ON IDEAS ON IDEAS Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's Theory of Forms GAIL FINE CLARENDON PRESS OXFORD This book has been printed digitally and produced in a standard specification in order to ensure its continuing availability OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS Great Clarendon Street, Oxford OX2 6DP Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Bangkok Buenos Aires Cape Town Chennai Dar es Salaam Delhi Hong Kong Istanbul Karachi Kolkata Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Mumbai Nairobi Sao Paulo Shanghai Taipei Tokyo Toronto Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York © Gail Fine 1993 The moral rights of the author have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) Reprinted 2004 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover And you must impose this same condition on any acquirer ISBN 0-19-823549-6 To My Parents and to Terry PREFACE THE Peri ideon (On Ideas) is a short essay by Aristotle, which survives only in fragments preserved by the Greek commentator Alexander, in his commentary on Aristotle's Metaphysics. In this essay, Aristotle presents and criticizes arguments for the existence of Platonic forms, and sketches his alternative. It is an especially rich source for anyone who wants to understand Plato's theory of forms. For it characterizes forms, and sets out arguments for their existence, more systematically than Plato does or than Aristotle does elsewhere. Asking whether Plato is committed to these arguments and characterizations affords new insights into the dialogues. Attention to the Peri ideon also illuminates Aristotle's under- standing of and alternative to Plato. Nor is the work of purely historical interest. It is one of the first contributions to the continuing debate about the nature of universals, and it raises still-current questions about, for example, the range of universals and whether they can exist uninstan- tiated. Anyone interested in this debate should be interested in its origins. I first became interested in the Peri ideon when, as a graduate student at Harvard in the early 19705, I took a seminar on it with Professor G. E. L. Owen. My interest in it deepened when I gave my own courses on it at Cornell. Initially I worked on the Peri ideon piecemeal, analysing a given argument and tracing its Platonic roots. But I gradually became convinced that the first book of the Peri ideon (which is my focus here) is an integrated whole, and so it seemed worth while to provide a connected discussion. This also seemed worth while because there was no systematic book length treatment of the Peri ideon available in English. Though the Peri ideon is short, the present work is rather long. This is partly because the Peri ideon's arguments are cryptic, abstract, and indeterminate. To explain the various ways in which they can be read, and to trace the implications of these readings, takes some time. This is not to say that Aristotle must have had any particular determinate reading in mind; perhaps he deliberately phrased the arguments in- determinately in order to highlight a corresponding indeterminacy in Plato's texts. But even if this is so, we need to see precisely how the arguments Aristotle records are indeterminate, and we need to see what this shows us about Plato and about Aristotle's understanding of him. Another reason for the relative length of my discussion is that the Peri ideon cannot be properly evaluated or understood in isolation. For example, in order to see whether the arguments Aristotle records can fairly be ascribed to Plato, we need to look at the Platonic texts. In order to understand the point of Aristotle's criticisms, we need to look at other Aristotelian passages where they are developed more fully. Or again, viii Preface short though the Peri ideon is, it often considers the same few Platonic passages from different points of view, so I often need to follow suit. (In a letter to Mersenne Descartes says that '[repetitions may be offensive in some places, but they are elegant in others' (AT III 36i/CSM III 180). I do not claim elegance, but the nature of the Peri ideon makes some repetition necessary.) Despite the length of my discussion, there are many omissions. For example, I do not provide a new text or edition of the Peri ideon, nor do I discuss the second book of the Peri ideon. I do not discuss in detail Platonists other than Plato, in order to see whether Aristotle might have them in mind, nor do I say much about Plato's late dialogues or so-called unwritten doctrines. There are many relevant aspects of Plato's and Aristotle's thought that I touch on but do not discuss in detail. Although I perhaps cannot justify all these omissions, I can explain my reasons for them. Since Dieter Harlfinger has recently produced a new, and good, text of most of the Peri ideon, based on a fresh examination of the manuscripts, it was unnecessary for me to produce yet another one. Nor was my aim to produce a critical edition of the Peri ideon; what follows is more of a philosophical than a philological exploration (although I do not think there are firm boundaries here). Although I do not discuss the second book of the Peri ideon, the part I focus on (book i) is self-contained. For example, as I explain in Ch. 2.7, its structure is neatly dilemmatic. I shall argue that one central aim of Peri ideon i is to illuminate Plato's theory of forms as it is described in the middle dialogues. (Peri ideon 2, by contrast, claims to discuss Eudoxus' theory of forms; it also discusses some arguments about principles which, while they are relevant to Plato, are not so clearly concerned with the middle dialogues in particular.) This is not to say that other sources, such as the late dialogues or other Platonists, are irrelevant; and at some stages I consider some relevant passages in the late dialogues as well as other possible sources. But since the middle dialogues seem to be a chief target, and since exploring that target is already quite a large project, it seemed reasonable to limit myself primarily to it. Others might like to carry my project further by asking what light the Peri ideon sheds on other sources. To explore the arguments and assess their cogency, I need to take stands on a variety of topics in Plato and Aristotle. To defend all my views in detail would have made an already long and complicated book even longer and more complicated. But in Ch. 4 I indicate my views on some of the central issues. Although this account is not as detailed or as thoroughly defended as it perhaps should be, I hope that it at least provides a framework for what follows. For my own part, it was only after much labour that the point of the Preface ix Peri ideon and its sources in the dialogues became clear to me. But the effort revealed to me a richness and depth in the dialogues and in the Peri ideon that I had not initially suspected. I hope that the light the Peri ideon casts on Aristotle and on various Platonic passages proves as illuminating for others as it did for me. An earlier version of Ch. 8 appeared as The One over Many', Philosophical Review, 89 (1980), 197-240; an earlier version of parts of Ch. ii appeared as 'Owen's Progress: A Review of Logic, Science, and Dialectic', Philosophical Review, 97 (1988), 373-99. The present versions appear here by permission of Cornell University. An earlier version of Ch. 9 appeared as 'The Object of Thought Argument: Forms and Thought', in Apeiron: A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science, 21 (1988), 105-46; the present version appears here by permission of Academic Printing and Publishing. An earlier version of Ch. 13 appeared as 'Aristotle's Criticisms of Plato', J. Klagge and N. Smith (eds.), in Methods of Interpreting Plato and his Dialogues, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Supplementary Volume (1992), 13-41. An earlier version of part of Ch. 14 appeared as 'Aristotle and the More Accurate Arguments', in M. Nussbaum and M. Schofield (eds.), Language and Logos (Cambridge University Press, 1982), 155-77. I gratefully acknowl- edge permission to use portions of these earlier articles. I am also grateful to the Casa Editrice Leo S. Olschki for permission to reprint Harlfinger's text of the Peri ideon. In writing this book, I have acquired a number of debts that I am pleased to record. I have been greatly influenced by G. E. L. Owen, both by his classes and by his published writings (now collected in Logic, Science, and Dialectic), and also by his unpublished manuscript on the Peri ideon (on deposit in the Classics Library in Cambridge University). I thank Mrs Sally Owen for giving me permission to consult Owen's manuscript before it was available to the public. Since 1975, I have had the great privilege of being a member of the Sage School of Philosophy at Cornell University. The friendliness, support, and stimulation that I have received from many colleagues and students has been remarkable. I should especially like to thank Sydney Shoemaker and Nicholas Sturgeon, both of whom provided encourage- ment as well as insightful comments, both written and oral, on various versions of various chapters; and Norman Kretzmann, who also provided encouragement, and who read and commented helpfully on most of a penultimate version. In 1982-3, while on a National Endowment for the Humanities fellow- ship, I was a Visiting Fellow at Brasenose College, Oxford; and in 1987 I was a Visiting Fellow at Wolf son College, Oxford. I should like to thank
Description: