ebook img

Montesquieu and Social Theory PDF

187 Pages·1979·3.41 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Montesquieu and Social Theory

Other Titles of Interest BUNGE, M. The Mind-Body Problem FITZGERALD, R. Human Needs and Politics What It Means To Be Human The Sources of Hope HARRIES, O. Liberty and Politics KHOSHKISH, A. The Socio-Political Complex LASZLO, E. The Inner Limits of Mankind: Heretical Reflections on Today's Values, Culture and Politics PECCEI, A. The Human Quality RICHARDS, T. The Language of Reason SCHAFF, A. Structuralism and Marxism TALMOR, E. Descartes and Hume Mind and Political Concepts TEVOEDJRE, A. Poverty: Wealth of Mankind WENK, E. Margins for Survival: Overcoming Political Limits in Steering Technology MONTESQUIEU AND SOCIAL THEORY by JOHN ALAN BAUM Assistant Dean of Social Science, Middlesex Polytechnic PERGAMON PRESS OXFORD • NEW YORK • TORONTO • SYDNEY • PARIS • FRANKFURT U.K. Pergamon Press Ltd., Headington Hill Hall, Oxford OX3 OBW, England U.S.A. Pergamon Press Inc., Maxwell House, Fairview Park, Elmsford, New York 10523, U.S.A. CANADA Pergamon of Canada, Suite 104, 150 Consumers Road, Willowdale, Ontario M2J 1P9, Canada AUSTRALIA Pergamon Press (Aust.) Pty. Ltd., P.O. Box 544, Potts Point, N.S.W. 2011, Australia FRANCE Pergamon Press SARL, 24 rue des Ecoles, 75240 Paris, Cedex 05, France FEDERAL REPUBLIC Pergamon Press GmbH, 6242 Kronberg-Taunus, OF GERMANY Pferdstrasse 1, Federal Republic of Germany Copyright ©1979 J. Alan Baum All Rights Reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means: electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without permission in writing from the publishers. First edition 1979 British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Baum, John Alan Montesquieu and social theory. 1. Montesquieu, Charles Louis de Secondat, baron de 2. Social sciences - France - History - 18th century I. Title 300\92'4 H59.M/ 79-40901 ISBN 0-08-024317-7 In order to make this volume available as economically and as rapidly as possible the author's typescript has been reproduced in its original form. This method has its typographical limitations but it is hoped that they in no way distract the reader. Printed and bound in Great Britain by William Clowes (Beccles) Limited, Beccles and London To the Memory of My Father JOHN KENNETH BAUM Acknowledgements This study is based upon a doctoral thesis submitted to the University of London in 1976. Of the many people who helped me in that endeavour a good number have continued to help in the writing of this book, especially Professor Donald MacRae of the London School of Economics and Professor J.D.Y. Peel of Liverpool University. I am much indebted to the British Academy for giving me a grant to pursue research in the libraries of Bordeaux and Paris during the summer of 1978 and to the Academie Montesquieu who helped me discover new material whilst in France. I would also like to thank friends and colleagues in the British Society for Eighteenth Century Studies for their guidance and inspiration and similarly to e members of the Socie*te franchise d'Etude du 18 Siecle whom I met at a joint conference of the two societies at Pembroke College, Oxford in September 1978. Secretarial assistance must never be undervalued and I would like to thank especially Mary Prime who worked so painstakingly to prepare this book for publication. To them all my thanks again. The responsibility for what lies hereafter is of course entirely mine. viii INTRODUCTION Montesquieu and the Enlightenment The word "sociology" was unknown to Montesquieu and no such discipline existed in its own right until half a century after the Age of Reason had passed away. However, no discipline can be said to spring to life suddenly at the invention of a new term, and often one finds it necessary to delve back into the history of ideas in order to discover its intellectual origins. One could argue, quite justifiably, that man has always been preoccupied with the social, and has sought to discover why indeed society is possible at all given the enormous amount of dissension and conflict which seems to have characterised every age. If one accepts this view, then it becomes even more difficult to be specific about the origins of a discipline such as sociology. What is less contentious, however, is that one can trace in the development of all disciplines key figures whose major contribution has been to focus more clearly otherwise disparate trends in their development. It is a central argument of this study that Montesquieu was a key figure in the development of sociology. Some would argue that Montesquieu 's contribution to the development of sociology has long been recognised, but in fact no systematic study of Montesquieu as a sociolo- gist has yet been undertaken.1 Certainly he has not been regarded as a key figure in the way that Comte or Spencer has. Yet, if by a key figure we mean someone who has made major contributions to the theoretical and methodological development of the subject, then we will try to show that such a label can quite justifiably be applied to Montesquieu. It might be argued that Montesquieu has already received adequate recognition as a social scientist through the vast amount of scholarship which has been devoted to Verhaps the best known account of Montesquieu as a sociologist is to be found in R. Aron: \ku.vi CuAKCWbb in Sociological Thought Volume One, 1965, pp. 11-56. Most overt recognition of Montesquieu as a sociologist rests with a number of rather short journal articles which produce little evidence to substantiate their claims. See, for example, A. Robinet de Clery: "Montesquieu Sociologue" in Revue IntQAnatLonalc da Sociology, VoJ. 47, 1939, pp. 221-232. 1 2 Montesquieu and Social Theory his contribution to the development of political thought and, furthermore, that subsumed within such scholarship has been the study of Montesquieu's contribution to Sociology. In other words, they argue, casuistic arguments about whether one aspect of Montesquieu's writings is specifically sociological rather than political is an exercise hardly worthy of serious attention, especially when one takes into account that it is an eighteenth century philosophe about whom we are writing. There are, however, good arguments against this view which need to be aired early on before this study gets under way. First, it is quite clear from most of the writings on Montesquieu as a political theorist that his works have been drawn upon far too selectively. The EApAit a&6 LoiA is a vast work, and yet much of its con- tent has remained unknown and relatively ignored by Montesquieuan scholars. What is well known is the content of the early Books which deals with the nature and types of government and with important concepts such as the 'separation of powers'. The unity of the work, which embraces studies of types of economic system, belief systems, systems of family and kinship, besides political and legal systems, has been largely neglected despite Montesquieu's plea in the P/tetface to the EApAit dzA LoiA that the reader should "approuver ou ccndamner le livre entier, et non pas quelques phrases". Second, it is not clear that Montesquieu wished to give priority of emphasis to the political. As Thomas Pangle has argued recently, "Montesquieu was the first to help us see a AOdiaZ rather than a political science", the result being a "de-emphasis of the political".2 So, too, one should think of the LzttAOA VlK&m&A as a study of the whole social structure of Paris in the early years of the eight- eenth century - a study in sociology rather than politics or even political sociology. A third argument against treating Montesquieu as primarily a political scientist is that to do so detracts from our understanding of Montesquieu's contribution to the development of a new methodology for social science, especially his contribution to the transition from historical to specifically sociological methodology. The use of ideal-types and the growth of histoire raisonne"e are instances of the emer- gence in the writings of Montesquieu of this new, more sociological method. The Con^id^AouUoru AUA £<LA CCUUZA da la Gsi&ndejuA d<u Romou.ru> at de I&JJI Vacadanca is a work of primary importance in the development of such a methodology which has received little critical attention because of its lack of interest to political scientists. This study hopes to substantiate these propositions about the political scientists' view, whilst at the same time making a fresh attempt to take a more sociological approach to Montesquieu. Apart from Aron's work on Montesquieu,-^ which is concerned much more with exposition than assessment or constructive criticism, Montesquieu has been virtually ignored by the main schools of contemporary sociological thought.^ This study aims to provide a reappraisal of Montesquieu's "generating power" as a sociological thinker and, thereby, it is hoped to fill this gap in our present knowledge. However, we are not concerned to argue that Montesquieu is as important to sociological thought Thomas Pangle: MontOAquiau* A Philosophy 0{J LLbeAaLum, Chicago, 1974, pp. 191-192. *R. Aron: op. cit., Vol. I. ^Except perhaps in the rather specialised field of the sociology of knowledge. See Werner Stark: MontOAquiau, 1960. Introduction 3 today as he would have been to that of his own day. Any study of a writer must begin from the point of view of his relevance to the age in which he lived. Chapters 1 and 2 attempt, therefore, by means of a biographical sketch of the life and times of Montesquieu and an analysis of the "audience" to whom he addressed his works, to place him in the context cf his own age and generation. Only by doing this can we appreciate the uniqueness of this thought, the extent to which he was influenced by other writers of the same period and, similarly, the extent to which his ideas constituted a new ere in the sociology of knowledge. As a philosophe and man of the Enlightenment, Montesquieu can be said to have been unusually well placed to take a new look at society. An important ideal of the Enlightenment philosophers was cosmopolitanism and Diderot, in the Encyclopedic, regarded Montesquieu as the model cosmopolite.5 of n the predominant philosophers a of the mid-eighteenth century, Montesquieu was the widest travelled, the best con- nected internationally, perhaps the best read, and probably the best known. After its publication in 1748, the E&pKit des Lois became the largest selling, philoso- phical work of the Enlightenment period, translated as it was within the space of a few years into all the major European languages. As Schlereth has argued recently, the Enlightenment philosophers thought of themselves first and foremost as "citizens of the world", rather than as Frenchmen, German, Englishmen or what- ever. 6 Like many of his contemporaries, Montesquieu was a chronic peripatetic, and as such acquired a vast range of knowledge of social, political and cultural systems besides those of his native France. When countries were too far afield to visit, he did his best to acquire as accurate a picture as possible of them from the accounts of explorers, travellers and missionaries who returned to Europe in large numbers during the first half of the eighteenth century. The world was at last being opened up to whomsoever wished to use this knowledge to advantage, and Montesquieu was at the forefront in this exercise. Such knowledge, we shall argue, put Montesquieu in a unique position to undertake the first really comparative sociological study of the major institutions of society. He began on the micro-level of analysis in his observations on Paris in 1721, looked back in history for evidence from past times in the Considerations of 1734, and put together his collected wisdom and experience in the macro-sociologicaJ study of society in the Esprit des Lois of 1748. Chapters 3, 4, 5 and 6 trace this process of evolution in Montesquieu's thought, at the same time comparing him with other major Enlightenment philosophers in order to reveal points of similarity and difference. In so doing, it has proved necessary to counter most strongly all those writers who would have us believe that Montesquieu (and indeed many other philosophers as well) does not break away from the predominantly metaphysical philosophy of the pre-Augustan era, a philosophy which, as they argue, struggled to introduce Reason into its ranks, but which was continually dogged by the traditional, theological prescriptions which had infused philosophical speculation since the Middle Ages. These are the writers who see the ESpAit des Lois as a ,l book of disconnected reflections - a book of essays really",7 having no methodology D. Diderot: "Cosmopolitain ou Cosmopolite" in Encyclopedic ou VictionnaiAC Aaisonnee des sciences, des alts ct des mbtieAS, (Paris, 1751-1765) Vol. 4, p. 297. ^Thomas Schlereth: The Cosmopolitan Ideal in the EAench Enlightenment, 1977, p. 1, Chapter One: "The Sociology of an International Intellectual Class" is o^ particular relevance here. 7 Carl Becker: The Heavenly City oh the Eighteenth CentuAy Philosopher, p. 113. 4 Montesquieu and Social Theory and the LettSies PeAAaneA as merely "a pleasant memory of disarming Persian fantasies".8 So, too, after his death in 1756, Montesquieu's ideas cannot be shown to have had an easy passage into modern sociology. In Chapter 7, we trace the slow process of assimilation of Montesquieu's thought into the mainstream of sociology, a process which, as we shall see, was fraught with set-backs and difficulties. As Raymond Aron has pointed out, a proper appreciation of Montesquieu's work has had to await the development of the discipline which he helped to create.^ This study aims to give Montesquieu that proper appreciation. Maxime Leroy: Histoiie des Jdees Sociale* en France, Volume One (de Montesquieu al Robespierre), p. 94. *R. Aron: Eighteen Lectures on Industrial Society, Chapter III, "Marx and Montesquieu", p. 52. CHAPTER 1 The Life and Times of Montesquieu Charles Louis de Secondat, Baron de Montesquieu, was born at the Chateau de la Brede some twelve miles south-west of Bordeaux on 18th January 1689. His father, Jacques de Secondat, second son of the Baron de Montesquieu, was an "active soldier, handsome, bronzed and sensual",* but with little wealth of his own. His mother, Marie-Francjoise de Pesnel, on the other hand, was an heiress who owned vast acres of land, and it was she who bought the Chateau de la BrSde for the family. He had two sisters, Marie and The'rese, who became nuns, and a younger brother Joseph, born in 1694, who also entered the Church. Another brother and sister both died at birth, and in giving birth to the younger of these in 1696 Marie-Francoise died. Charles was now seven years old, the inheritor of his mother's wealth and the title of Baron de la Brede. During his early years, Montesquieu was educated at home until the age of 11, when his father sent him to the College de Juilly in the diocese of Meaux, 370 miles from La Brede. At this school, renowned throughout the whole of France for its teaching, Montesquieu acquired that interest in Roman History, which no doubt gave him the inspiration to write his CovuidfriatioM *UL\ 1<U> CauACA da la GxandauA da* Rorraivu at da lauA Vacadanca later in life. However, the education he received was as liberal as France could offer, aimed at producing the all-round man rather than the more traditional, classical scholar. The range of subjects taught was considerably wider than that given in most schools at the beginning of the 18th century. He was taught Latin, French, and some Greek, Geography, History and Mathematics, Music, Riding, Fencing and Dancing and, with such a wide field of instruction, it is not difficult to envisage how Montesquieu later was able to draw upon this broad education in a work such as L'EApJiit da* Lot* , a work which demanded knowledge of many disciplines. After leaving Juilly, Montesquieu returned to Bordeaux where he took a degree in law at the University in 1708, and from thence he went to Paris to gain practical experience in his new profession. It was during these years in Paris that Montesquieu began to keep a scrapbook containing notes and comments on diverse matters which came to his attention. He gave it the title of the Spidlcgc, and Robert Shackleton: (AontCAquiau - A Qxttijcal BiogAapny, p.2. 5

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.