ebook img

Moral Particularism PDF

332 Pages·2001·4.388 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Moral Particularism

Moral Particularism Edited by BRAD HOOKER and MARGARET OLIVIA LITTLE CLARENDON PRESS · OXFORD MORAL PARTICULARISM This book has been printed digitally and produced in a standard specification in order to ensure its continuing availability OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS Great Clarendon Street, Oxford OX2 6DP Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford NewYork Auddand Bangkok Buenos Aires Cape Town Chennai Dares Salaam Delhi Hong Kong Istanbul Karad1i Kolkata Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Mumbai Nairobi Sao Paulo Shanghai Taipei Tokyo Toronto Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York ©The several contributors 2000 The moral rights of the author have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) Reprinted 2003 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under tenus agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer ISBN 0-19-823883-5 CONTENTS Introduction Vll List of Contributors Xll 1. Moral Particularism: Wrong and Bad BRAD HOOKER 2. Particularizing Particularism 23 RoGER CRISP 3. The Truth in Particularism 48 ]OSEPH RAZ 4. Ethical Particularism and Patterns 79 FRANK ]ACKSON, PHILIP PETTIT, AND MICHAEL SMITH 5. Ethics as an Inexact Science: Aristotle's Ambitions for Moral Theory 100 T. H. IRWIN 6. The Particularist's Progress 130 JoNATHAN DANCY 7. Ethical Particularism in Context 157 DAVID BAKHURST 8. Particularity and Principle: The Structure of Moral Knowledge 178 ]AY GARFIELD 9. Against Deriving Particularity 205 LAWRENCE BLUM 10. Why Practice Needs Ethical Theory: Particularism, Principle, and Bad Behaviour 227 MARTHA NussBAUM 11. Unprincipled Ethics 256 DAVID McNAuGHTON AND PIERS RAWLING 12. Moral Generalities Revisited 276 MARGARET OLIVIA LITTLE Vl Contents Bibliography 305 Index 313 INTRODUCTION Brad Hooker and Margaret Olivia Little Moral particularism is currently one of the most widely discussed-and hotly contested-issues in ethical theory. Spurred in large part by reactions to the writings of John McDowell and Jonathan Dancy, philosophers con tinue to divide between those who find particularism's claims insightful and those who find them exaggerated or wrong-headed. Indeed, philoso phers continue to divide over how best to interpret what claims 'moral par ticularism' is meant to represent in the first place. In this collection, we present a dozen new essays by theorists who take up the controversy.' The collection begins with those who are sceptical of moral particularism. In Chapter 1, Brad Hooker argues that adherents of the doctrine are overly impressed with the dangers of moral principles. He contends that, while the search for such generalizations has at times led to crudeness in theory, the particularist's response of jettisoning such principles introduces dangers that are far deeper. Starting from the premise that certain 'non-trivial general rules seem overwhelmingly sensible', Hooker argues that, once we isolate what particularism must claim in order to count as a distinctive thesis, we will see that the arguments proffered in its favour are unpersuasive. Indeed, faith ful followers of particularism would precisely fail to display the reliability we seek to develop in-and hope to rely on in-moral agents. Next, Roger Crisp in Chapter 2 distinguishes amongst various forms of particularism and argues that the true forms are uncontroversial and the controversial ones false. After arguing that self-described generalists can accommodate important insights about the incommensurability of values and the ineliminable need for judgement, Crisp criticizes the idea that underlies Jonathan Dancy's radical particularism, namely, the idea that a full specification of the reason for acting in some way can, in another con text, fail to constitute a reason or even constitute a reason for acting other wise. Crisp argues that such variance means that the reason cannot then be complete. Just as we do not in science take an explanation as complete if the 1 Two of the pieces, Joseph Raz's and (an expanded version of) Martha Nussbaum's, are also appearing in other fora. Introduction Vlll factors cited could in another case lead to the opposite result, we should not do so in ethics. Since Dancy himself demands that a difference in con siderations be cited when comparing two cases, Crisp urges, there is no good reason for stopping there. Joseph Raz continues to press on the particularist's model of explana tion. A sensible 'intelligibility principle' requires that there must be an explanation for the difference between a good and a bad action. If we agree that we must be able to cite a difference in pair-wise comparisons, we should agree that such a difference must be found more generally, and we recover pressure towards exceptionless principles. More specifically, on Dancy's view, a complete specification of an agent's reason for acting as he does can cite considerations that, in a different context, count as reasons against so acting. This means, Raz points out, that what determines the moral status of an action must extend beyond what the agent's reason for acting is. But this claim, Raz urges, 'drives a wedge' between the evaluative and the guiding functions of reasons, distorting what it is for an agent to be guided by reason in the first place. Frank Jackson, Philip Pettit and Michael Smith continue the sceptical press on particularism's notion of explanation, this time with a semantic argument. While particularism is compatible with the doctrine of moral supervenience (the doctrine, roughly, that any moral difference must be accompanied by some nonmoral difference), it must reject the idea that there are patterned nonmoral differences underlying attributions of moral properties. Yet this second claim, they urge, is essential to making sense of semantic competence with ethical concepts. The explanation of the consis tency in our use of our evaluative concepts has to find pattern in the nat ural. By abandoning the commitment to pattern at the natural level, the particularist renders mysterious how we could learn or justify our use of moral concepts and terms. In 'Ethics as an Inexact Science', T. H. Irwin argues that a close examina tion of Aristotle's texts indicates that he cannot, as it is often thought, be pressed into service as an ally to particularists. For Aristotle, some moral generalizations are, in certain respects, normatively prior to particulars in explanation, justification, and knowledge. Looking closely at Aristotle's acknowledgement that morality includes 'usual' generalizations, Irwin argues that Aristotle takes some moral principles with exceptions to be nat ural norms, not mere statistical frequencies. Irwin goes on to argue that, as in science, these moral principles are 'usual' not because the exceptions cannot be specified, but because an exhaustive specification of them would be irrelevant to the normative function of the principles. Introduction IX Next, in Chapters 6, 7, 8, and 9 comes a series of essays by theorists iden tified as broadly sympathetic to the particularist enterprise. Jonathan Dancy continues to advance the radical thesis that every consideration is capable of varied moral salience; his main concern, though, is not to defend this claim against possible exceptions but 'to break the stranglehold' of the generalist conceptions of how moral reasons must function. Emphasizing that particularism is an outcrop of holism, he argues that the latter allows us to understand why explanations of an action's moral status can be com plete without guaranteeing the same result in another context. Here he defends and expands the scope of his project to defend holism in the realm of epistemic and practical reasons, and in the realm of values and choice. He argues, intriguingly, that the availability of another alternative may change not just an agent's bottom-line decision, but a prior ranking of other alternatives. Dancy also argues that such a view is still compatible with the possibility offull ordering of values. In Chapter 7, David Bakhurst argues that the contextualism set forth in Alasdair Macintyre's After Virtue can be adjoined to Dancy's particularism to yield a more satisfying picture of the moral domain. A moral person must, as it were, have certain lingering commitments or concerns-she must set herself in favour of certain sorts of things and against others. Unless we can make sense of this, we can have no account of the structure of moral personality. To cash out these enduring concerns in terms of prin ciples conceived as rules of thumb, as particularists sometimes try to, is, Bakhurst thinks, implausible. So he tries to show how a particularist can think of such concerns as being directed to certain morally significant fea tures, and yet to do so in a way that does not contradict Dancy's idea that, in any particular case, the features in question may not be morally relevant per se (that is, they do not there contribute to the overall value of the case). Jay Garfield argues that if we take seriously certain broadly Aristotelian and Wittgensteinian lessons alluded to by John McDowell, we will see that particularism is not merely defensible, but superior as an account of moral epistemology and moral psychology. Exploring the issues through a sus tained examination of Ono ra O'Neill's writing, he distinguishes two kinds of rules. Some rules are capable of relatively mechanical application. But other rules, like moral principles, require experience to learn, judgement to apply, and admit of ever increasing expertise. Garfield defends a Wittgensteinian account of why consistency need not be found at the nat ural level, and argues that, far from straining our understanding of the moral life, such a view provides a better explanation of moral motivation and competency. X Introduction Lawrence Blum explores in detail one of the most important threads related to the debate over particularity and generality, namely, the role of partiality in the moral life. He applauds the renewed appreciation of par tiality in moral literature, but finds that claims to accommodate partiality's importance often, on closer examination, still turn out to judge the moral life by impartiality's lights. In this chapter, Blum distinguishes amongst, and argues against, different versions of this move, discussing in detail one such prominent attempt by certain consequentialists. The final three chapters are by theorists who, identified in their writ ings as sympathetic to particularism's lessons, seek here to refine or relo cate those lessons by reconsidering the proper roles of generality. Martha Nussbaum responds to the charge, common in some circles, that moral theory, especially in its Enlightenment versions, is needless and danger ous. She argues that such charges are misdirected. Invoking the Stoics' tri partite distinction amongst theories, rules, and concrete judgements, she argues that objections to moral theory are at best objections to the idea that such theory could reduce to a system of rules (a reduction, she adds, that no major historical figure has advanced). Rules of action, while use ful, do have limitations; they admit, for instance, of exceptions, and they set aside concern over the psychology of those who act. But theory, with its explicitness, abstraction, and generality, is precisely the arena that sup plements these limitations: for instance, by making perspicuous the 'point and purpose' of a given rule, it allows one to see where exceptions to it are warranted. Indeed, she argues, the real danger is presented by those who advocate the overthrow of theory; without abstraction and general ity, we could not have made the strides we have in the battle against injus tice. In 'Unprincipled Ethics: Piers Rawling joins with David McNaughton, one of the ground -breaking authors on particularism, to defend a brand of moderate particularism. They distinguish amongst different versions of 'intuitionism' by the types of properties to which one might deny invariant moral import. They agree that nonmoral features carry variant moral rel evance, since such features can enter moral principles only if they are understood as carrying evaluative riders (conditions that cannot be spelled out in purely nonmoral terms); but the same is not true of thick moral properties such as justice, which should be seen as carrying invariant moral valence. A more thoroughgoing particularism, according to which even thick moral properties are accorded variant moral valence, cannot happily explain the role that such concepts play in learning moral competency and justifying subsequent beliefs.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.