ebook img

Mortal Gods: Science, Politics, and the Humanist Ambitions of Thomas Hobbes PDF

346 Pages·2016·12.77 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Mortal Gods: Science, Politics, and the Humanist Ambitions of Thomas Hobbes

Mortal Gods MM oo rr ttaa ll GG oo dd ss SScciieennccee,, PPoolliittiiccss,, aanndd tthhee HHuummaanniisstt AAmmbbiittiioonnss ooff TThhoommaass HHoobbbbeess pp tt ee dd hh .. mm ii ll ll ee rr TThhee PPeennnnssyyllvvaanniiaa SSttaattee UUnniivveerrssiittyy PPrreessss UUnniivveerrssiittyy PPaarrkk,, PPeennnnssyyllvvaanniiaa Chapter 3 is a revised version of “Thomas Hobbes and the Constraints that Enable the Imitation of God,” Inquiry 42, no. 2 (1999): 149–76. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Miller, Ted H., 1965– Mortal gods : science, politics, and the humanist ambitions of Thomas Hobbes / Ted H. Miller. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. Summary: “Argues against the accepted idea that Thomas Hobbes turned away from humanism to pursue the scientific study of politics. Reconceptualizes Hobbes’s thought within early modern humanist pedagogy and the court culture of the Stuart regimes”—Provided by publisher. ISBN 978-0-271-04891-8 (cloth : alk. paper) 1. Hobbes, Thomas, 1588–1679. I. Title. II. Series. B1247.M49 2011 192—dc22 Copyright © 2011 The Pennsylvania State University All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America Published by The Pennsylvania State University Press, University Park, PA 16802–1003 It is the policy of The Pennsylvania State University Press to use acid-free paper. Publications on uncoated stock satisfy the minimum requirements of American National Standard for Information Sciences— Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Material, ansi z39.48–1992. This book is printed on Natures Natural, which contains 50% post-consumer waste. Contents Acknowledgments vi 1 Introduction 1 2 The Humanist Face of Hobbes’s Mathematics, Part 1 9 3 Constraints That Enable the Imitation of God 35 4 King of the Children of Pride: The Imitation of God in Context 55 5 Architectonic Ambitions: Mathematics and the Demotion of Physics 81 6 Eloquence and the Audience Thesis 115 7 All Other Doctrines Exploded: Hobbes, History, and the Struggle over Teaching 137 8 The Humanist Face of Hobbes’s Mathematics, Part 2: Leviathan and the Making of a Masque-Text 161 9 Conclusion 201 Appendix: Who Is a Geometer? 221 Notes 239 Bibliography 303 Index 333 aCknowledGMents I have accumulated many debts in writing this book. I can’t begin to repay them. I nevertheless wish to thank those who were there from the very begin- ning, and those who have come along later as the work continued. I am par- ticularly grateful for the assistance I have received from Tracy Strong, who saw this work from its earliest and now distant inception. I also have Gerald Doppelt, Alan Houston, Arthur Lupia, Steven Shapin, and Don Wayne to thank for their early comments and assistance. I’ve been sustained by good intellectual company as the ideas in this book made it to the page. For this I also owe thanks to Chris Dugan, Elizabeth Ellis, Verna Gehring, Bernard Gert, Christina Haddad, John Hughes, Nancy Luxon, Utz McKnight, James Murphy, James Philipp, Hans von Rautenfeld, John Richardson, Arlene Saxenhouse, Verity Smith, Pat Snyder, Marek Steadman, and Elizabeth Wingrove. Chris Laursen’s encouragement and comments from afar have always been more than helpful. I offer especially heartfelt thanks to Samantha Frost. She and Dean Mathiowetz were steadfast in their assistance. They allowed this work to reach a safe harbor. I owe particular thanks to Terry Royed for her companionship and encouragement. She has kept me going. J. David and Susan Miller were always there, interested and patient. Karen, Alan, Elana, and Michael Rubinstein were rooting for me. I also wish to single out Sandy Thatcher for his interest, and his integrity as an editor. Dan O’Neill gets the credit for sending me to Sandy. I have also had the good fortune to work with Kendra Boileau and Stephanie Lang. I’m grateful for their invaluable assistance. I thank those institutions whose support was crucial to the completion of this project. This study would not have been possible were it not for the gener- ous grant and institutional assistance I received from the Huntington Library, the British Academy, the Earhardt and Mellon Foundations, Dartmouth College, and the University of Alabama. I also wish to thank the Chatsworth Devonshire Collection, in particular Andrew Peppitt and Peter Day, the librarians at Chatsworth, and Diane Naylor for her assistance in procuring the images from the collection used in this book. 1 introduction Alexis de Tocqueville is not, perhaps, the first name readers of an interpreta- tion of Thomas Hobbes would expect to see. For some, it will correctly stand as a marker of the eclecticism of North American political theory. Neverthe- less, every interpretation must have an origin, and this one is no exception. It emerges from within the broad, relatively fragmented and freewheeling constellation of curiosities of political theory as it is primarily practiced in departments of political science in the United States and Canada. These departments are staffed by a community of practitioners long interested in Hobbes, but often resistant to those readings which celebrate him as a pio- neer of social science, or hold up his work as an early model of analytic phi- losophy.1 This reading is, in part, an extension of that tradition of resistance. De Tocqueville declared history’s trajectory to be the inevitable growth and progress of equality. Equality was an “irresistible revolution advancing century by century.”2 There is a straightforward way to connect Hobbes to this master narrative. By making men equals in the state of nature, Hobbes rejected the premises that sustained the hierarchical ways of understanding the natural, social, and political orders rooted within the doctrines of the schools, churches, and courts. As such, he is a part of the history of equality’s progress.3 As de Tocqueville insisted, though, that progress was (and still is) haphaz- ard. One can imagine, says de Tocqueville, an “extreme point” where liberty and equality would “meet and blend.”4 All having an equal right to participate in government, and all being equal, no one would be able to exercise tyran- nical power. Along the way, however, the two principles are realized neither at the extreme nor simultaneously, but distinctly and unevenly. Here again, a connection to Hobbes can be made. Hobbes moved from the equality of his state of nature to the gaping inequality embodied in the absolute sovereign’s relation to his or her subjects. In accord with the ideology of absolutism, Hobbes declares that the sovereign must outshine all the other subjects like the sun outshines the stars.5 The thirst for equality, de Tocqueville thought, 2 p mortal gods could bring about tyranny. It could be of the absolutist variety, or the tyranny of the majority, which he feared most. Both the absolute sovereign and the sovereign majority might be compared to gods; they are likened to entities that dwarf all others with their power (and make them more equal to each other in their common subjection).6 When Hobbes speaks of his sovereign as a “Mortal God,”7 it is useful to think of what he hoped to assemble, but also, with de Tocqueville, what he was taking apart. His work was also an assault on the intermediary institutions between the sovereign and the people such as the established church,8 the nobility, and the courts. In so far as his philosophy insisted upon a unified form of sovereignty that need not take the form of an assembly, it was also an assault on Parliament. For my immediate purposes, however, these initial points of connection to de Tocqueville can give way to another, perhaps less straightforward link. It concerns not merely de Tocqueville, but also the sometimes tangled relation- ship between some committed Tocqueville scholars and the audiences that make use of de Tocqueville for their own purposes. Alan S. Kahan, author of Aristocratic Liberalism: The Social and Political Thought of Jacob Burckhardt, John Stuart Mill, and Alexis de Tocqueville, wrote of de Tocqueville (and his two other subjects) that “the interpreters of aristocratic liberals are all too often ready to ignore the issues and circumstances . . . [these thinkers] thought crucial. Instead of asking the three what their questions were, we ask them our own questions, and as a result get an answer that is distorted and misun- derstood.”9 Hobbes scholars have undertaken their own reclamation efforts. Hobbes, they have declared, must be spared our purposes and given back to his own. Among Hobbes scholars, these sentiments will bring to mind the “con- textualist” approach of the Cambridge School historians. I will discuss the relationship between contextualist readings and the status of “his own” below. In light of the goals of this interpretation, de Tocqueville’s would-be rescuers offer a more poignant dynamic. They, of course, resist certain pres- entist readings by insisting that we understand de Tocqueville as a man of the nineteenth century (if not a man whose life was primarily determined years before by the French Revolution). They also, and more interestingly, caution against reading de Tocqueville as if his intended audience was in fact (or at least necessarily) the society of relative equals within the United States. They urge us to consider that his foremost audience may have been the frightened aristocrats of his native France. In short, they raise the possibility that Democracy in America was not aimed toward the sensi- bilities of our time and the political events that consume us. Democracy in America is not “ours,” they suggest, because it was not written to appeal to introduction p 3 today’s egalitarians, much less those whom it describes. The book critically defends democratic ways to an inegalitarian aristocratic culture still trying to find its footing in early nineteenth-century France.10 For whom did Thomas Hobbes write? My purpose is not to duplicate the reservations urged upon readers by the de Tocqueville scholars. Hobbes is not warning one class that another is coming to replace it. The differences between our society and Hobbes’s are in many ways unlike the differences between our society and de Tocqueville’s. In both cases, however, our demo- cratic sensibility is offended by the suggestion that the texts of these two men are not immediately ours.11 Nevertheless, the example of de Tocqueville should prompt useful questions about how to approach Hobbes. Why should we be more attentive to where Hobbes’s audiences stood within the hier- archical cosmos of seventeenth-century Britain? In short, because doing so gives us a better appreciation of Hobbes’s politics. We should therefore ask: what did it mean to address oneself, or to offer a philosophical doctrine, to a sovereign one would make absolute? We can gain new and important insights into Hobbes’s politics if we try to discern how he negotiated (in the full sense) these distinctly seventeenth-century contexts and their attending practices. More specifically, I will read Hobbes in light of the practices of humanist education, patronage, and what I call the high culture of practical mathematics that were a part of seventeenth-century Britain’s most imagina- tive plastic arts. Against the trajectory of this—or any contextual—approach one might raise a hermeneutic objection. Any reader—in fact, all readers, whether they acknowledge it or not—will reveal that the text they interpret is always for them because it cannot be otherwise.12 My interpretation always makes a book mine, and your interpretation makes it yours. In a broader historical frame, we, today, make the books we interpret ours. This argument seems to me undeni- able, but if we must always make an author ours, the example of de Tocqueville suggests that one of the more fruitful ways to make an author ours is to make him untimely: “acting counter to our time and thereby acting on our time.”13 That is, the interpreted author who will necessarily be made ours can be ours in the way we make them not theirs. In this case “not theirs” does not mean deny- ing authors their contexts, or more aptly, what we think of as their contexts. It means working from those contexts to pull him or her away from some of our contemporaries. In fact, this reading works toward a doubly untimely Hobbes. I make arguments for taking Hobbes away from his scientific admirers,14 and for bringing him, I hope, too close for comfort to those who typically think of themselves as having achieved maximal distance from him.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.