ebook img

Peckness of Edge Posets PDF

0.26 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Peckness of Edge Posets

PECKNESS OF EDGE POSETS DAVIDHEMMINGER,AARONLANDESMAN,ZIJIAN YAO Abstract. ForanygradedposetP,wedefineanewgradedposet,E(P),whoseelementsaretheedges 5 in the Hasse diagram of P. For any group, G, acting on the boolean algebra, Bn, we conjecture that 1 E(Bn/G) is Peck. We prove that the conjecture holds for “common cover transitive” actions. We give 0 some infinite families of common cover transitive actions and show that the common cover transitive 2 actionsareclosedunderdirectandsemidirectproducts. n a J 9 1. Introduction 1 Let P be a finite graded poset of rank n. In this paper we study the structure of the edges in the ] HassediagramofP. Tothis end,wedefineanendofunctorEonthecategoryoffinite gradedposetswith O rank-preserving morphisms as follows C . Definition 1.1. For P the category of graded posets, define the functor of edges E: P → P as follows. h Given P ∈ P, the elements of the graded poset E(P) are pairs (x,y) where x,y ∈ P, x ≤ y, and t P a rk(y) = rk(x)+1. Define the covering relation ⋖E on E(P) by (x,y)⋖E(x′,y′) if x⋖P x′ and y⋖P y′. m Then define the relation ≤E on E(P) to be the transitive closure of ⋖E. [ LetQ be a finite gradedposet ofrank n. Givena morphismf: P →Q, define E(f): E(P)→E(Q) by E(f)(x,y)=(f(x),f(y)). 1 v We will show that E(P) is a well-defined graded poset in Section 3. Note that an edge in the Hasse 0 diagram of P can be identified with a pair (x,y) ∈ P ×P such that x⋖y, and the edges in the Hasse 4 5 diagram are in bijection with elements (x,y) ∈ E(P) via this identification. With this in mind, we will 4 frequently refer to E(P) as the edge poset of P. 0 . Example 1.2. We give an example of an edge poset in Figure 1. Note that it is important we declare 1 0 the relation ≤E to be the transitive closure of ⋖E. If instead we defined a relation ≤E′ on E(P) by 5 (x,y) ≤ (a,b) if x ≤ a,y ≤ b, then E(P) would not necessarily be a graded poset. In Figure 1 we give 1 an example of a poset P for which E(P) is not graded with the relation ≤E′. In Figure 1 it is clear that : E(P) is a graded poset, with rk(x,y) = rk(x), but the Hasse diagram on the right represents a poset v i which does not have a grading. X WeobservethatwhenP hasanicestructure,E(P)commonlyhasanicestructureaswell. Inparticular r a we examine the boolean algebra of rank n, denoted B , which is defined to be the poset whose elements n are subsets of {1,...,n} with the relation given by containment, namely, for all x,y ∈ B , x≤ y if x is n a subset of y. ThroughoutthepaperwesaythatagroupGactsonP ifitactsontheelementsofP andtheactionis order-preservingandrank-preserving,thatis,forallg ∈Gwehavex≤y ⇔gx≤gy andrk(gx)=rk(x). By Theorem 2.6 and the fact that B is unitary peck, if G is any action on B , then B /G is Peck. We n n n conjecture the following. Conjecture 1.3. If G⊆Aut(B ), then E(B /G) is Peck. n n We prove this conjecture holds whenever the group action of G on B has the following property. n Definition 1.4. A group action of G on P is common cover transitive (CCT) if whenever x,y,z ∈ P such that x⋖z, y⋖z, and y ∈Gx there exists some g ∈Stab(z) such that g·x=y. Theorem 1.5. If a group action of G on B is CCT, then E(B /G) is Peck. n n 1 2 DAVIDHEMMINGER,AARONLANDESMAN,ZIJIANYAO 7 (5,7) (6,7) (5,7) (6,7) 5 6 (3,5) (4,6) (3,5) (4,6) 3 4 (1,3) (2,3) (2,4) (1,3) (2,3) (2,4) 1 2 (0,1) (0,2) (0,1) (0,2) 0 P E(P) E(P) with relation ≤E′ (not graded) Figure 1. Examples of E A large number of groupactions onB have the CCT property. We first provethat some basic group n actions on B are CCT. Throughout the paper we let a subgroup G⊆S act on B by letting it act on n n n the elements within subsets of [n]:={1,...,n}, i.e. g·x={g·i: i ∈x} for all g ∈G, x ∈B . We also n embed the dihedral group D into S by letting it act as rotations and reflections on the vertices of an 2n n n-gon. Proposition 1.6. The following actions are CCT. (1) The action of S on B , n n (2) The action of D on B , 2p p (3) The action of D on B , 4p 2p where p is prime. Wefurthershowthatcovertransitivityispreservedundersemidirectproducts,allowingustodescribe several large families of CCT actions in Subsection 4.2. Proposition 1.7. Let G⊆Aut(P), H⊳G, K ⊂G such that G=H⋊K. Suppose that the action of H is on P is CCT and the action of K on P/H is CCT. Then the action of G on P is CCT. Thepaperisorganizedasfollows. InSection2wecoverthe necessarybackgroundforposetsandPeck posets. In Section 3 we show that E is well-defined and prove Theorem 1.5 regarding CCT actions along with various other nice properties of E. Section 4 contains the proofs of Propositions 1.6 and 1.7 as well as some examples of families of group actions shown to be CCT by these propositions. In Section 5, we obtain a very different proof of [5, Theorem 1.1], in the case that r=1. 2. Background In this section we review necessary background for this paper. A graded poset P is a poset with a rank function rk: P →Z satisfying the following conditions. ≥0 (1) If x∈P and x⋖y, then rk(x)+1=rk(y), (2) If x<y then rk(x)<rk(y) We denote the ith rank of P by P = {x ∈ P: rk(x) = i}. Additionally, if for all x ∈ P, we have i 0≤rk(x)≤n, and there exists x,y with rk(x)=0,rk(y)=n, we say that P is a gradedposetof rank n. PECKNESS OF EDGE POSETS 3 Throughout the paper we write x≤ y to denote that x is less than or equal to y under the relation P defined on the poset P. When the poset is clear we omit the P and simply write x≤y. Let P,Q ∈ P be two finite graded posets. A map f: P → Q is a morphism from P to Q if it is rank-preserving and order preserving, in other words, for all x,y ∈P, x≤ y implies f(x)≤ f(y) and P Q rk(x) = rk(f(x)). We say that f is injective/surjective/bijective if it is an injection/surjection/bijection from P to Q as sets. Remark 2.1. Notethatwedonotrequiretheimplicationthatf(x)≤ f(y)impliesx≤ y inorderfor Q P f to be a morphism. In particular this means that a bijective morphism f need not be an isomorphism, since it will not necessarily have a two-sided inverse. In what follows, let P be a poset of rank n, and write p =|P |. If we have i i p ≤p ≤...≤p ≥p ≥...≥p 0 1 k k+1 n for some 0 ≤ k ≤ n, then P is rank-unimodal. If p = p for all 1 ≤ i ≤ n, then P is rank-symmetric. i n−i An antichain inP is aset ofelements inP thatarepairwiseincomparable. If no antichainin P is larger than the largest rank of P, then P is Sperner. More generally, P is k-Sperner if no union of k disjoint antichains in P is larger than the union of the largestk ranks of P. We say that P is strongly Sperner if it is k-Sperner for all 1≤k ≤n. Definition 2.2. P is Peck if P is rank-symmetric, rank-unimodal, and strongly Sperner. LetV(P)andV(P )bethecomplexvectorspaceswithbases{x:x∈P}and{x:x∈P }respectively. i i NotethatwewillfrequentlyabusenotationandwriteP andP forV(P)andV(P )whenwhatwemean i i is clear from context. In determining whether P is Peck, it is often useful to consider certain linear transformations on V(P). Definition 2.3. A linear map U: V(P) → V(P) is an order-raising operator if U(V(P )) = 0 and for n all 0≤i≤n−1, x∈P we have i U(x)= c y X x,y y⋗x for some constants c ∈ C. We say that U is the Lefschetz map if all c on the right hand side are x,y x,y equal to 1. We then have the following well-known characterizationof Peck posets. Lemma 2.4 ([7],Lemma1.1). P is Peck if and only if there exists an order-raising operator U such that for all 0≤i< n, the map Un−2i: V(P )→V(P ) is an isomorphism. 2 i n−i Definition 2.5. Ifthe LefschetzmapsatisfiestheconditionforU inLemma2.4,thenP is unitary Peck. NotethatagroupGactsonP iftheactiondefinesanembeddingG֒→Aut(P). Wedefinethequotient poset P/G to be the poset whose elements are the orbits of G, with the relation O ≤ O′ if there exist x∈O, x′ ∈O′ such that x≤ x′. We will use the following result in the paper. P Theorem 2.6 ([8], Theorem 1). If P is unitary Peck and G⊆Aut(P), then P/G is Peck. 3. The Edge Poset In Subsection 3.1 we show that E as described in Definition 1.1 is well-defined and prove some useful propertiesofE. InSubsection3.2weprovethatEsendsself-dualposetstoself-dualposets. InSubsection 3.3 we give several equivalent definitions for CCT actions, and Subsection 3.4 is devoted to the proof of Theorem 1.5. 4 DAVIDHEMMINGER,AARONLANDESMAN,ZIJIANYAO 3.1. Functoriality of E and Group Actions. FirstweshowthatEiswell-definedinLemmas3.1,3.2, and 3.3. After showing that E is well-defined we then define a natural G action on E(P) and define a surjection E(P)/G→E(P/G) that will be important for the proof of Theorem 1.5. When the poset P is clear, we will use ≤E and ⋖E to refer to ≤E(P) and ⋖E(P). Similarly, in Subsec- tion 3.4, we define posets H(Bn), and will use ≤H and ⋖H in place of ≤H(Bn) and ⋖H(Bn). Lemma 3.1. The relation ≤E defines a partial order on E(P). Proof. We have that (x,y) ≤E (x,y) and that ≤E is transitive by definition. It remains to be shown that ≤E is antisymmetric. Suppose (x,y) ≤E (x′,y′) and (x′,y′) ≤E (x,y). Then x ≤P x′ ≤P x and y ≤ y′ ≤ y, so x=x′ and y =y′ by antisymmetry of ≤ , hence (x,y)=(x′,y′). (cid:3) P P P Lemma 3.2. For P a graded poset, the object E(P) is a graded poset. Proof. To show E(P) is graded, we must show that (x,y)⋖E(x′,y′) =⇒ rk(x,y)+1= rk(x′,y′). This fact follows immediately from the definition of ⋖E and the definition rkE(x,y)=rkP(x). (cid:3) Lemma 3.3. Let f: P →Q be a morphism of finitegraded posets, and define a map E(f): E(P)→E(Q) by E(f)(x,y)=(f(x),f(y)) for all (x,y)∈E(P). Then (1) E(f) is a morphism of finite graded posets (2) E(idP)=idE(P) (3) If g: Q→R is a morphism of finite graded posets, then E(g◦f)=E(g)◦E(f). Proof. Part (1) First, E(f) is rank-preserving,since for all (x,y)∈E(P) we have rkE(x,y)=rkP(x)=rkP(f(x))=rkE(E(f)(x,y)). Suppose (x,y)⋖E(x′,y′). Then x⋖P x′, y⋖P y′, and since f is order-preserving,it follows that f(x)⋖P f(x′), f(y)⋖P f(y′). Hence E(f)(x,y) ⋖E E(f)(x′,y′). Since ≤E is the transitive closure of ⋖E, we similarly obtain E(f) is order-preservingand hence a morphism of finite graded posets. Part (2) This is trivial. Part (3) For all (x,y)∈E(P) we have E(g◦f)(x,y)=(g(f(x)),g(f(y)))=(E(g)◦E(f))(x,y). (cid:3) Remark 3.4. ByLemmas 3.1,3.2,and3.3,the edgeposetconstructionEdefines anendofunctoronthe category of finite graded posets with rank-preserving morphisms. Given a group action of G on P, we can now easily define a natural group action of G on E(P) using Lemma 3.3. For all g ∈ G we have that multiplication by g is an automorphism of P, so it follows that E(g) is an automorphism of E(P) and furthermore that this gives a well-defined group action by Lemma 3.3. Definition 3.5. Given a G-action on P, define a G-action on E(P) by g·(x,y)=E(g)(x,y)=(gx,gy). We then have a well-defined quotient poset E(P)/G. It is natural to ask whether the operation of quotienting out by G commutes with E, that is, whether E(P/G) ∼= E(P)/G. Unfortunately the two posets are rarely isomorphic, but there is always a surjection E(P)/G → E(P/G), and this surjection is also an injection precisely when the G-action on P is CCT, as will be shown in Lemma 3.14. Proposition 3.6. The map q: E(P)/G → E(P/G) defined by q(G(x,y)) = (Gx,Gy) is a surjective morphism. Proof. Note that q is well defined because if (x′,y′)=g(x,y)=(g·x,g·y) for some g ∈G, then x′ ∈Gx and y′ ∈Gy. Clearly q is rank-preservingand surjective, so it suffices to show that q is order-preserving. Suppose that G(x,y)⋖E(P)/GG(w,z). Then there exist some (x0,y0)∈G(x,y), (w0,z0)∈G(w,z) such that x0⋖P w0 andy0⋖P z0. We then havethat(Gx,Gy)⋖E(P/G)(Gw,Gz) by definition. Since ≤E(P/G) is the transitive closure of ⋖E(P/G), q is order-preserving. (cid:3) PECKNESS OF EDGE POSETS 5 3.2. The Opposite Functor and Self Dual Posets. Next, we introduce the notion of a dual poset, given by applying the opposite functor, op, to a graded poset. We will show that op commutes with E. This willimply that E(P) is self-dual if P is, which, in turn, willimply that E(B /G) is self-dual for any n group action of G on B . n Definition 3.7. Let P be the category of graded posets and let op: P → P be the opposite functor, defined on posets as follows. For P a poset, the elements of Pop are the same as those of P with order relation ≤Pop defined by x ≤Pop y ⇔ x ≥P y. Induced maps on morphisms are given as follows: for P,Q gradedposets with f: P →Q, then fop: Pop →Qop is defined by fop(x)=f(x). The poset Pop is called the dual poset of P. A poset P is self-dual if there is an isomorphism of posets P ∼=Pop. Remark 3.8. Note that it is easy to check op: P → P is indeed a covariant functor. In more abstract terms, ifwe view P as a category,Pop is the opposite category. Additionally, opasdefined in this wayis actuallyaendofunctoronthe categoryofallfiniteposets,whichrestrictstoafunctoronthesubcategory of graded posets. Lemma 3.9. The functor op: P→P commutes with the functor E: P→P. That is, E(Pop)∼=E(P)op. Proof. ObservethatE(Pop)iscanonicallyisomorphictoE(P)op,asgivenbythemorphismF: E(Pop)→ E(P)op,(x,y) 7→ (x,y). The inverse to F is given by G: E(P)op → E(Pop),(x,y) 7→ (x,y). These maps are welldefined because E(P)op andE(Pop) are the same as sets, and it follows from the definitions that these are both morphisms of graded posets, and so F defines an isomorphism. (cid:3) Proposition 3.10. If P is a self-dual poset, then E(P) is also self-dual. Proof. Since P is self-dual, there is an isomorphism f: P → Pop. By functoriality of E, as shown in Lemma 3.3, we obtainthat E(f): E(P)→E(Pop) is an isomorphism. By Lemma 3.9, there is an isomor- phism E(Pop) ∼= E(P)op. Then, letting F: E(Pop) → E(P)op,(x,y) 7→ (x,y) be the same isomorphism defined in the proof of Lemma 3.9, the composition F ◦E(f): E(P) → E(P)op defines an isomorphism, so E(P) is self-dual. (cid:3) Example 3.11. While E(P) is commonly Peck when P is Peck, E(P) need not be Peck in general. Furthermore, adding the condition that P be self-dual does not change this fact. In Figure 3.2 we give anexampleofaposetP suchthatP isunitaryPeckandself-dual,butE(P) isnotrank-unimodal,hence not Peck. (4,6) (5,6) (5,7) 6 7 4 5 (2,4) (3,5) 2 3 (0,2) (0,3) (1,3) 0 1 P E(P) Figure 2. P is self-dual and unitary Peck, but E(P) is not Peck Remark 3.12. Wheneverthereisanactionψ: G×[n]→[n],weobtainaninducedactionφ:G×B → n B defined by n φ(g,{x ,...,x })={ψ(g,x ),...,ψ(g,x )}. 1 k 1 k 6 DAVIDHEMMINGER,AARONLANDESMAN,ZIJIANYAO It is easy to see that any action φ: G×B → B arises in this way. That is, for any action φ of G on n n B there existsanactionψ ofGon[n]suchthat φ(g,{x ,...,x })={ψ(g,x ),...,ψ(g,x )}. This fact, n 1 k 1 k that all actions on B are induced by actions on [n] follows from the more general fact about atomistic n lattices. Recall, L is an atomistic lattice if there exists a minimum element of L and a subset of L called “atoms” such that any other element of L can be expressed as a join of atoms. Then, for L an atomistic lattice, any poset automorphism f: L → L restricts to an automorphism of the atoms of L, and f is uniquelydeterminedbythisrestrictiontoatoms. InthecaseofB ,theatomsarepreciselythesingletons, n and hence can be identified with [n]. Whenever an actionψ of G on [n] is given, we refer to the action φ defined above as the induced action on B . n Corollary 3.13. For any action φ: G × B → B , both E(B /G) and E(B )/G are self-dual. In n n n n particular, they are both rank-symmetric. Proof. ByRemark3.12,anyactionφ: G×B →B isinducedbyanactionψ: G×[n]→[n]. Usingthis, n n observethatforanyφ,theposetB /Gisself-dual,asthereisanisomorphismf: B /G→(B /G)op,G· n n n x7→G·([n]\x). ThismapiswelldefinedonGorbitsbecauseeveryactiononB isinducedbyanaction n on [n]. Then, by Proposition 3.10, it follows that E(B /G) is self-dual. n It only remains to prove that E(B )/G is self-dual. However, from Proposition 3.10, E(B ) is self- n n dual, with the isomorphism given by E(f): E(B ) → E(Bop) ∼= E(B )op, that is, the map sending a n n n (x,y) 7→ ([n] \ y,[n] \ x). Once again, since the action on B is induced by an action on [n], this n isomorphism descends to an isomorphism E(f)G: E(B )/G → (E(B )/G)op, and so E(B )/G is self- n n n dual. (cid:3) 3.3. Equivalent Definitions of CCT Actions. We next give four equivalent definitions of CCT ac- tions. The equivalence of (1) and (2) in the following Lemma 3.14 uses the notion of dual posets, while the equivalence of (1),(3), and (4) use the fact that q: E(P)/G→E(P/G),G(x,y)7→(Gx,Gy) is always a surjection. Lemma 3.14. Let G be a group acting on a graded poset P. The following are equivalent: (1) The action of G on P is CCT. (2) Whenever x⋖y,x⋖z, and y ∈Gz, there exists some g ∈Stab(x) with gx=z. (3) The map q: E(P)/G → E(P/G) defined by q(G(x,y)) = (Gx,Gy) is a bijective morphism (but not necessarily an isomorphism). (4) For all i there is an equality |(E(P)/G) |=|(E(P/G)) |. i i Proof. First, we show (1) ⇔ (2). There is an isomorphism f: B → Bop,x 7→ [n]\x. This defines a n n bijection between triples (x,y,z) with x⋖z,y ⋖z with x ∈ Gy, and triples (a,b,c) with c⋖a,c⋖b with a ∈ Gb, given by (x,y,z) 7→ (f(x),f(y),f(z)). Furthermore, some g ∈ G satisfies g ∈ Stab(z) and gx=y, if and only if it also satisfies g ∈Stab(f(z)) and g·f(x)=f(y). If an action is CCT, all triples (x,y,z)satisfythese properties,andcondition(2)saysalltriples(a,b,c)satisfythese properties. So,the above shows that (1) is equivalent to (2). Second, we show (1) ⇔ (3). Observe that q is a bijection exactly when there do not exist distinct orbits G(x,y) 6= G(x′,y′) with x′ ∈ Gx, y′ ∈ Gy. Fix (x,y),(x′,y′) ∈ E(P) such that x′ ∈ Gx and y′ ∈Gy. Pick a g ∈G such that g·y′ =y. Then (g·x′,y)∈G(x′,y′), so G(x,y)=G(x′,y′) if and only if there exists some g′ ∈G such that g′·x=g·x′ and g′·y =y. Hence q is a bijection if and only if the G action is CCT. Finally,wecheck(3)⇔(4). Againusing Proposition3.6,the morphismq is alwayssurjective. Sincea morphismisalwaysrankpreserving,itmustmap(E(P)/G) surjectivelyonto(E(P/G)) . However,since i i the posets are finite, this surjection is a bijection if and only if the sets have the same cardinality. (cid:3) Remark 3.15. While q is a bijection if and only if the action of G on P is CCT, it is not true that if the action of G on P is CCT, then q is an isomorphism. For example, take G = D ⊂ S acting by 20 10 reflections androtationson{1,2,...,10}and considerthe induced actiononB . FromProposition1.6, 10 this actionisCCT.However,considerx={2,4},y={1,2,4},a={2,4,7},b={2,4,6,7}. Thenwemay observe (x,y),(a,b)∈E(B10) and Gx<Ga,Gy <Gb, so (Gx,Gy) <E (Ga,Gb). However, it is not true that G(x,y)<E G(a,b). PECKNESS OF EDGE POSETS 7 3.4. Proof of Theorem 1.5. In this section we prove Theorem 1.5, which we recall here: Theorem 1.5. If a group action of G on B is CCT, then E(B /G) is Peck. n n The proof is largely based on the following Lemma. Lemma 3.16. Let P,Q two graded posets with a morphism f: P → Q that is a bijection (but not necessarily an isomorphism). If P is Peck, then Q is Peck. Proof. Let rk(P) = rk(Q) = n. Since P is Peck there exists an order-raising operator U such that Un−2i: V(P )→V(P )isanisomorphism. Sincef isaposetmorphism,itfollowsthatthemapf◦U◦ i n−i f−1 isanorder-raisingoperatoronQ. Wethenhavethatf◦Un−2i◦f−1 = f ◦U ◦f−1 n−2i : V(Q )→ i (cid:0) (cid:1) V(Q ) is an isomorphism since Un−2i: V(P )→V(P ) is an isomorphism and f is a bijection. n−i i n−i (cid:3) By Lemma 3.16 and Proposition 3.6, in order to prove Theorem 1.5 it suffices to prove that E(B )/G n is Peck. One way to do this is to provethat E(B ) is unitary Peck and then apply Theorem2.6. In fact, n this approach generalizes to an arbitrary poset P. Theorem 3.17. If the action of G on P is CCT and E(P) is unitary Peck, then E(P/G) is Peck. Proof. Since the G-actionisCCT,there isabijectionq: E(P)/G→E(P/G)by Lemma3.14. Since E(P) isunitaryPeckwehavethatE(P)/G isPeckbyTheorem2.6,henceE(P/G) isPeckby Lemma3.16. (cid:3) WeprovethatE(B )isunitaryPeckforn>2in[4,Section8],butunfortunatelytheproofistechnical n andcomputational. NotethatbyTheorem3.17,thisimmediatelyimpliesTheorem1.5. Fortunatelythere is a cleaner – albeit less direct – route to proving Theorem 1.5. In order to avoid showing that E(B ) n is unitary Peck, we define a graded poset H(B ) for all n such that H(B ) is easily seen to be unitary n n Peck in Corollary 3.26. Furthermore, we define H(B ) such that a group action of G on B induces a n n groupactiononH(B )(Lemma3.23)andthereisalwaysabijectivemorphismf: H(B )/G→E(B )/G n n n (Lemma 3.24). By the above discussion, Theorem 1.5 readily follows. Definition 3.18. For P a graded poset, define the graded poset H(P) as follows. Let the elements (x,y)∈H(P)be pairs(x,y)∈P×P suchthatx⋖y. Define (x,y)⋖H(x′,y′)ifx⋖x′,y⋖y′ andx′ 6=y. Then, define ≤H to be the transitive closure of ⋖H, and define rkH(x,y)=rkP(x). Example 3.19. WegiveanexampleoftheposetH(B )inFigure3. ObservethatH(B )canbewritten 3 3 as a disjoint union of three copies of B . This is a single case of the more generalphenomenon provenin 2 Proposition 3.25. Remark 3.20. Note that by definition (x,y)⋖H (x′,y′) precisely when (x,y)⋖E (x′,y′) and x′ 6= y, hence (x,y)⋖H (x′,y′) ⇒ (x,y)⋖E (x′,y′). In other words, H(P) has the same elements as E(P) but with a weaker partial order. Lemma 3.21. For P a graded poset, the object H(P), as defined in Definition 3.18, is a graded poset. Proof. This follows immediately from Remark 3.20 and the fact that E(P) is graded. (cid:3) Remark 3.22. While E: P → P is a functor, H is not a functor. In particular, it is not possible to define H(f) for f a morphism. This is illustrated in Figure 4. For example, suppose we took f: P →Q defined by f(1) = 1,f(2) = f(3) = 2,f(4) = 3. It is easy to see that there is no possible morphism H(f): H(P)→H(Q) because there are no morphisms H(P)→H(Q). Given an action of a group G on P, we define an action of G on H(P) as we did for E(P) by again defining g·(x,y) = (gx,gy) for all (x,y) ∈ P. We will then have a well-defined quotient poset H(P)/G with the same elements as E(P)/G. Lemma 3.23. The automorphism defined by g·(x,y) = (gx,gy) for all g ∈ G, (x,y) ∈ H(P) yields a well-defined group action of G on H(P). 8 DAVIDHEMMINGER,AARONLANDESMAN,ZIJIANYAO {1,2,3} {1,2} {1,3} {2,3} {1} {2} {3} ∅ B 3 ({2,3},{1,2,3}) ({1,3},{1,2,3}) ({1,2},{1,2,3}) ({2},{1,2}) ({3},{1,3}) ({1},{1,2}) ({3},{2,3}) ({1},{1,3}) ({2},{2,3}) (∅,{1}) (∅,{2}) (∅,{3}) H(B ) 3 Figure 3. B and H(B ) 3 3 4 3 3 4 2 2 3 2 1 2 1 1 1 P Q H(P) H(Q) Figure 4. Proof. Letg ∈G. Since ≤H is the transitiveclosureof⋖H it suffices toshowthat forall(x,y),(x′,y′)∈ H(P) we have (x,y) ⋖H (x′,y′) ⇔ g(x,y) ⋖H g(x′,y′). Since g is an automorphism of P, we have x ≤ x′ ⇔ gx ≤ gx′, y ≤ y′ ⇔ gy ≤ gy′, and y 6= x′ ⇔ gy 6= gx′, so the result follows from the P P P P definition of ≤H. (cid:3) Lemma 3.24. The map f: H(P)/G → E(P)/G defined by G(x,y) 7→ G(x,y) is a bijective morphism for any group action of G on P. Proof. The elements of H(P)/G,E(P)/G are the same by definition, so it suffices to show that f is a morphism. Since f is clearlyrank-preserving,itsuffices to show f is order-preserving. This is immediate from Remark 3.20. (cid:3) PECKNESS OF EDGE POSETS 9 The remaining step in the proof of Theorem 1.5 is to show that H(B ) is unitary Peck, which we do n by generalizing Example 3.19 and showing that H(B ) is isomorphic to the disjoint union of boolean n algebras. Proposition 3.25. H(B ) is isomorphic to n disjoint copies of B . n n−1 Proof. Let the n disjoint copies of B be labeled B(i) , 1≤i≤n, with the elements of B(i) labeled n−1 n−1 n−1 x(i), x⊆{1,...,n−1}. We will show that the map n f: H(B )−→ B(i) n [ n−1 i=1 (x,x∪i)7−→x(i) is an isomorphism. Suppose we have (x,y),(x′,y′)∈H(Bn) with (x,y)⋖H(x′,y′). Let j ∈[n] such that y′ = y∪{j}, and let i ∈ [n] such that x′ = x∪{i}. If i 6= j, then x′ = y, contradicting the assumption that (x,y)⋖H(x′,y′). Thus x′ =x∪{i} and y′ =y∪{i} for some i∈[n]. Converselywecaneasilycheckthatifi6∈y,then(x,y)⋖H(x∪{i},y∪{i}). Itfollowsthatforallsubsets w ⊂ [n] such that |w| = 1, there is an isomorphism from the subposet of elements {(x,y): y\x = w} to B defined by (x,y) 7→ (x\w,y \w). Furthermore if y \x 6= y′ \x′, then (x,y) and (x′,y′) are n−1 incomparable,sothesesubposetsindexedbywarepairwisedisjoint,andH(B )isisomorphictoncopies n of B . (cid:3) n Corollary 3.26. H(B ) is unitary Peck for all n≥0. n Proof. This follows immediately from Proposition 3.25 and the fact that B is unitary Peck. Indeed, n−1 B is shown to be unitary Peck, in [8, Theorem 2a] by noting that B = (B )k and that B is clearly n k 1 1 unitary Peck. (cid:3) Corollary 3.27. H(B )/G is Peck for any subgroup G⊂Aut(B ). n n Proof. This follows from Corollary 3.26 and Theorem 2.6. (cid:3) The next corollary will not be particularly relevant in proving Theorem 1.5, but let us note it as an aside. Corollary 3.28. Both E(B ) and H(B ) have symmetric chain decompositions (SCD). n n Proof. H(B ) has an SCD by Proposition 3.25 and the fact that B has an SCD, as shown in [3]. By n n−1 Lemma 3.24 there is a bijective morphism f: H(B )→E(B ), and since a bijective morphism takes an n n SCD to an SCD it follows that E(B ) has an SCD. (cid:3) n Corollary 3.29. E(B )/G is Peck for any subgroup G⊂Aut(B ). n n Proof. ByCorollary3.27,H(B )/GisPeck. ByLemma3.24,themapf: H(B )/G→E(B )/G,G(x,y)7→ n n n G(x,y) is a bijective morphism. Then, by Lemma 3.16, it follows that E(B )/G is Peck. (cid:3) n We now deduce Theorem 1.5. Proof of Theorem 1.5. By Corollary 3.29, E(B )/G is Peck for any group action of G on B . Since n n the G-action is CCT, there is a bijective morphism from E(B )/G to E(B /G) by Lemma 3.14. Hence n n E(B /G) is Peck by Lemma 3.16. (cid:3) n NotethatwehavealsodevelopedseveralgeneralizationsofE,forwhichmanysimilarresultshold. For more information, see [[4], Subsection 3.3] 10 DAVIDHEMMINGER,AARONLANDESMAN,ZIJIANYAO 4. Common Cover Transitive Actions In this section, we develop the theory of CCT actions φ where G is a group, P is a poset, and φ:G×P →P isanaction. RecallDefinition1.4,thatφisCCTifwheneverx,y,z ∈P,x⋖z,y⋖z,x∈Gy then there exists g ∈ Stab(z) with gx = y. We show that the CCT property is closed under semidirect products,intheappropriatesense. FromProposition1.6,whichwillbeproveninSubsubsection4.2.4,the actionofS onB andtheactionofcertaindihedralgroupsareCCT.We canthenusethese asbuilding n n blocks to construct other CCT groups. In particular, we shall show in this section that automorphism groups of rooted trees are CCT. Example 4.1. Two rather trivialexamples ofCCT actions are φ: S ×B →B and ψ: G×B →B n n n n n where G is arbitrary, φ is the action induced by S permuting the elements of [n], and ψ is the trivial n action. In the formercase, E(B /S )is simply a chainwith npoints, andsois E(B )/S , since all(x,y) n n n n are identified under the S action. In the latter case,since Gacts trivially by φ, both E(B /G)∼=E(B ) n n n and E(B )/G∼=E(B ). So again, ψ is CCT. n n 4.1. Preservation Under Semidirect Products. Lemma 4.2. Let G⊆Aut(P), H⊳G, K ⊂G such that G=H⋊K. We then have a well defined group action K×P/H →P/H,(k,Hx)7→H(k·x). Proof. Note that if x,x′ ∈Hx, we have x′ =h·x for some h∈H. Since H is normalin G, we have that for all k ∈G there exists h′ ∈H so that khk−1 =h′. So k·x′ =kh·x=k(k−1h′k)·x=h′·(k·x) Hence k·x and k·x′ are in the same H-orbit, so we have a well-defined group action of K on P/H defined by k·Hx=H(k·x). (cid:3) Recall Proposition 1.7, as stated in the introduction, which says that the CCT property is preserved undersemidirectproducts. WewilluseProposition1.7toconstructmoreexamplesofCCTgroupactions, in particular using it to give a simple proofs that CCT actions are preserved under direct products and wreath products. Proposition 1.7. Let G⊆Aut(P), H⊳G, K ⊂G such that G=H⋊K. Suppose that the action of H is on P is CCT and the action of K on P/H is CCT. Then the action of G on P is CCT. Proof. Since G=H⋊K, every element g ∈G can be written uniquely as a product hk for some h∈H, k ∈ K. Let x,y,z ∈ P such that x⋖z, y ⋖z and such that there exists some h k ∈ G such that 0 0 h k ·x=y. It suffices to show that there exists some g ∈Stab(z) such that g·x=y. 0 0 TheorbitsHx,Hy,Hz ∈P/H satisfyHx⋖Hz,Hy⋖Hz suchthatk ·Hx=Hy,sosincethe action 0 of K on P/H is CCT there exists some k ∈ K such that k ∈ Stab(Hz) and k ·Hx = Hy. It follows 1 1 1 that there exists some h ∈H such that h k h ∈Stab(z) and h k h ·x∈Hy. 1 1 1 0 1 1 0 Write x′ = h k h ·x. Since the group action of G must be order-preserving by definition, we have 1 1 0 that x′ ⋖z. We already had that y⋖z and x′ ∈ Hy, hence there exists some h ∈ Stab(z) such that 2 h ·x′ = y by the fact that the action of H on P is CCT. Then we have that h h k h ·x= h ·x′ =y 2 2 1 1 0 2 and h h k h ·z =h ·z =z, as desired. (cid:3) 2 1 1 0 2 Proposition 4.3. For φ: G×P →P,ψ: H ×Q→Q two CCT actions, then the direct product φ×ψ: (G×H)×(P ×Q)→(P ×Q),(g,h)·(x,y)7→(gx,hy) is also CCT. Proof. FirstnotethatifeitherGorH actstrivially,thenitcanbeeasilycheckedthattheactionofG×H is CCT. Next, observe that G×H can be viewed as the semidirect product of (G×{e})⋊({e}×H). Since the action of G on P is CCT, the action of G×{e} on P ×Q is CCT. Also, since the action of H on Q is CCT, it follows that the action of {e}×H on (P/G)×Q is CCT. Therefore, the action of (G×{e})⋊({e}×H) satisfies the conditions of Proposition1.7 and so the action of G×H is CCT. (cid:3)

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.