On the Government of Rulers De Regimine Principum THE MIDDLE AGES SERIES Ruth Mazo Karras,General Editor Edward Peters, Founding Editor Acomplete listof books inthe series isavailablefrom the publisher. On the Government of Rulers De Regiminc Principum PtolemyofLucca with portions attributed to Thomas Aquinas translated by [ames M. Blythe' PENN University of Pennsylvania Press Philadelphia Copyright © 1997UniversityofPennsylvaniaPress Allrights reserved Printed intheUnited StatesofAmericaonacid-freepaper 109 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 I Published by University ofPennsylvaniaPress Philadelphia, Pennsylvania19104-6097 Library ofCongressCataloging-in-Publication Data Bartholomew, ofLucca,ca.1236-1327. [Deregimineprincipum. English] On thegovernment ofrulers :Deregimineprincipum /Ptolemy ofLucca; withportions attributed toThomas Aquinas; translated by JamesM.Blythe. p. em. - (TheMiddleAgesseries) Includesbibliographical referencesandindex. ISBN 0-8122-3370-0(alk.paper) 1.Politicalscience- Earlyworksto 1800. I.Blythe,JamesM., 1948- . II.Thomas, Aquinas, Saint,1225?-1274.Deregno, adregemCypri. English. III.Title. IV.Series. JC121.B2813 1997 320.1'01-dc21 97-2015 CIP Contents Preface vii ANote on the Text xi Introduction I Book I 60 Book 2 104 Book 3 146 Book 4 215 Bibliography 289 Index to Aristotle Citations 293 Index to Augustine Citations 295 Index to BiblicalCitations 297 General Index 301 This page intentionally left blank Preface WHEN I WAS WORKING ON MY BOOK, Ideal Government and theMixed Constitution in theMiddle Ages, I was especially drawn to Ptolemy of Lucca (c.1236-c.1327), whose radical ideas were remarkable for his time, but about whom very little has been written, and Idevoted achapter to him.' I felt that atranslation of hiswork waslong overdue, considering itsoriginality and the fact that it influenced much ofthe political thought ofthe later Middle Ages, the Renaissance, and the early modern period. Only afew professional medi evalistshavereadPtolemy's work initsscholastic Latin, but ifitwere available in English it could benefit allhistorians of political thought aswell asmany others interested in political theory, the history of ideas, and the history of constitutionalism. It could also beused in courses in political thought and in the medieval and earlymodern intellectual tradition. I have already used it in agraduate readings course in medieval history with excellent results. It might also begin to redress the serious undervaluation of Ptolemy'S position in the history of ideas, reflected in what has been at best cursory treatment in gen eralhistories ofpolitical thought. More than anyone else, Ptolemy combined the principles of northern Italian government with scholastic Aristotelian political theory. He was also the first of his time, or among the first, to state many ideas that were later to become commonplace. He is the first medieval political theorist not to endorse kingship as the best form of government . In fact, he attacks it as the moral equivalent of despotism, totally inappropriate for a virtuous and freedom-loving people. Believing this, he obviously cannot subscribe to the dominant medieval appreciation for the Roman Empire. Instead he glorifies Republican Rome and brands Julius Caesarasatyrant and the Roman Empire astyranny. These areremarkable assertions for someone writing around 1300, 1. JamesBlythe,IdealGovernment and theMixed Constitution intheMiddle Ages (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press,1992), 92-II7. viii Preface and the harbinger of acommonplace humanist viewof the fifteenth century. Although he defends republicanism vigorously, he nevertheless believesthat different circumstances, climates, and national characters may require differ ent forms ofgovernment andthat most arenot suited to the bestgovernment, which includes the representation of the few and the many in amixed con stitution. Ptolemy was also the first to equate the standard Greek models of mixed constitution-Sparta, Crete, and Carthage-with the Roman Repub lic, biblical rule, the Church, and medieval government. Again anticipating the humanists, hewasthe firstto suggest that the perfect republic could beso inwardly harmonious that itcould transcend the normal imperatives ofdecay and ultimate destruction. He alsobegan adebate on whether women should servein the military. One of the most remarkable things about Ptolemy's book isits wealth of examples, unique in scholastic works of his time. Almost everything he writes suggests some new example to him. Many ofthese come from the an cient or patristic classics,and these are unusual only in their number, their variety, and the use to which Ptolemy puts them. But he also makes many references to the history, customs, and attitudes of the Middle Ages. For ex ample, mentioning that aking should bewealthy inspireshim to discusshow coins areminted. After stating that climate determines national character, he demonstrates this with German immigrants to Sicilywho soon became like the Sicilians. He analyzes northern Italian city-states and the struggles be tween popes and emperors and touches on such diverse topics asTotila the Ostrogoth, Tuscan battle formations, the hunting habits of the French and English kings, the procedure for secret ballots in Florence, and the exchange between Pope Innocent III and the king ofAragon overdebased money. I am convinced that Ptolemy today stands in much the same position Marsilius ofPaduaoncedid. Hewasmentioned brieflyinsomegeneralworks and afew scholars pointed out that severallater writers referred to him, but even those who noticed him did not accord him anymajor importance. This all changed in the 1950S, when Alan Gewirth translated Marsilius's major work andwrote abook-length introduction to histhought.' Today,Marsilius is considered to be the great radical political thinker of the fourteenth cen tury, andexcerpts of hiswork appear ineveryhistorical anthology ofwestern political thought. In his own way, Ptolemy was every bit as radical and in fluential asMarsilius, and I think that this translation of his major political work, On theGovernment ofRulers, perhaps supplemented in the future by a 2. Alan Gewirth, MarsiliusofPadua,theDefenderofPeace,2 vols,Records ofCivilization: SourcesandStudies 46 (NewYork:Columbia University Press,1951-1956; reprinted NewYork: Harper andRow, 1967). Preface ix translation of his other political treatise, A ShortDetermination oftheJuris dictionoftheRoman Empire, would contribute to Ptolemy achieving amajor placeinfuture histories ofpolitical thought. _ Although Ptolemy did not write Book I and part of Book 2 ofthe trea tise translated in this volume, I decided to translate the whole, since"it has appeared in this form since the fourteenth century, and I wanted to show the difference between the two parts more clearlybyproviding aversion that maintains a consistent terminology throughout. Whether the other author wasThomas Aquinas, ashasbeen traditionally assumed, or another, asisnow often argued, isofsecondary concern inavolume centered on Ptolemy. In the next fewpagesIwilldiscussthe firstpart anditsauthor, but mymain purpose is to introduce Ptolemy's thought and the contemporary events, conflicts, and intellectual trends and paradigms that shaped it. Of necessity,this intro duction will be brief, but I hope to publish abook-length study of Ptolemy within the next fewyears. Ptolemy supported papal supremacy, justified despotic kings for most peoples, and tied character to birth and geography, but he also began the theoretical attack against monarchy. Today,American and European peoples pride themselves on their "democracies;' which reduce monarchy to at most a ceremonial post. At the same time, their governments sponsor tyrannies, massacres, and exploitation around the world and immiserate agrowing seg ment oftheir own citizenry,yetwith no senseofirony use"medieval" to mean "backward;' "cruel;' and "barbaric." Ptolemy and his successors may have begun to undermine the almost universal acceptance of monarchy, but the revolutions they eventually spawned created aresourceful new ruling class.In its dotage, this classhasbeen able,to adegree not possible inthe recent past, to rededicate itself to greed and the oppression necessary to sate its mem bers' individual desires,thanks to the discrediting ofegalitarian ideologies by totalitarian pseudo-socialist regimes. Almost miraculously ithasbeen ableto justify this to the massesasthe essenceoffreedom. Aristotle andthe medieval writers who followed him defined good government asthat which promotes the common good. What these words mean has changed over the centuries, but the concept issound and cannever rationally mean the right of afew to monopolize and destroy the wealth ofthe earth for their own benefit. In that senseclassicaland medieval political thought stillhasrelevancefor ustoday. The University of Memphis requires that the following statement be in cluded: "This work was supported in part by agrant from the University of Memphis Faculty Research Grant Fund. This support does not necessarily imply endorsement bythe University ofresearch conclusions." For advice on afew difficult passages, I thank Brian Tierney and James
Description: