ebook img

On the Natural State of Men PDF

142 Pages·1990·2.832 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview On the Natural State of Men

SAMUEL PU FEN DORFS ON THE NATURAL STATE OF MEN The 1678 Latin Edition and English Translation Translated, Annotated, and Introduced by Michael Seidler Studies in the History of Philosophy Volume 13 The Edwin Mellen Press Lewiston/Queenston/Lampeter Library of Congress Caialoging-in-Piiblication Data This book has been registered with the Library of Congress. This is volume 13 in the continuing series Studies in the History of Philosophy Volume 13 ISBN 0-88946-299-2 SHP Series ISBN 0-88946-300-X A C1P catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Copyright © 1990 Michael Seidler All rights reserved. For information contact The Edwin Mellen Press The Edwin Mellen Press Box 450 Box 67 Lewiston, New York Queenston, Ontario USA 14092 CANADA LOS 1L0 The Edwin Mellen Press, Ltd. l^mpeter, Dyfed, Wales UNITED KINGDOM SA48 7DY Printed in the United States of America for Sarah and Alex for all the waiting... TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgments ix INTRODUCTORY ESSAY 1 i. Pufendorfs Life and Works 3 II. The Modern Natural Law Tradition 13 III. The ‘Natural State’ in Pufendorf 25 IV. The Function of the ‘Natural State’ in Early Modern Natural Law Theory 43 Notes to Introductory Essay 54 SELECT BIBLIOGRAPHY 71 COMMENTS ON TEXT AND TRANSLATION 77 "DE STATU HOMINUM NATURALI" (Latin Text of 1678) 83 "ON THE NATURAL STATE OF MEN" (Translation) 109 NOTES TO TRANSLATION 137 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS The current, relatively undeveloped state of Pufendorf scholarship makes research in this area somewhat more difficult than in fields where texts and studies are more easily available. This means, among other things, that one’s eventual debts are also enlarged. Since my initial task was to acquire the appropriate manuscripts, I owe thanks to the rare book librarians of UCLA, Northwestern University, and the New York Public Library for respectively supplying me with the 1675, 1677, and 1678 editions of Pufendorfs Dissertaiiones academicae selectiores, the essay collection in which "De statu hominum naturali" is found. I am likewise indebted and grateful to the underfunded and no doubt understaffed Library of Congress, particularly the head of its Loan Division, Christopher Wright, for making available to me a microfilm copy of the 1744 Mascovius edition of Pufendorfs De jure naturae et gentium, which is bound with a late, complete version of the latter’s Eris scandica. Closer to home, it is a pleasure to acknowledge the expert and cheerful assistance of Ms. Susan Tucker and the Interlibrary Loan Department at Helm-Cravens Library of Western Kentucky University whom I pestered with many an obscure and difficult request. Ms. Tucker and her staff helped remedy the real geographical handicaps that confronted me in this particular kind of scholarly work. Western Kentucky University also furthered my project by generously granting me a Summer Faculty Research Fellowship in 1987, and by approving reduced teaching loads for two semesters. For this latter assistance, and also for his general support and encouragement, I am particularly grateful to Alan B. Anderson, Head of the Department of Philosophy and Religion. Finally, I thank the Department of Political Science at Portland State University (OR) for providing me with working space and other facilities during the summer of 1987. Though mostly completed by then, this project has also benefited from my participation in the NEH Summer Institute on Early Modern Philosophy at Brown University (1988). The stimulating presentations of the Institute staff, particularly Edwin Curley, David Fate Norton, Richard Popkin, and Jerome Schneewind, as welt as conversations with them and other participants, including Mary Gregor and Mark Waymack, improved my understanding of early modern moral philosophy and made me aware of some needed corrections and qualifications in my introductory essay-for whose remaining defects I alone am responsible. I thank all of them, as well as the National Endowment for the Humanities and Daniel Garber, the Institute’s director, for making this valuable opportunity available to me. My colleague and sometime collaborator, Craig L. Carr (Department of Political Science, Portland State University, OR), deserves special mention not only for his many helpful comments on both the translation and the introductory essay (where 1 have sometimes taken his advice), but also for test-teaching the translation for clarity and readability in one of his political theory classes. I continue to appreciate his collegial assistance. Finally, I owe thanks to Ms. Joan ten Hoor, reference librarian at the University of Louisville, for responding to an important initial inquiry from an unknown scholar on locating 17th-century manuscripts; and to Joseph and Monessa Cummins for clarifying one of Pufendorfs unattributcd classical references at a point when I had almost given up. My greatest debts are to Sarah and Alex Seidler. The former demanded that I transform my Germanic prose into more or less readable English, and the latter, quite simply, to be paid some attention. Though they may think this book has been written in spite of them, both it and many other things besides would never have been accomplished without their indulgence, help, and support. INTRODUCTORY ESSAY1 There are few discussions of Pufendorf in English, particularly ones that are both general and short.2 Moreover, for reasons that will become clear, the scholarly literature as a whole is relatively meager. Hence, the task of introducing one of Pufendorfs smaller and lesser-known works is formidable. In what follows, I offer both a broad overview of Pufendorfs work and its 17th-century context, as well as a more detailed analysis of the subject of this newly edited and translated text on the state of nature. My treatment is divided into four major sections. Following a survey of Pufendorfs life and works in the first section, Section II situates Pufendorf within the natural law tradition before and after him, particularly in relation to his main intellectual predecessors: Grotius, Hobbes, and Weigel. Section III contains a description of Pufendorfs various treatments of and carefully distinguished meanings for the ‘state of nature/ as well as a structured content analysis of the essay translated here for the first time. Finally, in Section IV, I discuss Pufendorfs philosophical use of the state-of-nature concept in relation to the larger 17th-century natural law problematic, particularly as this has been recently interpreted by Richard Tuck and others. Given my essay’s double function of introducing both Pufendorf and one of his works, portions thereof are necesarily more general and less nuanced than they otherwise might be. Also, except for the closer analysis in Section III, I have relied primarily and heavily on the existing secondary literature, hoping thereby also to fulfill my introductory task of orienting the reader and opening up avenues for the further study of Pufendorfs thought. I. PUFENDORFS LIFE AND WORKS Samuel Pufendorf was bom into a Lutheran pastor’s family in Dorfchemnitz-bei-Thalheim, in Saxony, on January 8, 1632, a year that also saw the birth of Spinoza, Locke, and Cumberland. Their century was marked by tremendous social, political and intellectual upheaval-a fact reflected differently in each of their philosophies. In general, it was still an age of exploration when the significance of many new geographical and social discoveries was beginning to be absorbed-often disruptively-into European thought. Increasingly, too, it was an age of science, which began seriously to challenge the established secular and religious orthodoxies with both its theoretical claims and associated practical results. And on the Continent, the Protestant Reformation’s legacy of religious fragmentation contributed to ongoing political reorganization of major proportions-the disintegration of the German (Holy Roman) Empire coinciding with the ascendancy of Sweden, France, and Prussia as modem, secular nation-states, and with the transformation of the Netherlands from a Spanish colony into an independent republic. Many of these changes were marked by a pervasive violence that added fear to the insecurity and disorientation that must already have been felt. Nothing represents this better than the brutal Thirty-Years’ War (1618- 48) that was but half over at the time of Pufendorfs birth. Though his immediate environment was not ravaged, the young Pufendorf was no doubt 6 refusal of the doctorate, Weigel prudently persuaded him to earn the master’s degree essential for a university career. Now Pufendorf, like other independent students throughout history, faced the prospect of getting a job. He declined an unacceptable offer at the University of Halle and was unable to find an academic post in his native Saxony, at Leipzig, where his future prospects would have been difficult at best.7 Once again, however, he benefitted from the lifelong fraternal attention of Esaias, who had already left Jena for the diplomatic service of Christina of Sweden. There Esaias now obtained for his younger brother the position of tutor to the family of Peter Julius Coyet, the Swedish minister in Copenhagen. Soon after Samuel’s arrival there, Sweden suddenly expressed its dissatisfaction with the ongoing peace talks by reconvening its war with Denmark. Whether or not Coyet himself anticipated the Swedish betrayal, he managed to flee while leaving his family and their tutor behind. But Pufendorf turned the ensuing eight-month imprisonment into an opportunity (much in the fashion of Grotius at Loevenstein castle) and composed without benefit of books an already planned work that inaugurated the rest of his career. In the Elementa jurisprudentiae universalis, a work much indebted to Grotius and Hobbes, Pufendorf deduced in quasi-mathematical fashion a system of law based on the light of reason alone that foreshadowed much of his later thinking. After his release and recuperation from prison, he brought the manuscript to Holland, where he rejoined the Coyet family. Though apparently not intending to publish his notes, he nonetheless circulated the Elementa among his brother and friends, who persuaded him to publish it in 1660. While in Holland, Pufendorf also pursued studies in classical philology at the University of Leiden, becoming more familiar with the Stoicism that would play such an important role in his mature system. He edited and annotated two works on classical antiquity,8 and-perhaps most importantly for his future career-he made the acquaintance of the great classical scholar, Gronovius, and also of Peter de Groot, son of Hugo Grotius, both of whom had'taught the Elector of the Palatinate, Kart Ludwig, who was an alumnus of the university.9 7 Recommended by these two notables and his own Elementa, which he had calculatingly dedicated to Karl Ludwig, Pufendorf soon (1661) received an invitation to the University of Heidelberg. To prove his usefulness, he also wrote around this time a short legal opinion called "Wildfangstreit" in which he defended the Elector's right to levy a medieval serf tax on immigrants from the surrounding Rhenish towns and on knights. Offered a professorship (ordinarius) in Roman law, Pufendorf now demonstrated the Saxon courage and manly independence so lauded by some of his German expositors by promptly refusing it. Instead, he requested an appointment on the law faculty as a professor of politics. As he later explained, he had no desire to add yet another to the 999 existing commentaries on the Corpus Juris.10 Under probable pressure from Karl Ludwig, the reluctant university senate then proposed an associate professorship (extraordinarius) in international law and philology (humaniora) on the philosophy faculty which Pufendorf accepted. Soon after his arrival, though, he turned this position into a professorship in natural and international law-the first such chair in Germany, as he himself later recalled11--and began lecturing on Grotius. A few years later, in 1664, Pufendorf tried again to join the law faculty by vying for a vacant professorship in German constitutional law. But after being spurned once more by the juristic establishment, he had his existing position transformed into a chair in natural law and politics. And so it remained until his removal to Sweden. Pufendorfs eight years in Heidelberg were among the happiest of his life. In 1665, he entered into a successful marriage with the widow of an academic colleague, a union that produced two loyal daughters. At the university, both the content and style of his teaching made him popular among the students, a number of whom were lodged at his house (as he himself had lodged with Weigel at Jena12). The Elector appointed him privy councilor and entrusted to him the education of his son. And Pufendorf supplemented his concrete political education at court by utilizing the excellent university library to further expand the already broad and diverse learning so evident in his main works. Ironically, much of his writing during this period was evoked by less satisfying experiences. To demonstrate his qualifications for the chair on the

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.