ebook img

Open Systems and Measurement in Relativistic Quantum Theory: Proceedings of the Workshop Held at the Istituto Italiano per gli Studi Filosofici Naples, April 3–4, 1998 PDF

232 Pages·1999·11.35 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Open Systems and Measurement in Relativistic Quantum Theory: Proceedings of the Workshop Held at the Istituto Italiano per gli Studi Filosofici Naples, April 3–4, 1998

State Vector Reduction in Relativistic Quantum Mechanics: An Introduction Heinz-Peter Breuer and Francesco Petruccione Fakult£t fiir Physik, Universit~t Freiburg, Hermann-Herder-Str. 3, D-79104 Freiburg i. Br., Germany Abstract. An introductory outline of measurements in relativistic quantum theory is given. Following the ideas of Aharonov and Albert, the apparent paradoxes of causality for nonlocal measurements and of the instantaneity of the state vector reduction are discussed. A relativistically covariant prescription for measurements of local and nonlocal observables is presented. The selective measurement of nonlocal observables is formulated in terms of the state vectors of the quantum object and of the corresponding quantum probe. Finally, some general conclusions concerning the constraints imposed by causality on the measurability of operators and states are drawn. 1 Introduction In 1932 John von Neumann ]1[ introduced the following assumption about the reduction of the wave function within the orthodox statistical interpretation of quantum mechanics: As a consequence of the measurement of one (or more) observables the state vector characterizing the measured system undergoes an instantaneous change, a discontinuous quantum jump; after the measurement the system is described by one of the possible eigenfunctions of the measured observables. It is the aim of this introductory article to address some paradoxes aris- ing in the application of this 'standard' reduction postulate to relativistic quantum mechanics and to show how these apparent problems can be solved. Furthermore, we will indicate directions of actual and future research. Applying naively the reduction postulate to relativistic quantum mechan- ics one is immediately confronted with two apparent paradoxes. These para- doxes are easily made explicit by considering two simple physical situations which have been discussed in detail by Aharonov and Albert [2]. The paradox of causality for nonlocal measurements: Let a particle be originally localized in a certain spacetime region A. At a certain time tl a measurement of the momentum of the particle is performed. As a result of the measurement the particle will be in a momentum eigenstate for times t > tl; as a consequence of the measurement it will have a non-vanishing amplitude in the whole 3-space. In other words: Apparently, the measurement of the momentum distributes the particle instantaneously over the whole space (see Fig. 1). Namely, when the location of the particle is measured at a time 2 Heinz-Peter Breuer and Francesco Petruccione around t -- tl + e, the particle is found in a spacetime region B with a probability which is different from zero: P(B) > 0. (1) On the other hand, the spacetime regions A and B can be chosen such that each pair of points AX E A and xB E B is separated by a spacelike distance: (XB--XA) 2-(xB-xA)~(xB-xA)~ <0 for all XB E B, AX EA. (2) xO-- t tl -~- E tl A ¢#0 Fig. 1. A particle is initially confined to some spacetime region A. A measurement of the momentum at time tl redistributes the probability amplitude over all 3-space. In this way information could be transferred from A to B with a speed greater than the speed of light. Thus, the causality principle is violated here; had we not measured the momentum at time t = tl, then clearly P(B) = 0. It seems that through the State Vector Reduction in Relativistic Quantum Mechanics 3 measurement of momentum, information can be carried from A to B with a speed greater than the speed of light. The paradox of the instantaneity of the state vector reduction" This problem is related to the relativity of instantaneous events, i.e. to the nonexistence of an absolute time in relativity theory. If the state vector re- duction takes place instantaneously in an inertial system, in another inertial system it will not be instantaneous. Again we consider an example. Let a free particle be prepared in a momentum eigenstate at time t -- -oo. At time t -- 0 the same particle is found at x = 0 by some detector which is placed there (see Fig. 2). The detector is assumed to interact locally with the particle. Ac- Lorentz transformation ,, "-S;:" ,~;S +" Fig. 2. Instantaneous state reduction following a local measurement. The state reduction occurs along an equal-time hypersurface t = const in one frame (left). In a moving inertial frame this surface is no longer an equal-time hypersurface (right). cording to the reduction postulate at the time of measurement t = 0 the state of the particle will change instantaneously from a momentum eigenstate to a position eigenstate. The paradox of this situation is the following: Although the local position measurement should be described by some local, covariant interaction between object and measurement device, the above prescription for an instantaneous state vector reduction is obviously not covariant. Thus, the following question arises naturally: How does a covariant prescription for state vector reduction look like in relativistic quantum theory? Some of the questions related to the first paradox have already been dis- cussed by Landau and Peierls in 1931 [3]. They concluded that all nonlocal quantities, like the momentum operator, cannot be observables in relativistic quantum theories. This seems to be a very severe restriction if one con- 4 Heinz-Peter Breuer and Francesco Petruccione siders that the momentum is a very important quantity, e.g. for scattering experiments, and that the canonical quantization of field theories is usually performed in the momentum representation. In a certain sense the important work of Bohr and Rosenfeld 'Zur Frage der Mefibarkeit der elektromagnetischen FeldgrSi]en' [4], which was published in 1933, can be understood as an argumentation against Landau and Peierls. Bohr and Rosenfeld show how the operators of the electromagnetic field can be measured, and that the uncertainity relations for the field operators are in- deed satisfied. The essential difference to the reasoning of Landau and Peierls is that Bohr and Rosenfeld assume the measuring apparatus to be classical, and that, therefore, its atomistic structure can be neglected completely. Thus, we see that one of the central questions of state vector reduction in relativis- tic quantum mechanics will be: What can and what cannot be measured in relativistic quantum mechanics? The second paradox clearly has its origin in the fact that the standard reduction postulate is definitely not Lorentz covariant. Accordingly, the sec- ond fundamental question of relativistic state vector reduction is: What is the relativistic covariant prescription of state vector reduction? Such a prescription in the spirit of Landau and Peierls has beeen given by Hellwig and Kraus [5]. They assume that the relativistic state reduction for a local measurement has to occur along the backward ligh t cone of the measurement event (see Fig. 3). As Hellwig and Kraus have shown their pre- scription is manifestly Lorentz-covariant and leads to the correct predictions for all probabilities of local measurements. However, this state vector reduc- tion prescription fails for the measurement of nonlocal observables [2]. This can be seen easily with the help of Fig. 3. If the particle has been prepared at time t = -~ in a momentum eigenstate, a further measurement of the momentum at time t = 0-e, i.e. at a time prior to the position measurement, will simply affirm the state of the system. At time t = 0 - c the particle is in a momentum eigenstate and not in the state indicated in Fig. 3, which is concentrated along and within the backward light cone. Hellwig and Kraus will not consider this criticism to be a problem, simply because, in the sense of Landau and Peierls, the measurability of momentum at time t = 0 - e is regarded as impossible. However, there is indeed a problem. Aharonov and Albert have shown [2, ]6 that it is possible to measure and prepare nonlocal observables. We will discuss this in detail in Sect. 3. There we will also ex- plain why causality is not violated in such measurement schemes. Herewith the reduction postulate of Hellwig and Kraus is invalidated. The second paradox will be studied in detail in Sect. 2. Among the many attempts to circumvent this problem we want to mention just the work of Co- hen and Hiley [7]. These authors suggest to perform the state vector reduction instantaneously in a so-called preferred Lorentz frame. This approach does not seem to be particularly attractive. The introduction of a preferred coordi- nate system in a certain sense seems to be a regression to a pre-relativistic age. State Vector Reduction in Relativistic Quantum Mechanics 5 / Fig. 3. Illustration of the relativistic state vector reduction postulate of Hellwig and Kraus and its invalidation by Aharonov and Albert. In particular, such a prescription implies the reintroduction of the concept of an absolute time, which is essentially determined by the inertial system in which the state vector reduction is instantaneous, i.e. in which it occurs along the hypersurfaces t = const. There might be cases for which a preferred frame can be introduced in a plausible way (e.g. considering a particle decay- ing into two other particles, one could choose the rest frame of the common center of mass), however there does not seem to be the possibility to achieve this satisfactorily in more general eases. Consider for example an electron, whose position we want to measure. If the reduction is to be performed in- stantaneously in the rest system of the electron, we have to determine the momentum of the electron; however the measurement of position leaves the momentum completely undetermined. A continuous measurement of the po- sition of the electron is therefore impossible. 6 Heinz-Peter Breuer and Francesco Petruccione 2 State Vector Reduction for Local Measurements Let us now concentrate our attention on the paradox of the instantaneity of state vector reduction. We begin by considering local measurements. Essen- tially there are two fundamental possibilities to circumvent this paradox. First, one can stick to the usual concept of a wave function ¢(t, x) as a function on the spacetime continuum. If one wants to construct a Lorentz covariant prescription for the state vector reduction, one has to identify some Lorentz invariant hypersurface (such as the backward light cone) along which the reduction takes place, that is along which the dynamics of the wave function is not continuous. There is a second possibility which has been first proposed by Aharonov and Albert [8]. This possibility consists in the assumption that the state vec- tor reduction takes place instantaneously in all inertial flames. Formulated in a more precise way this means the following: Let us assume that a local measurement takes place in the spacetime point P. Then the state vector reduction takes place along all spacelike hypersur/aces a, which pass through this point P .1 In the following we will denote this set of surfaces by ~p (see Fig. 4). The set of all flat, spacelike hypersurfaces in Minkowski space is then given by U )3( Obviously, this construction leads to a Lorentz covariant prescription of the state vector reduction, because the set ~p is Lorentz invariant. Each surface a E ~p appears as an 'equal-time' hypersurface in some reference frame. Thus ~'p can be identified with the set of all local observers which go through the point P. In other words we can identify Ep with the set of all worldlines y = y(~-) (parametrized by their proper time 7) passing the point P, y(0) = P, (4) with a timelike 4-velocity n, n-- YTy~d r=0 , n,n" = 1. (5) Given such a path, the hypersurface which is defined by a = a(n,P) = {x e ]R41n(x- P) = 0} (6) represents an 'equal-time' hypersurface T = 0 for the corresponding local observer (in the instantaneous rest frame K' of this observer we have = ~ n 1 Aharonov and Albert have formulated this prescription for arbitrary, not neces- sarily flat, spacelike hypersurfaces. For our present needs, however, it is sufficient to consider only the subset of flat hypersurfaces, which is closed under Lorentz transformations. State Vector Reduction in Relativistic Quantum Mechanics 7 a Ep X 1 Fig. 4. The covariant state reduction postulate of Aharonov and Albert for a local measurement at the spacetime point P. (1, 0, 0, 0) and the equation for a becomes simply x °~ - ~ =t const). Hence we see that ~p is a 3-dimensional manifold, which is parametrized uniquely by a timelike unit normal vector n. In this way the reduction prescription of Aharonov and Albert appears to be completely natural. In agreement with the theory of relativity all instan- taneous observers are physically equivalent. Regardless from the meaning we want to attribute to the state vector reduction as a real physical process, the practical scope of the state vector reduction is to describe in a consistent way how to exploit the information gained in a certain measurement for the prediction of the probabilities of future events. It should describe how the result of a certain measurement determines the following state of the quan- tum mechanical system. The question to be answered is: How does a certain observer in his frame o/ reference use the information gained in the mea- surement to describe future states of the system? In this formulation the set ~p appears very naturally and the paradox of the instantaneity of the state vector reduction loses all aspects of a violation of covariance. 8 Heinz-Peter Breuer and Francesco Petruccione The above prescription for the reduction of the state vector does have an important consequence. Namely, the wave function is no longer a function on the spacetime continuum. In order to explain this important point we suppose that in the infinite past an electron has been prepared in a state which is given by a superposition of two wave packets )/(1) and )/(2) localized at xl and x2, respectively, ¢(x) )7( = x(1)(x) + In the following we shall neglect, for simplicity, the extension as well as the spreading of these wave packets. At the spacetime point P a position mea- surement is performed with the result that the electron is at P. Given such a situation we may consider two spacelike hypersurfaces al and a2 which intersect at the spacetime point Q (see Fig. 5). Both hypersurfaces appear as equal-time hypersurfaces in appropriately chosen coordinate frames K1 and Ks, that is there are observers 1O and 02 at rest in K1 and/(2, respectively, such that al is an equal-time hypersurface for O1, and a2 is an equal-time hypersurface for O2. The important difference between both observers is that for 02 the measurement has already taken place, whereas for O1 it has not. Consequently, both observers assign different amplitudes to one and the same objective spacetime point Q, that is, ¢(Q) on al is different from ¢(Q) on 0" 5. The conclusion is that ¢ is no longer a function of the spacetime coordinates: The value of ¢ at a spacetime point depends, in general, on the hypersurface crossing this point and to which it is associated. Thus, the wave function becomes a function on the set of spacelike hypersurfaces and we may write ¢ = ¢(a, x), (8) where x runs over the points of the hypersurface a. For example, we have at the spacetime point Q of Fig. 5: ¢(a~, Q) = x(2)(Q) ~ ¢(a2, Q) = 0. (9) To illustrate further the consequences of this concept, we shall discuss an- other example which also stems from Aharanov and Albert. At time t = -co we prepare a particle to be in the state ¢1, which is a superposition of three wave packets localized respectively at xl, x2 and x3. At time tl we measure in xl and we find that the particle is not in xl. At time t2 a measurement at x2 is performed and it turns out that the particle is not at x2. It is assumed that the events (tl, xl) and (t2, x2) have a spacelike distance. Then there is an inertial system K in which t2 > tl and the observer associated with it ascribes the 'history' depicted in Fig. 6 to the wave function. There is also another inertial frame of an observer B who sees the 'history' of the wave function in his coordinate system K ~ in the following way (see Fig. 7; this picture is drawn in the coordinate system K of the observer A). For the observer B the measurement at x2 takes place before the measurement at xl: His 'equal time' hypersurface crosses the measurement event at (t2, x2) State Vector Reduction in Relativistic Quantum Mechanics 9 t-O D 1 X QJ 17( 27( I Xl X2 Fig. 5. Illustration of the fact that the state vector ceases to be a function on spacetime if local measurements are taken into account. before the measurement event at (tl, xl). The state ¢~ is obtained from the state ¢1 by a unitary representation U(A) of a Lorentz transformation A which maps al to a~, ¢~ = U(A)¢I. (10) In the same way one gets ¢~ from ¢3 through a Lorentz transformation ¢~ = U(A)¢3. (11) The same is true also for the components ]xi), whose superposition we have considered )~xI = U(A)lxi). (12) However, the important point is that this is not true for the 'intermediate' state ¢2. Namely, ¢~ is not the Lorentz transform of ¢2; these states are not related by a unitary representation of some Lorentz transformation. The processes formulated by the observers A and B are thus completely different. Nevertheless, covariance is satisfied here. Since we have introduced the wave function as a functional on the hypersurfaces, the processes described 01 Heinz-Peter Breuer and Francesco Petruccione 0-3 ¢3 = Ix3) ? t2 ¢2 = Ix2> + Ix3) 0- 2 • I I tl - I - - ? ¢1 = Ix1> + Iz2> + Ix3> 1-0 • I I I I | I D Xl X2 X3 1 X Fig. 6. A system subjected to a sequence of state vector reductions as seen from an observer A in a reference frame K in which t2 > tl. in Figs. 6 and 7 are really different! Covariance requires only the equivalence of all inertial systems, hence the independence of all physical statements from a special coordinate system. And exactly this point has been made obvious in what we have discussed above: Performing a Lorentz transformation from an inertial system to another one has to trans]orm the states of the quantum system as well as the observer who ascribes a history of state vectors to his equal-time hypersur/aces. 3 Preparation and Measurement of Nonlocal Observables Having discussed the reduction of the state vector of a system under arbitrary local measurements we now turn our attention to the problems arising in the context of the measurement of nonlocal observables. In order to illustrate the problem we consider a system of two spin-l/2 particles [2, 6, 8], which are situated at two fixed points xl and x2 in a fixed coordinate system. The Hilbert space of the spin states is 4-dimensional and it is spanned by the states (we adopt the notation used in [2]):

Description:
This book treats modern aspects of open systems, measurement, and decoherence in relativistic quantum theory. It starts with a comprehensive introduction to the problems related to measuring local and nonlocal observables and the constraints imposed by the causality principle. In the articles that f
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.