminal justice system presented in Chapter 3 is addressed but his views and those of other abolitionists sit comfortably with to the iniquitous societies in which we five (Holterman and van a variety of insights found in sociology, politics, and philosophy. Maarseveen 1980). This chapter also examines the critical responses Abolitionism is a counter-idea put forward by cultural workers provided by abolitionism to other key assumptions, namely that who feel that ‘the dehvery of pain, to whom, and for what, contains the law addresses individual rather than collective actors, and an endless line of deep moral questions’. Philosophers, Christie that liabihty and non-Habihty can be scientifically assessed. Here, says, should address these questions, even those who, faced by the the proximity of abolitionist arguments to those put forward by complexity of problems, may conclude that not action but think conflict theorists is highlighted, although it is also emphasized that ing is the only available possibility. ‘That may not be the worst abolitionism develops its own tenets in an original manner. For, alternative when the other option is delivery of pain’ (Christie example, while conflict theorists hmit themselves to the crmque of 1993: 184-5). Penal Abolitionism discusses the counter-ideas, the the criminal justice system as an expression of antagonistic values thinking, the origin, philosophy, and achievements of abolitionism. 8 Introduction Introduction 9 and interests operating from above, abolitionists re-appropriate Analyses adopting a mixed approach are finally presented, par the very notion of conflict and turn it into a critical tool to be uti- ticularly the concept of ‘carceral social zone’, which designates ted from below. The chapter, therefore, focuses on the key notion the marginalized, the underemployed, the occasional workers, the that conflicts are hijacked by the criminal justice system, in the petty property offenders, in other words all the excluded who con sense that they are taken away from the parties directly involved. stitute the main human receptacle of contemporary penality. The aa of hijacking by professionals entails a specific construc The infliction of punishment might be justified if it contributed tion of reality hingemg on an incident, narrowly defined in time to the maximization of happiness rather than the maximization of and space, whereby the individual is separated from the context in pain. Hence the need for any theorizing on punishment to consider which the action takes place. Presenting the abolitionist critique of its social consequences. Those who defend institutional coercion legal professionalism, echoes of some insights offered by phenome in the form of punishment may advocate rehabilitative treatment, nology and ethnomethodology are noted, particularly the idea that may value its general or individual deterrent effect or its function the ineanmg of crime cannot be divorced from the environment in of incapacitation aimed at prolific offenders. Chapter 5 presents which It arises. The chapter ends with the juxtaposition between the abolitionist arguments against such philosophies and their what abolitionists term the ‘industrialized’ but also sacred nature practical outcomes. In Mathiesen’s view, for example, prison has of current justice systems and the natural, substantial, type of jus no defence, not even when, in a moderate version of penal retri tice they advocate. bution, offences are said to possess a ‘punishment value’ that can Among the most critical traits characterizing abolitionist theo be translated into a specific amount of ‘time’. Mathiesen argues ries and prac^ces are those concerned with the nature, function, that time is only measurable subjectively, and that the perception and philosophy of punishment. Chapter 4 discusses such concerns of its entity depends on one’s proximity to those serving a prison drawing an analytical map of views and cultures around impris- sentence. The chapter then addresses the debate around the alleged onment, in order to identify the theoretical enemies and allies of evolution of punishment towards a gradual leniency, and proposes abolitionism. It sets off with Kant’s assertion that crime makes a definition of the exact nature of what abolitionists describe as those committing it the property of the state, whose right to pun- penal suffering. A section titled ‘The Manufacture of Handicaps’ ish IS therefore a categorical imperative. Kant’s rejection of the attempts to identify the real effects of imprisonment on the bodies Idea that imprisonment should lead to the rehabilitation of offend and minds of those incarcerated. Returning to the analytical map ers IS discussed, along with his notion that renouncing retribution drawn in the previous chaptei; it is then noted that abolitionists amounts to unpractical compassion. If in Kant the sovereign has are more concerned with institutional rather than material aspects a right to punish, m Hegel it is offenders who have a right to be of imprisonment, as their preoccupations are mainly addressed to punished. The chapter moves on to analyse the different forms of the immoral and destructive components of the legal infliction of wrong considered by Hegel and his view that crime and pun pain. The chapter concludes with an analysis of what Nils Christie ishment are aspects of a single category or whole. The analytical sees as potential developments in the economy which might trigger map drawn in this chapter includes the critique levelled by Marx change, produce solidarity, and ultimately lead to social arrange at Kant and Hegel and the concept of punishment as vengeance ments more conducive to abolitionist ideas. posited by Durkheim. Here, the intellectual vicinity of Durkheim As remarked above, abohtionism does not possess one single and Nietzsche is noted, while the theory of penal evolution in the theoretical or political source of inspiration, but a composite back former is critiqued. There are other approaches to the analysis of drop from which, wittingly or otherwise, it draws its arguments prison and its functions. This chapter schematically divides them and proposals for action. The following three chapters, therefore, into mstitutional’ and ‘material’ approaches, namely views of aim to locate in more detail three major figures of the aboHtion- ^prisonment emphasizing its regulatory funaion in relation to ist school of thought in specific traditions. Chapter 6 provides an the labour market and the productive process, on the one hand account of the intellectual biography of Louk Hulsman, and links and those emphasizing its mere retributive functions, on the other' his views with some crucial passages in the Bible where mercy 10 Introduction Introduction 11 IS advocated while judgement and retribution are rejected. The keep in mind the workers to whom it was addressed. Chapter 8 Gospels of Mark and Luke and the Epistles of Paul seem to provide examines the system of thought of Nils Christie, drawing a con an apposite theological underpinning for Hulsman’s abolitionism, stant parallel between his abolitionism and anarchist theories w ich^n also be assimilated to Saint Francis’s ecumenism and his of law and authority. The similarities are astounding: Christie’s view that thieves are not those who steal, but those who do not critique of legal professionafism echoes the anarchist arguments give enough to the needy. Radical theology or the theology of liber against the proliferation of laws, while his appreciation of con ation also provide significant sources of inspiration, and the chap flict as a resource brings to mind the anarchist idea that problems ter connects such sources with abolitionist arguments provided within communities can only be resolved if those involved pos by some giants of Western literature. With Bakunin’s anarchism sess sufficient autonomous resources to do so. One of Christie’s Hulsman shares the belief that the realization of freedom requires arguments is that communities and groups, irrespective of their that political action be conducted religiously. In some pages of dimension, may find abolitionist experimentation possible only if Marx, Engels, Tolstoy, and Hugo an echo is felt of Hulsman’s con the interactions within them are highly frequent and intense. In cepts of redemption of punishment, self-government, mercy, and this sense, he expresses the purest of anarchist notions, namely that pietes Hulsman’s system of thought, in brief, is shown to display a a better social life is experienced when communities develop social nigh degree of syncretism. feelings and, particularly, a collective sense of justice that grows An equal if not a higher degree of syncretism shows the intel until it becomes a habit. This chapter, in brief, locates Christie’s lectual trajectory of Thomas Mathiesen, on whose work Chapter 7 abolitionism alongside anarchist hbertarian analyses of law and concentrates. His initial materialist approach is discussed alone society, in total harmony with Emma Goldman’s views on the arbi with hs arguments for a plurafistic, interdisciplinary, sociology of trariness of punishment, Errico Malatesta’s argument that all penal law. The writings of Marx and Engels constitute an ideal back reforms will be unable to erase the principle of revenge inscribed in ground for an understanding of Mathiesen’s work, which on the prison systems, and Proudhon’s idea that principles of justice are other hand draws on a number of other theoretical sources. The constructed through experiences of interaction. locus on offenders and prisons, and on social movements tradi Attracted by natural law, anarchists believed in prevention and tionally excluded from orthodox notions of class struggle, makes fraternal treatment of offenders, and looked to examples of self- Mathiesen s stance an implicit critique of classical Marxism. The help and forms of primitive restorative justice for the potential c apter exanunes his strategy of action revolving around the idea developments of new ways of dealing with undesirable behaviour. of the unfinished , which also distances him from orthodox revolu Chapter 9 is devoted to the debate around restorative justice, per tionary ideas. What constitutes the originality of Mathiesen’s work haps the major practical outcome, in terms of poficy, with which IS the coalescence of research, action, and theorizing that charac abolitionist analysis can be associated. Setting off with Durkheim’s terizes his entire careei; as an academic as well as an activist. The notion of ‘restitutive sanction’, the chapter defines the character chapter, therefore, gives an account of his activity in KROM an istics of participatory disputes, and critiques the tyranny of public orgamzation for penal reform in which he has been involved for a opinion. Knowledge, proximity, and dialogue are pinpointed as ve^ long time, and of his relentless engagement in action research. key variables informing alternative ways of dealing with problem Action IS inherent in the research method adopted by Mathiesen, atic situations. It is widely acknowledged that abolitionism, while and those researched are the prime subjects involved in research elaborating non-conventional analyses of crime, legal systems, and as well as m action. His radical analysis, therefore, is regarded as punishment, has simultaneously made a significant contribution in a tool which constantly translates knowledge about conflict into placing the victim at the centre of the criminal justice system. This collective praxis for those producing it. final chapter discusses the controversies surrounding the debate on I • ^ work. Nils Christie stands in favour of simplicity and intel the victims of crime and all those forms of mediation and repara ligibility. He says that when we write we should keep our favourite tion intended to ‘make amends’. A brief conclusion, after summa aunt m mind, like Kropotkin said that anarchist literature had to rizing the content of the book and through some supplementary 12 Introduction theoretical observations, suggests that abohtionism, pursuing its 2 own ideas of justice, is well equipped to join the current tendency towards a public sociology. Authors are normally allowed autobiographical notes. Here is Crime as Trouble mine. A few years ago, during the course of a job interview, I was asked why m a previous book, I had opted for a subtitle such as says m Anti-Criminology’. The colleague posing this question, of course, was personally offended by my scepticism about the originahty, independence, or separateness of our field of knowl Are crimes exceptional events? Louk Hulsman’s reply to this rhe edge. I was also asked the reason for my interest in international torical question takes the form of an excursus into the criminal classical hterature and why, in another book, I used that fiterature justice system as a ‘special’ set of procedures addressed to a ‘not so to make criminological points. When I rephed that great hterature special’ category of individuals. We are accustomed, he argues, to can help miiunologists understand the dilemmas around law, social regarding the criminal justice system as a rational apparatus spe w er, and crime, I was told that the opposite was more likely to be cifically devised to respond to crime and to control or neutralize the case. In other words, John Smith and Gennaro Esposito (ficti its effects. We are also accustomed to interpreting crimes as excep tious names of two colleagues sitting on the interview panel) were tional events, ‘events which differ to an important extent from telling me that Dostoevsky, Thomas Mann, Cervantes, Manzoni, other events which are not defined as criminal’ (Hulsman 1986: Baudelaire, Jack London, Victor Hugo, Bertold Brecht, and others 63). In conventional perceptions, criminal conduct is at odds with had more to learn from them, John and Gennaro, than the other the average conduct in that it deviates from the type of interactions way around. This book is dedicated to colleagues who do not take supposedly estabfished by the majority. Such deviation, statistically personal offence when faced with criminological scepticism, and exceptional, is thus deemed to trigger the special responses offered who believe that the Bible, Marx, Kropotkin, Plato, Hegel, Kant by official institutions: special events justify the special nature of Nietzsche, and many others can teach us how to make sense and the reaction against them. radically alter the categories, often derivative, plagiarized, or non According to abolitionist analysis, conducts classified as crimi sensical, that crowd the ancillary criminological enterprise. nal are only a small proportion of a variety of similar conducts which escape criminalization. On the one hand, therefore, only certain types of events are selected as specific, undeniable, self- evident representatives of what we understand as crime. On the other hand, the events selected are brought together in a discreet category, as if they constituted a homogeneous group of conducts. ‘Within the concept of criminaHty a broad range of situations are finked together. Most of these, howevei; have separate properties and no common denominator’ (ibid. 65). What do violence within the family and street violence have in common? Do shoplifting, drug selling, and armed robbery belong to the same rubric of behaviour? What makes dangerous driving similar to fencing? And political violence to pollution? Neither the motivation of those involved nor the techniques required, let alone the consequences of those specific conducts, display a precise set of common compo nents. If we are led to analyse them by referring such conducts to a common logical and moral framework it is because the framework 14 Crime as Trouble Anti-Platonism 15 we adopt is inspired by the criminal justice system: ‘All these events ‘radical anti-Platonism’. The ideal conversation partner, in this have in common is that the criminal justice system is authorised to case, is indeed Plato. take action against them’ (ibid. 65). It has been suggested that our ideas of action and responsibifity This is not to deny that human interactions may cause consid are closer to those of the ancient Greeks than we usually suppose, erable degrees of suffering to those involved: abolitionism would and that ‘if we can come to understand their ethical concepts, we only question why some types of suffering mobilize the interven shall recognise them in ourselves’ (Williams 1993:10). It has also tion of institutional agencies while others do not. Moreover, in an been noted that philosophical analyses of crime can be traced back imaginary scale of personal hardship, the distress caused by some at least to Plato, ‘thereafter becoming a subject of theological con interactions of a criminal nature would not score particularly cern throughout the middle ages’, subsequently engaging‘the legal high when compared to those of a quotidian, apparently prosaic, ponderings of Beccaria and Bentham and the scientific discourse of nature. ‘Matrimonial difficulties, difficulties between parents and the early biological positivists’ (Arrigo and Williams 2006: 4-5). children, serious difficulties at work and housing problems will, In Plato, the distinction between good and evil amounts to the as a rule, be experienced as more serious.’ In brief, there is noth difference between those who ‘are conquerors of their desire for ing that intrinsically distinguishes, for those directly involved, pleasure and feelings of anger’ and those who ‘are conquered by criminal events from a variety of other unpleasant events. Most them’. Injustice, and we may assume evil, result from the mastery episodes causing hardship are normally dealt with informally by of the soul by anger, fear, pleasure, pain, envy, and desire, whether the individuals affected, at times with the mediatory participa they lead to any actual damage of not (Plato 1970: 374). The tion of people or groups belonging to the community in which basic human faults leading to painful consequences are therefore such episodes occur. Many conducts that generate serious harm anger and fear, but also the obtuse pursuit of pleasures and desires, do not elicit responses from the criminal justice system, while which Plato juxtaposes to hope and opinion as attempts to reveal those involved in problematic situations mostly attempt to find the truth. solutions within the context in which they arise: the family, the group of friends or neighbours, the workplace. All this means, Hulsman concludes, ‘that there is no “ontological reality” of Appetites crime’ (ibid. 66). Of our unnecessary pleasures and appetites there are some lawless ones, I think, which probably are to be found in us all, but which, when con Anti-Platonism trolled by the laws and the better desires in alliance with reason, can in As Nussbaum (2000a) argues, we have strong reasons to address some men be altogether got rid of, or so nearly so that only a few weak remain, while in others the remnant is stronger and more numerous. (Plato difficult contemporary issues by engaging in conversation with important texts in the history of philosophy, and for each issue we 1937: 338) are required to identify suitable conversation partners. Hulsman’s For Plato, lawless appetites emerge in sleep, when the rest of the critique of conventional ways of conceptualizing crime is a direct soul, the rational, gentle and dominant part, slumbers, allowing attack on the very distinction between good and evil. His state the ‘beastly and savage part, replete with food and wine’ to take ment that there is no ontological reality in crime not only entails a over. In sleep instincts are satisfied and individuals are released polemical stance against positivist criminology, it also challenges from ‘all sense of shame and all reason’; they become ‘ready for assumptions around harmful and harmless behaviour. Moreover, any foul deed of blood’. ‘There exists in every one of us, even in the notion that crime is not an exceptional event ultimately pits some reputed most respectable, a terrible, fierce and lawless brood Hulsman against a whole Western philosophical tradition con of desires, which it seems are revealed in our sleep’ (ibid. 339). cerned with drawing boundaries between the ‘good’ and the ‘bad’ Our appetites, howevei; are of three types, reflecting the tripar life. I term this challenge, which is inherent in abolitionist analysis. tite character of our soul. The first is concerned with learning, the 16 Crime as Trouble Anti-Platonism 17 second with anger, and the third, owing to its manifold forms, can If we had lived in that small town at that time, we would probably have not be designated by any one distinctive name. This unnameable found it ridiculous to call in an expert of the mind to explain why the type of appetite is distinctive for its intensity, and can be addressed killer had killed. Ridiculous because we all knew why he killed. After all, to food, drink, love, and money. ‘There being, then, three kinds of we would not have been surprised, and we would have agreed among pleasure, the pleasure of that part of the soul whereby we learn is friends that this was exactly what we all might have expected all along. sweetest, and the life of the man in whom that part dominates is (Nils Christie, personal communication) the most pleasurable’ (ibid. 372). The difference between the experience and perception of the Learning is therefore the only antidote to lawless appetites, two murders resides in the'nature and amount of information while ignorance is a kind of emptiness of the soul, hampering the the residents share about one another. So many people live in a experience of wisdom and virtue. middle-sized modern town that it is impossible to know them all. In addition, life is organized in ways that only allow us to hold Those who have no experience of wisdom and virtue but are ever devoted a superficial or segmented knowledge of other beings. We have a to feastings and that sort of thing are swept downward, it seems, and back narrow basis for predicting behaviour outside the specific group again to the centre, and so sway and roam to and fro throughout their to which we belong. lives. But they have never transcended all this and turned their eyes to the Another example comes from the Norwegian valleys, where the true upper region ... nor ever been really filled with real things, nor ever traditional institutional figure of the lensmann is still operative. tasted stable and pure pleasure. But with eyes ever bent upon the earth A local sheriff of sort, the lensmann performs a variety of civil and heads bowed down over their tables, they feast like cattle, grazing and copulating, ever greedy for more of these delights. And in their greed tasks and his/her ability to function is dependent upon the support kicking and butting one another with horns and hooves of iron they slay received by his/her fellow citizens. The lensmann may direct auc one another in stateless avidity, because they are vainly striving to satisfy tions, help mothers get money from absent fathers, and deal with with things that are not real the unreal and incontinent part of their souls crime. When Christie interviewed one such institutional figure, he (Ibid. 392-3) was told that there was no crime in the district. But during the course of the interview several things happened that testified to Plato s criminals are not involved in problematic interactions, the contrary. they are just incontinent people unable to dominate the ‘many The telephone rang, a lady had lost her purse: the lensmann asked his headed beast lying in their soul. It is the law that can restrain the assistant to drive down to the close-by cafe; the purse was found and brutish part of our nature, by repressing the ‘foul and base things brought back to the lady. So was the young man who was using the purse. that enslave’ our gentle nature to the wild. There is, here, an onto He happened to be the lady’s son. A report came in on breaking and enter logical reality in crime, which is also described as a tyrant acting ing into a store of weapons. The lensmann jumped into his cat; drove far upon the judgement and self-control of offenders, while the law is up into the mountains in the direction of the store, met a car high up there, seen as the only possible response to this inbuilt tyranny. Law is stopped the car, found Ole drunk as usual, with a carload of guns he had knowledge, crime is ignorance. Let us see how abolitionism over stolen just to irritate his father. He brought Ole home and took the guns turns this axiom. to a safer depot. What a cliff-hanger story lost for the mass-media! Heli A murder occurs in a town inhabited by some 300,000 people, copters and anti-terrorist police might have been engaged in the crime- and the alleged murderer is a university lecturer. A few days earfier, hunt of the century. Now, it was Ole. An old story of misery and family the lecturer has delivered a public speech and no one in the audi quarrels. (Christie 1982: 73-4) ence noticed anything unusual in the speech and in the speaker. These cases show that law, not crime, is ignorance, namely lack The event is incomprehensible and the investigators feel the neces of familiarity with the events described as criminal. In this sense, sity to entrust a team of psychiatrists with the explanation of the abolitionists, while drastically distancing themselves from Platon mystery. Let us now imagine another murder occurring 200 years ism, appear to embrace some Aristotehan concepts around law before in a small town. and justice. According to Aristotle (1977), the students of ethics