ebook img

Moore on Right and Wrong: The Normative Ethics of G. E. Moore PDF

212 Pages·1995·3.221 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Moore on Right and Wrong: The Normative Ethics of G. E. Moore

MOORE ON RIGHT AND WRONG PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES SERIES Founded by Wilfrid S. Sellars and Keith Lehrer Editor KEITH LEHRER, University ofA rizona, Tucson Associate Editor STEWART COHEN, Arizona State University, Tempe Board of Consulting Editors LYNNE RUDDER BAKER, University of Massachusetts at Amherst ALLAN GffiBARD, University of Michigan DENISE MEYERSON, University of Cape Town RONALD D. MILO, University ofA rizona, Tucson FRAN<:OIS RECANAT I, Ecole Poly technique, Paris STUART SILVERS, Clemson University NICHOLAS D. SMITH, Michigan State University VOLUME 61 MOORE ON RIGHT AND WRONG The Normative Ethics of G. E. Moore WILLIAM H. SHAW Department of Philosophy San Jose State University Springer-Science+Business Media, B.V. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Shaw, Will iam H., 1948- Moore on right and wrong the normative ethics of G. E. Moore I by William H. Shaw. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-90-481-4489-1 ISBN 978-94-015-8537-8 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-015-8537-8 1. Moore, G. E .. <George Edward), 1873-1958--Ethics. 2. Ethics. 1. Title. B1647.M74S48 1995 171' .2--dc20 94-38968 ISBN 978-90-481-4489-1 Printed on acid-free paper AII Rights Reserved © 1995 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1995 Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover lst edition 1995 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner. For Carolyn TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION 1 "GOOD" AND THE THINGS THAT ARE GOOD 8 The Naturalistic Fallacy 9 Organic Wholes 15 Against Hedonism 18 Goods aIid Evils 27 The Value of the Virtues 35 2 MOORE'S COMMITMENT TO CONSEQUENTIALISM Three Criticisms of Utilitarianism 41 A Closer Look at Utilitarianism 46 Good and Moral Obligation 53 Principia's Arguments 58 Moore's Later Account of "Right" 61 3 REBUTIALS AND REFINEMENTS 68 Attitudinal Theories of Ethics 68 Egoism 77 Duty and Expediency 81 Virtue Once More 85 Motives 89 4 LIMITS TO MORAL KNOWLEDGE 94 No Self-Evident Moral Rules 95 Prima Facie Duties 97 No Action Known to Be Our Duty 104 Overlooked Options 107 Future Reversals 109 Consequences, Actual and Probable 114 Retreating from Skepticism 120 Vll viii T ABLE OF CONTENTS 5 MORAL RULES 123 Justifying Moral Rules 123 The Rule against Murder 127 The Universal Core of Ordinary Morality 131 Rules Resting on Contingent Circumstances 135 Rules Not Generally Observed 140 Review and Reformulation 145 6 INDIVIDUAL MORAL CHOICE 148 Part I: Obeying the Rules 148 No Exceptions 149 Bad Examples 155 Three Things Moore Could Have Said 160 Part II: Beyond Rules 163 Situations without Valid Rules 164 Three Principles 167 CONCLUSION 179 BIBLIOGRAPHY 189 INDEX 195 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Sabbatical leave from San Jose State University made writing this book possible. I am indebted also to the following friends and colleagues for reading and commenting on all or part of my manuscript: Jonathan Bennett, Clement Dore, Sterling Harwood, Tom Leddy, Lucretia "Quee" Nelson, Rita Manning, Joe Waterhouse, and Andy Ward. Whatever its defects, this book is better than it would have been without their useful suggestions and insightful criticisms. I also thank Susan Neuhoff for her help in preparing the manuscript and Carolyn Martin Shaw for her wise counsel at every stage of the project. ix INTRODUCTION G. E. Moore was a central figure in twentieth-century philosophy. Along with Russell and Wittgenstein, he pioneered so-called analytic philos ophy, and his argumentative technique, his intellectual example, and his characteristic philosophical concerns have informed the way more than one generation of philosophers have approached their discipline. As a result, Moore's influence is hard to exaggerate. Even if few philoso phers today self-consciously adhere to any distinctively Moorean methods or philosophical tenets, his legacy is deeply and permanently embedded in Anglo-American philosophy. In no realm of philosophy has Moore's legacy been more significant than in ethics, and few, if any, would dissent from the judgment that "no philosopher had greater impact on Anglo-American moral phi losophy in the first half of the 20th century than G. E. Moore.") Moore's Principia Ethica of 1903 restructured the field, and for nearly seventy years, no single work in ethics was to have repercussions as profound. In Principia Moore saw the task of ethics as that of addressing certain basic questions. He undertook to formulate those questions with preci sion, to clarify the differences among them, and to define the funda mental concepts involved in, and specify the procedures appropriate to, answering them. This emphasis drove ethics toward conceptual analysis and away from synthetic and systematic moral theorizing. In large measure because of Principia Ethica, metaethical disputes came to dominate professional ethics; that is, disputes over the nature of moral judgment, the meaning of moral language, and the possibility, if any, of justifying ethical propositions. All sides to those debates agreed that metaethical questions represented the distinctive province of philo sophical ethics and that those questions needed to be answered before philosophers could usefully address substantive moral principles and concrete ethical problems. I Stephen Darwall, "Moore to Stevenson," p. 366. 2 INTRODUCTION Principia itself had argued that almost all prior moral theories were flawed at their foundations - guilty of what Moore called the "natural istic fallacy," that is, of viewing the truth of ethical propositions as in some way or other a function of natural facts. Moore was a cognitivist who believed that there are true ethical propositions and that we can know some of them. But his doctrine that ethical knowledge involves the appre hension of a nonnatural property (namely, goodness) never found as much favor as did his bracing critique of naturalism. Although this critique had a powerful impact, the appeal of Moore's nonnaturalistic cognitivism was, by contrast, relatively weak. In the decades following Principia, many philosophers who were persuaded by the former ended up abandoning cognitivism altogether in favor of the position that distinctively ethical discourse is not cognitive at all, but rather an expression of attitude or emotion. As a result of this development, twentieth-century metaethics has long been understood to be a three-way dispute among naturalism, nonnaturalism, and noncognitivism. Moore's challenge to naturalism still lies at the heart of metaethical debate, but philosophical discussion has, as one would expect, moved beyond Moore's contribution to that debate.2 Furthermore, philosophers no longer shy away from substantive ethical questions. In particular, since the publication of John Rawls's A Theory of Justice in 1971, many analytically minded philosophers have set aside traditional metaethical topics in order to investigate and assess normative principles and theories, on the one hand, and concrete moral issues (like abortion, capital pun ishment, and the treatment of animals), on the other. These considerations might lead one to doubt the contemporary relevance of Moore's contri bution to ethics. But such doubt would be misplaced. To be sure, the historical impact of Moore's work in ethics is gener ally understood to consist in the fact that it shaped the analytic character of twentieth-century ethics and framed the metaethical disputes that engaged philosophers for several decades but now seem slightly stale. Because the philosophical climate Moore helped to create reinforced the priority of issues of meaning, language, and justification, Moore's own contribution to ethics came to be seen as residing solely in his resistance to naturalism and in his thesis that "good" names a simple, 2 For an insightful review of current trends in metaethics, which sets them in the context of the controversy that Principia Ethica initiated, see Stephen Darwall, Allan Gibbard, and Peter Railton, "Toward Fin de siecle Ethics: Some Trends."

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.