ebook img

Nietzsche and Plato on Ancestral Authority PDF

266 Pages·2017·1.84 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Nietzsche and Plato on Ancestral Authority

Google, Grandfathers, and God(s): Nietzsche and Plato on Ancestral Authority by Janice Freamo A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate and Postdoctoral Affairs in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Political Science Carleton University Ottawa, Ontario © 2017, Janice Freamo Abstract The ever-changing technological landscape is shifting generational patterns of authority. Authority is grounded in knowledge. Knowledge—technical, moral, or otherwise— commonly proceeds from an older generation to a younger one. This is changing. Younger generations in the Western world are posing their questions to Google rather than Grandpa or God. Such challenges to the hierarchy of generational knowledge are not entirely novel though, and the history of Western political thought suggests that they are telling indicators of impending political change. The study engages two examples, one in Nietzsche (“Second Treatise” of On the Genealogy of Morality) and one in Plato (“Book One” of The Republic), wherein lapsed generational authority is discussed alongside the topic of justice. In the texts, both authors proceed from a definition of justice associated with ancestral authority and described in the language of debt and credit. Justice is what is owed to one’s ancestors. Ancestral knowledge provides the first codification of duties or obligations. It is the first sense of law. It describes a clear division between the ruler (to whom one’s obligations are due) and the ruled. To date, the vast literature on these authors has not yet considered how the precise concept of ancestral authority informs the political meaning of their works. This is particularly the case for Nietzsche. The contest that he invokes with Plato, his philosophical ancestor, requires meditation on the significance of this idea. This ii comparative analysis meets this objective in two ways. First, it analyzes the selections to understand what happens politically and philosophically when the primary direction of intergenerational education changes. Second, it proposes that Nietzsche’s politics of cultural formation should be understood as a non-nostalgic recovery of ancestral authority. This concept is central in Nietzsche’s understanding of the shift from kinship- based models of justice to what he calls in §12 of the Second Treatise, “misarchism” or the “democratic idiosyncrasy” of being against the idea of rule itself. His account of justice describes the theological conditions that informed the shift from tribalism to universalism in the West, and, by this account, he forces an assessment of the limits of overwriting the grandfathers’ generational knowledge. iii Acknowledgements A project of this nature is not an individual feat. I owe a great deal of gratitude to those who inspired it in the first place, those who sustained it over the course of its development, and those who saw it through to its present state of completion. Its muses were two. My paternal grandmother, Mary Mandryk, and my husband’s grandfather, “Poppa” John Stelter (now deceased), loom large in the thoughts behind these pages. As I witnessed the societal reception of this generational cohort, and closer to home, the familial dynamics brought on by their advancing age and greater need of care, I began to think about intergenerational relationships, and whether or how they were changing. As a line in one of my daughter’s books goes, “some questions are tricky and some hold on tight.” This was such a question for me. I am fortunate enough to be married to a man who knows and appreciates the grip of such questions and the value of the intellectual endeavour and with whom I could repeatedly discuss and revisit the fundamentals of the project. It is impossible to do justice to my husband John’s contribution in a sentence or even two. So, let it suffice to say that I could not be more grateful that he was the one to share the highs and lows of this journey with me. I am also fortunate to have built a broader community of such friends, and mentors, included among them my supervisor Tom Darby and committee members Marc Hanvelt, Robert Sibley, and Geoffrey Kellow. I imagine that it is often difficult for a supervisor to strike the correct balance between liberty and guidance with students, but this was something that Tom was able to achieve in our relationship, and I am grateful iv for it. Beyond my committee, the project was developed with, or portions of it read by, the following people: Nicole Van De Wolfshaar, Denis Madore, Larissa Atkinson, Colin Cordner (for assistance with Greek), Gillian Bose (for assistance with German), Megan Pickup (for assistance with life!), Caleb Chaplin (for our writing exchanges), and my mother, Mary Rudyk-Papadogonas, who braved reading my commentary on Nietzsche. Additionally, over the course of the project’s development, I had the opportunity to study at the University of Chicago with the Fulbright Canada program. During that time the project benefitted immensely from the guidance of Martha Nussbaum, Nathan Tarcov, Heinrich Meier, Demetra Kasimis, and Brian Leiter. Last, the project was supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (SSHRC) as well as the Ontario Graduate Scholarships (OGS) program. These acknowledgements themselves confirm one of the central arguments in the pages that follow. Humans, including political philosophers who seem to claim god-like capacities, are not self-sufficient beings. We do, and we must, exist with others. This is not something to be disparaged. It is part of the beauty of what it means to be human. It is part of the chaotic beauty of love and friendship that informs who we are as political animals, that I hope to be able to help my daughter, Marian, to see as she grows up in this messy, but wonderful, and all-too-human world. That is a promise to her that I will be honoured to keep. v Table of Contents Abstract .......................................................................................................................................... ii Acknowledgements .................................................................................................................... iv Table of Contents ........................................................................................................................ vi Introduction .................................................................................................................................. 1 1 Philosophy, Poetry, and Politics........................................................................................ 48 1.1 Dialogical writing ...................................................................................................... 53 1.2 Plato's Phaedrus .......................................................................................................... 58 1.3 Nietzsche's Zarathustra .............................................................................................. 66 1.4 Analytics and Hermeneutics .................................................................................... 81 1.5 Authority .................................................................................................................... 88 2 Debt and Bad-Conscience: The Problem of the Ancestral in Genealogy II............. 100 2.1 Approach and Assumptions .................................................................................. 104 2.2 Related Matters ........................................................................................................ 106 2.3 The Question of Nature .......................................................................................... 108 2.4 Promising .................................................................................................................. 115 2.5 Punishment and Bad Conscience .......................................................................... 124 2.6 Debt, Credit, and Guilt............................................................................................ 131 2.7 Ancestors and God(s) .............................................................................................. 142 3 Promises, Piety, and Paternity: The Problem of Cephalus in Republic I ............... 162 3.1 Approach and Assumptions .................................................................................. 167 vi 3.2 Related Matters ........................................................................................................ 173 3.3 The Mythic and Ancestral ...................................................................................... 179 3.4 The Old and New .................................................................................................... 185 3.5 Exit the Father .......................................................................................................... 198 4 The Problem of Plato's Socrates .................................................................................... 204 4.1 Exit Eros .................................................................................................................... 208 4.2 Enter Efficiency ........................................................................................................ 214 4.3 Heroes, Young and Old .......................................................................................... 218 Conclusion ............................................................................................................................... 228 Bibliography ............................................................................................................................. 249 vii INTRODUCTION Google, Grandfathers, and God(s): Nietzsche and Plato on Ancestral Authority “But,” said the accuser, “Socrates taught his companions to abuse their fathers by persuading them that he made them wiser than their fathers.” — Xenophon, Memorabilia God is dead. God remains dead. And we have killed him. — Nietzsche, The Gay Science In the past there were always some elders who knew more than any children in terms of their experience of having grown up within a cultural system. Today there are none. It is not only that parents are no longer guides, but that there are no guides, whether one seeks them in one’s own country or abroad. There are no elders who know what those who have been reared within the last twenty years know about the world into which they were born. — Margaret Mead, Culture and Commitment Mobile phones, satellite television, and the Internet have allowed the newer generations to associate, connect, and debate on a “peer-to-peer” basis rather than through a top- down, authoritarian system of knowledge transmission. The young feel less strongly bound to patriarchal customs and institutions… — Olivier Roy, “The Transformation of the Arab World” Researchers found that older generations are being replaced by Google, Wikipedia and YouTube, with their grandchildren not asking them basic questions that they can look up themselves. — The Telegraph1 The Problem: Lapsed Generational Authority In middle school, when my English teacher was struggling to have our class embrace a particular point about a novel we were reading, she mentioned to the class 1 The Telegraph reported on the results of a poll taken of 1,500 grandparents that indicated younger generations were requesting less advice or knowledge from them than previous generations. Less than one in four had advice requested of them, and ninety-six percent indicated that they requested more advice of their grandparents when they were young. See “How Grandparents are being replaced by Google,” n.p. 1 that she understood our reluctance. Not long ago she had lived by the maxim “don’t trust anyone over 30.” She was now past the threshold of that age and asking us to trust her, and the text and its author, who were surely much older than that. At the time, I took it for granted that she should even feel the need to make that plea to a room full of pre-teens. The following study considers the political and philosophical consequences when the primary direction of intergenerational education changes. In its broadest sense, it asks: of what significance is it that children learn more from each other than from ‘those over 30’? Intergenerational education refers to the way in which knowledge—technical, moral, or otherwise—is commonly seen to proceed. This is typically understood in a linear fashion. It proceeds from an older generation to a younger one. This is changing. Specific language has been adopted to describe the challenger to this model. In classrooms,2 governments,3 and private sector enterprises, the “peer-to-peer”4 networked model exemplifies this change in generational priority. Peers are equal participants in the network. This is contrast to “command-and-control” models wherein hierarchical structures determine the decision-making processes, and 2 As an example, see Topping, “Trends in Peer Learning,” 631–45. 3 The Government of Canada has been pursuing this through their Blueprint 2020 and Workplace 2.0 initiatives. See Clerk of the Privy Council, Twentieth Annual Report to the Prime Minister, 8. 4 “Peer-to-peer” (P2P) describes a computational structure, wherein “peers” are the computer systems that connect to a network (Internet) and act simultaneously as clients and servers (or senders and receivers of data) eliminating the need for a centralized server that distributes data. As Baker describes, “The P2P model can be used to reframe the concept of organizational leadership and organizational architecture. It enables us to take a fresh new look at the authoritarian and centralized notions of current organizational leadership approaches. While traditional hierarchies place emphasis on a certain chain of command, P2P architecture places emphasis on the organizing and indexing of data (both archival, real-time inputs), so that nodes in the organization act as both servers and clients (senders and receivers) of the data. In this model, the network itself becomes the leader as it constantly computes raw data and turns it into actionable information.” See Peer-to-Peer Leadership, n.p. 2 place greater or lesser value on its members based on their rank in the order. Younger generations in the Western world are posing their questions to Google rather than Grandpa or God. The ever-changing technological landscape challenges traditional structures of authority. While it may be benign to use a food blogger's recipe for chocolate chip cookies instead of Grandma's, this process of knowledge transmission and its reconfiguration deserves reflection. This is particularly the case when we turn from matters of technical knowledge to moral or ethical codes and to the political structures associated therewith. In other words, it is one thing to understand how authority is construed in the sharing of a certain expertise among friends, and it is another thing to understand its moral, political and educational dimensions. This is notable because these peer-to-peer exchanges propose to answer the question of what is best. They advise new parents of the best home remedy for their child, or foodies of the best taco stand in the city, or citizens of the best candidate for political office. Digital forums amplify peer-exchanges and, in the process, diminish the voices of experts, in part because there is a collective loss of trust in what had constituted expertise. All opinions are validated, or at least so the idea of relativism proclaims. Post-truth conditions are pre-conditions for political upheaval. Such challenges to the hierarchy of generational knowledge are not entirely novel though. The history of Western5 political thought confirms that they are telling indicators of impending political change. The following study will take up two 5 One of the epigrams that open this introduction makes reference to the Arab world. I include this to allude to the idea that the discussion of intergenerational dynamics is not one that is limited geographically and should be properly considered alongside questions concerning globalization. 3

Description:
The study engages two examples, one in Nietzsche (“Second Treatise” of On the nicht gerade jene paradoxe Aufgabe selbst, welche sich die Natur in Hinsicht .. character traits are deemed virtuous or vicious. Cast in another manner, the human disappears into the cycle of patterned change in
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.