ebook img

NATURE AND GRACE IN THE THEOLOGY OF SAINT AUGUSTINE PDF

125 Pages·06.324 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview NATURE AND GRACE IN THE THEOLOGY OF SAINT AUGUSTINE

THE UNIVERSITY OP CHICAGO NATURE AND GRACE IN THE THEOLOGY OP SAINT AUGUSTINE With Special Reference to the Confessions and the Anti-Pelagian Writings A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OP THE DIVINITY SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OP MASTER OP ARTS BY<- X THOMAS J. :J/ALTIZER ii CHICAGO, ILLINOIS JUNE, 1951 Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission. TABLE OP CONTENTS Page Chapter I. INTRODUCTION The Historical Significance of St. Augustine On the Method of St. Augustine The Problem of the Present Thesis II. SAINT AUGUSTINE’S CONCEPTION OP NATURE .......... 22 Against Manicheanism God and Nature Evil and Privation Evil and Creation Nature as Being and Nature as Creature III. SAINT AUGUSTINE’S DOCTRINE OP SIN AND GRACE . . . $1 St. Augustine’s Conversion St. Augustine and Pelagianism St. Augustine’s Doctrine of Original Sin The Meaning of Sin St. Augustine’s Doctrine of Grace Freedom and Grace IV. CONCLUSION................................... 91 A Roman Catholic Solution St. Augustine: the Man and the Problem Classical Nature and Christian Nature Nature, Grace, and God BI3LI0GRAPHY ........................................... 120 ii Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission. CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION The Historical Significance of St. Augustine A zealous admirer of St. Augustine might insist that the rise and fall of theology reflects the path of the history of Augustinianism. Certainly, the three great periods in the his­ tory of post-Patristic theology: the high Middle Ages, the Ref­ ormation, and the twentieth century, were periods of a return to many of the theological problems which were central to St. Augus­ tine. The very structure of Western dogmatics was largely laid by the work of St. Augustine. For, the history of dogma in the West was so thoroughly dominated by St. Augustine from the begin­ ning of the fifth century to the era of the Reformation, that the historian may properly take this whole time as forming but one period.Thus, in reconsidering an Augustinian problem, the mod­ ern student is not delving into the dusty pages of a deservedly forgotten past; but, is, in fact, coming into contact with one of the very foundations of Western theology itself. Another dimen­ sion of his historical significance which has found renewed empha­ sis in contemporary discussion lies in the relation of the Classi­ cal and the Hebrew Weltanschauungsn in the substructure of his ■^Adolph Harnack, History of Dogma, trans. Neil Buchanan (Boston: Little, Brown and Company, .1599)» V, 3* 1 - - Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission. thought. In fact, the present inquiry is but a sub-topic of this general problem. The crucial point here is that many critics think that it was not until the time of St. Augustine that Greek and Jewish thought was brought into a dynamic and enduring synthe­ sis. Augustine provided a new way for Christian thought not only with his dogmatic efforts but also with his philosophical Inquiries which helped lay the basic foundations for the Christian thought of the West. As Charles Norris Cochrane points out: For, by pressing to a logical conclusion the implication of the new starting-point, he completed the effort of thought initiated by the Fathers and laid the foundation of what he claimed to be "ours, the one true philosophy." In Augustine we may then perceive the full meaning of the Evangel as it presented itself to the mind of the fourth century and there­ with, the measure of the revolution in attitude and outlook which resulted from the impact of Christianity upon the Graeco- Roman world.1 One of the most difficult obstacles in Augustinian studies to the modern mind, living as it does in a world of specialisa­ tions, is the vastness of St. Augustine^ thought. Yet, his work did not merely extend over most of the great areas of the intel­ lectual life. It was so organically ordered, that despite an ap­ parent disparity of content, it comprehensively included the mind of the Church itself. Hence, Friedrich Heiler has said: "What makes Augustine marvelous and indeed unique is that his character is a microcosm which comprehends the entire range of that macros- cosm, the Church."^ 3h his consideration of St. Augustine as a Christian teacher, Adolph Harnack asserts that he reconstructed ^Charles Norris Cochrane, Christianity and Classical Culture (London: Oxford University Press, 19i)4), p. 399. ^Quoted by Kenneth E. Kirk, The Vision of God (London: Longmans, Green and Co., 1932), p. 3 Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission. -3- § and connected absolutely three great circles of thought, thereby I I assuring himself of a lasting influence. Harnack then sets these P [i three circles forth as follows: In the first place, he built up a complete circle of con­ ceptions which is marked by the categories, "God, the soul,' alienation from God, irresistible grace, hunger for God, un­ rest in the world and rest in God, and felicity." a circle in which we can easily demonstrate the cooperation of Neoplatonic and monastic Christian elements, but which is really so pure and simple that it can be taken as the fundamental form of monotheistic piety in general. Secondly, he gave expression to a group of ideas in which sin, grace through Christ, grace in general, faith, love, and hope forms the main points; a Paulinism modified by popular Catholic elements. Thirdly, he constructed':another group, in which the Catholic Church is regarded as authority, dispenser of grace, and administrater of the sacraments, and, further, as the means and aim of all God’s ordinances | However, St. Augustine’s significance is not to be summed up in ;-j theology alone. Augustine was also a philosophical Father of the 1 ij West. A contemporary historian of philosophy, Richard McKeon, ] has pointed out that the philosophy of Augustine, whatever its ’i | origin, was to determine the problems, and in part even the con- 2 1 elusions, of a thousand years of philosophers. But perhaps more « | important even that this influence is the fact that, "in his work 1 there emerges, for the first time, a system of Christian philos- l ophy."3 Historians of Ideas are often much more concerned to demon­ strate the proposition that the real origin of modern philosoph­ ical Introspection and subjectivism does not lie in the Italian ■^■Harnack, op. clt., V, 1|. ^Richard McKeon (ed.), Selections from Medieval Philos­ ophers (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1929), I, 3* " 3Ibid. Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission. A 1 Renaissance, or in the philosophy of Descartes, but, in fact, in 1 1 f the creative work of this great Patristic doctor of the Church* •■I Ever since Pascal, critics have pointed out that Descartes’ fa- '•'i - mous "cognito ergo sum” is repeated many times in an only slightly i different form in the writings of St. Augustine. Moreover, if St. Augustine's teachings about nature and the self are to have any cogency, they must be seen in the light of his discovery of the centrality of the inner life. W. Windelband has asserted that: The line of thought in which medieval philosophy essen­ tially moved, and in which it continued the principle of the philosophy of antiquity, was proscribed for it by the doctrine of Augustine. He had moved the principle of intemality (Innerlichkeit), which had been preparing in the whole clos­ ing development of ancient science, for the first time into the controlling-central position of philosophic thought, and the position to which he is entitled in the history of philes- 5 ophy is that of the beginner of a new line of development. - The contents of the inner life lay clearly before Augustine’s eyes as a realm of distinctive objects of perception independent of perceptory experience. In truth, he was convinced that in this I sphere a genuine knowledge and information based on inner experi­ ence could be arrived at which was just as genuine as an empirical knowledge of external nature. St. Augustine brought to an end the I development of ancient philosophy by completing the process which lead from the naive objective to the subjective objective. He found what had long been looked for: the making of the inner life Note especially the essay of Erich Przywara in the sym- i posium entitled, A Monument to Saint Augustine (London: Sheed & ] Ward, 19i|5)» PP* 2i;9-256. 1 I ^W. Windelband, A History of Philosophy, trans. James H. j Tufts (New York: The Macmillan Co., 1093)» p. 270. Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission. -5- the starting-point of reflection on the world.^ Yet, Augustine went even further than this. Principles which he derived from the inner life became his general criteria of certitude. For the first time, the criteria of epistemelogical certitude were derived from self-consciousness. As Angel C. Vega sums it up: Knowledge of oneself, as the primary guarantee of the truth of our concepts; the existence of thought, as the first incontrovertible affirmation of the mind; the existence of the Ego as the first object of consciousness, the existence of Consciousness as the first criterion of our internal acts, and the fundamental basis of our certitude; the introspective method, the hypothetical doubt, the theory of mental aberra­ tion— all these criteria of certitude originated with St. Augustine.^ All of Augustine’s philosophical ideas centered about the principle of the absolute and immediate certainty of con­ sciousness. In fact, all of these ideas have their ultimate ground and inner union in the principle of the immediate certainty of inner experience, which Augustine first expressed with complete clearness, and formulated and used as the starting-point of philos­ ophy. 3 Accordingly, Etienne Gilson asserts that, "in proportion as the teaching of St. Augustine arrived at being a metaphysics, it is a metaphysics based upon a psychological empiricism, or, if preferred, a metaphysics of inner experience.”^- But from the very ^arnack, op. clt.. V, 107. p Angel C. Vega, Saint Augustine: His Philosophy, trans. Denis J. Kavanaugh (Philadelphia: The Peter Reilly Company, 1931)» p. 47. | ^Windelband, op. clt., p. 276. ^Etienne Gilson, ”The Future of Augustinian Metaphysics,” •j A Monument to St. Augustine, pp. 302-303. 1 •I Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission. beginning of his career as a philosopher, Augustine had insisted that God is not only the center of all philosophy but is the end of all philosophizing.^- In the second book of his Soliloquies, Augustine has said that, "All human knowledge involves the presence of God, all attainment of truth is the knowledge of God, all things ? are real insofar as they are like God." Whereas pagans fell into error into the ordering of their knowledge because they assigned to each science an independent domain, the Christian philosopher can recognize the affinities of the sciences to each other for all would be unintelligible save in view of their common source. Thus, God is first in philosophy, because He is the beginning and end of all things. Richard McKeon has judiciously asserted: That God is present in all knowledge is particularly rel­ evant to the knowledge of the soul since of all knowledge that of the existence of thought is most certain; and it can in turn be made the basis of other certainties. Therefore Augus­ tine’s exquisite gift of self-analysis and introspection, by which he is enabled to describe with precision the most deli­ cate phenomena of intimate life, is turned wholly to the inti­ mation of God.3 In the true philosophy, the mind grasps God first as truth, after Him the soul, after the soul the body, after the body, other bodies. Hence, to the Classical scholar.McKeon, philosophy must consist of an inversion of perspective towards things, and the mind must be prepared for it as for an initiation.^- The work of philosophy is ^William Pearson Tolley, The Idea of God in the Philosophy of St. Augustine (New York: Richard R. Smith, Inc., 1930), p. 2Solil. ii. 13. 7, 8. 3McKeon, op. cit., I, 7* frlbid., I, 10. Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission. if first a work of conversion, and it is not without reason that Gilson considers Augustine’s philosophy to be a metaphysics of 1 conversion. But philosophically, at least, this conversion con- sists largely in a reorientating of the mind so that it looks not f-i "'5 .j at itself and God through nature but at nature through itself and • J God. Self-knowledge is then fundamental in the knowledge of the I world. In fact, Augustine reached the revolutionary principle ■1 p j that truth, formally considered, can exist only in the intellect. :j "Go not outside, return to thyself." "Within the man dwells ■\ truth. "3 I • With regard to the problem of nature and grace, Hamack asserts that St. Augustine, "was the first to separate nature and •1 l-j grace, two spheres which men had long attempted unsuccessfully to I divide: but by this means he connected religion and morality, and :! gave a new meaning to the idea of the good."^- Augustine dialec- ;j tically developed the Christian idea of the good so that it encom- passed and surpassed all that Classical ethics had arrived at, thus, ; probably effecting a crowning victory over Classical culture. It .j is in this area that the problem of the present thesis lies. But i it is important to insist at the outset that Augustine’s work is j . j so organically related that it is only with grave risk that the j ] historian can consider any given problem in abstraction from the j •‘•Etienne Gilson, The Spirit of Medieval Philosophy, trans. j A. H. C. Downes (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 19ij.O), p. 131. j Vega, op. cit., p. 208 i ^Quoted by Vega, Ibid. ] ^Harnack, op. cit., V, 6£. Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission. H rest* If only for this reason the present study will suffer in 2 ■i I its necessary restriction of its data to the Confessions and the I anti-Pelagian writings. Consequently, it is important to set the A .3 problem of nature and grace into some sort of coherent relation •j I with the great areas of Augustine’s life work. If such a study were to be presented in its proper fullness, it would require a j life-time’s preparation. However, the present thesis will merely | be concerned with presenting the barest of outlines. On the Method of St. Augustine j An analysis of St. Augustine’s theological method is extremely difficult if only because of its comprehensiveness. As Hamack indicates,^ there are three planes in Augustine’s theolo-g- ; ical thought: Neoplatonic mysticism (without means of grace, I without the Church, and even, in a sense, without Christ), Christological soteriology, and the plane of the authority and i sacraments of the Church. The critic must deal carefully with j = each one of these planes and must always be careful to refrain ! from making judgments on the basis of one plane which would imply in their conclusions to those of all three. But there are other i ; factors in his method which present yet graver complications. i | Karl Adam has noted that: it isJcharacteristic of this fresh creative fertility of his i psychological habit of mind that he neglected the purely i logical relations and interconnections of the data which he ] had acquired, and did not seek to devise any neat and system- \ atic arrangement of his thought. His theological and phi- j losophical views tend to lie unconnected, in a relation of j mere juxtaposition to one another. He does not contrive, or ^Harnack, op. cit., V, 101+. I Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.