The Opening Mind For my parents Contents Preface ix 1 Words, Concepts, and Things 3 2 Open Concepts 25 3 Art 49 4 Tragedy 91 5 Style in Art History 105 6 Human Action 141 7 Morality 189 8 Epilogue 237 Notes 251 Bibliography 257 Index 271 vii Morris Weitz The A Philosophical Study of Humanistic Concepts Opening Mind The University of Chicago Press Chicago and London Morris Weitz is the Richard Köret Professor of Philosophy at Brandeis University. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago 60637 The University of Chicago Press, Ltd., London © 1977 by The University of Chicago All rights reserved. Published 1977 Printed in the United States of America 82 81 80 79 78 77 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Weitz, Morris. The opening mind: a philosophical study of humanistic concepts; Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Concepts. I. Title. BD181.W38 121 77-7387 ISBN 0-226-89240-9 Preface Concepts are fundamental in philosophy, the sciences, and the humanities and in many human and animal activities. What they are and what roles they play have been of perennial concern to philosophers in their efforts to provide an adequate account of the conceptual life. Perhaps philosophers alone employ concepts and proffer theories of them: what they are and what they do. Even though a particular philosopher's range of concepts can be as narrow as he pleases—he may devote his life to an investiga tion of the one concept of entailment—any philosophical theory of concepts, if it is to do justice to the ostensible variety of conceptualization, must accommodate at least the major distin guishable uses of concepts, whether the concepts themselves are ordinary, scientific, or humanistic. It is just here, I think, that philosophy is inherently inter disciplinary, since the adequacy of our understanding of con cepts depends primarily on our appreciation of the diversity of concepts as they are found, not only in philosophy, but in all disciplines. It has long seemed to me, as it has to others, that a central task of philosophy is the exploration of the conceptual life. One important region to be mapped—certainly as important as the sciences—is the humanistic disciplines. During the past ten years or so, especially in Hamlet and the Philosophy of Literary Criticism and in various essays in the philosophy of art, I have tried to elucidate some of the basic concepts of literary criticism and art history. Instead of beginning with preconceived theories of drama, tragedy, interpretation, evaluation, and criticism of works of art in literary criticism or of period-style concepts in art history, I studied the roles of these concepts in a rich and living tradition of criticism and art history. This examination, whether ix x finally correct or not, uncovered three radically different kinds of concepts, hitherto unnoticed by philosophers: the perennially debatable (tragedy); the perennially flexible (art, drama); and the irreducibly vague (Mannerism). All of these seem to me indisputable examples of open concepts: that is, concepts and their conveying terms that function under no definitive sets of criteria. These concepts, I concluded, are not ambiguous, nor are they vague in the traditional sense of obscure or without boundaries"; and, more important, they are not closed in the classical platonic sense of being governed by necessary and sufficient criteria. These discoveries of the logical character of certain concepts were, of course, anticipated as well as inspired by others, especially Waismann and Wittgenstein. But I also realized that their probings into open texture and family resemblances do not Preface sufficiently clarify the logic or range of open concepts. More is needed on the logic of different kinds of less-than-definitive sets of criteria for certain concepts if these diverse open concepts are to be sorted out. It is precisely this task of sorting-out that I have set myself in this book. I begin with the relation between words, concepts, and things or, in grander, traditional terms, the relation between language, conceptualization, and the world. In particular, I ask whether concepts are words, meanings of words, or uses of words; whether concepts are abilities or entities, either sensible or supersensible; whether talk about concepts is reducible to talk about uses of words; and whether the having of concepts is the same as the having of certain skills, including being able to wield certain expressions. I attempt to formulate and defend the only theses I am able to support regarding these questions: that there are concepts, irreducible to anything else, and that any theory of concepts, whether explicit or implicit in a particular philos opher's use of concepts, entails a corresponding theory of language—specifically, a theory about the logical nature of the sets of criteria governing the intelligible, correct use of certain words. Having articulated these two theses, I go on to present a survey of the recent critique of closed concepts among some contemporary philosophers, along with their various concep tions of open concepts. These first two chapters introduce the next five, devoted to certain basic concepts in aesthetics, art history, psychology, and ethics, in which I argue that these concepts are open, in varying degrees of openness, rather than closed, as they are traditionally and commonly assumed to be. Unfortunately, I have not canvassed as many varieties of open concepts as I wished; there xi is much to be done on the detailed explorations of concepts, especially in the social and natural sciences and in mathematics, which, had I attempted them, would have required another volume. However, having established my main contention, that the underlying assumption of Western philosophy, expresed or embodied in its various theories of concepts, namely, that all concepts are and must be closed—beautifully put by Frege's "A concept that is not sharply defined is wrongly termed a concept" —is false, I am satisfied with the results of this volume. What I have done, I have tried to do thoroughly. That there are concepts other than closed ones, of varying degrees of openness, I think I have shown. What I have not established or even ventured is a general theory of concepts: open and closed. The reason I have not is that my lingering suspicion that there is no such theory may be justified; if so, we are left in philosophy with Preface an ever-incomplete sampling of their great diversity. In place of a conclusion, then, I offer only afterwords: about what is no longer questionable or deniable, that there are irreducible and respectable varieties and even vagaries of conceptualization; and about what can be done in this area of inquiry, where what can be done is not to be understood as what remains to be done. I know the answer to the one, but not to the other. Throughout the book, I attempt not only to establish founda tions for concepts in the humanities, by disclosing their varieties of openness, but, equally as important, to dispel the myth that the respectability of the humanities rests on the determination of closed concepts and their definitions, supposedly modeled on the precision and definitive sets of conditions governing scientific concepts. In showing that some of the basic concepts of the humanistic disciplines are governed by open, not closed, sets of criteria, without which they do not and perhaps cannot func tion, I celebrate rather than continue to apologize for the irreducible varieties and vagaries of the conceptual life. Chapters 2, 4, 5, and 6 have appeared in other versions elsewhere. I have reworked these extensively and have tried to integrate them with the wholly new materials of the other chapters. An earlier version of chapter 2 appeared in my article "Open Concepts" in the Revue Internationale de Philosophie, no. 99 (1972), pp. 86-110. Parts of chapter 4 have been reworked from my article "Tragedy," which appeared in volume 8 of The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Paul Edwards, copyright © 1967 by Crowell Collier and Macmillan, Inc. Chapter 5 is a much-revised and expanded version of my article "Genre and Style," published in Perspectives in Education, xii Religion, and the Arts, edited by Howard Kiefer and Milton Munitz, copyright © 1970 by the State University of New York Press, Albany. And an earlier, quite different version of chapter 6, "Human Action," appeared under the same title in the Annual Proceedings of the Center for Philosophic Exchange, vol. 1, no. 3 (1972). Finally, I wish to express my gratitude to my colleagues, Douglas Stewart and David Wiesen, for aid in certain matters Greek and Latin, and to Henry David Aiken for invaluable conversations in the language of philosophy; to The National Endowment for the Humanities for a Senior Fellowship that enabled me to devote the academic year 1973-74 to the writing of this book (as well as a companion volume on the history of philosophical theories of concepts, to be published, I hope, in the not too distant future); and to La Fondation Camargo and, especially, its director, Russell Young, who graciously and generously accommodated myself, my three children, and my wife—a Resident Fellow—in the Fondation. The Opening Mind