Metanoia i Also Available From Bloomsbury Present Tense , Armen Avanessian and Anke Hennig Genealogies of Speculation , edited by Armen Avanessian and Suhail Malik Speculative Realism, Peter Gratton Th e New Phenomenology, J. Aaron Simmons Philosophical Chemistry, Manuel DeLanda Philosophy and Simulation, Manuel DeLanda Introduction to New Realism, Maurizio Ferraris Aft er Finitude, Quentin Meillassoux ii Metanoia A Speculative Ontology of Language, Th inking, and the Brain By Armen Avanessian and Anke Hennig Translated by Nils F. Schott With a foreword by Levi Bryant Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc LONDON • OXFORD • NEW YORK • NEW DELHI • SYDNEY iii Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square 1385 Broadway London New York W C 1B 3 DP NY 10018 UK U SA www.bloomsbury.com BLOOMSBURY and the Diana logo are trademarks of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published 2014 Originally published in German as Metanoia: Spekulative Ontologie der Sprache, © Merve Verlag 2014 English Translation published 2018 English language translation © Armen Avanessian and Anke Hennig 2018 Armen Avanessian and Anke Hennig have asserted their right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identifi ed as Authors of this work. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication can be accepted by Bloomsbury or the author. British Library Cataloguing-i n-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN : HB : 978-1-3500-0472-6 e PDF : 978-1-3500-0471-9 ePub: 978-1-3500-0474-0 Library of Congress Cataloging-i n-Publication Data A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. Typeset by Refi neCatch Limited, Bungay, Suffolk iv Contents Foreword viii Introduction 1 I Poetics: Principles of Lingual Poiesis 15 Th e poetic function of language (Jakobson) 15 Th e potentializing function of language (Guillaume) 17 Poietic linguistics 23 Th e myth of the arbitrariness of the sign 28 Speculative poetics 32 II Th e Analytic Circle: Th e Lingual Creation of a True World 37 Triadic logic of the sign (Peirce) 45 Th e poietic triad 54 Th e linguistic turn, or the signifi ed as predicate of the signifi er 61 S means X by Y (Kripke, Meillassoux, Harman) 75 Lingual things and the ontology of individuals (Strawson) 83 III Speculation: Aspects of a Poetics of Th ought 87 Th e speculative triad 99 Subject—object—other: our methodical constellation 103 Abduction as a poietic procedure 111 Poeticizing philosophy 122 IV Cognition: Metanoia is an Anagram of Anatomie 135 Th e recursive structure of cognition (Metzinger and Malabou) 141 Th e coevolution of language and the brain 148 Aspects of universal grammar (Chomsky v Leiss): generative, extra-linguistic, cognitive 151 Semiotics of the brain (Deacon) 154 v vi Contents Epilogue: Th e Whole Truth and Nothing. But the Truth! 161 Matters ethical (and religious) 166 Going beyond thought: temporality 172 Glossary 179 Notes 187 Index 203 Illustrations 1 Semiotic triangle by Andreas Töpfer 47 2 Semiotic triangle by Andreas Töpfer 50 3 Semiotic triangle by Andreas Töpfer 51 4 Semiotic triangle by Andreas Töpfer 52 5 Eco’s Subterfuge 57 6 Rosa x Centifolia “purpurea” 63 7 “Maheka” “La Belle Sultane” 64 8 “Rosa Indica dichotoma. Le Bengale animating” 65 9 “Rosa Indica Caryophyllea. Le Bengale Oeillet” 66 10 “Slater’s Crimson China” 67 11 Abduction in perception 123 12 Terrence Deacon’s Semiotics of the Brain 157 All chapter opening images are from Armen Avanessian, Andreas Töpfer, Speculative Drawing, Berlin: Sternberg Press 2014. vii Foreword Th e book before the reader brilliantly deals with the theme of m etanoia . Drawn primarily from religious language in the Christian tradition, metanoia is oft en mistranslated as “repentance”. More properly the term should be translated as “conversion”. M etanoia refers to a fundamental transformation of one’s self, nature, thought, and world. However, it would be a mistake to conclude that the origin of this word indicates that this book is a work of theology. In the concept of m etanoia Avanessian and Hennig discern a phenomenon that is far more pervasive than the religious register and its conversions, but that lies at the core of thought and language. Th ere is a power of language, thought, and speech to transform both the subject and the world. How is it, Avanessian and Hennig wonder, that a book, a poem, a conversation, or a thinking can fundamentally transform both the subject and the world? We enter that book, poem, conversation, or trajectory of thought at one end and when we come out the other everything is completely diff erent. Indeed, in such experiences we can scarcely remember who we were and what the world looked like before. So thorough is the transformation that it even transforms our retroactive selves and worlds. We see the past diff erently than we did before. Th is is metanoia . In a thinking that traverses speculative realism, new materialism, neurology, structural linguistics, and Peircian semiotics, Avanessian and Hennig seek to determine just how something like metanoia is possible. I will leave the book to the reader for the details of this account, instead using the space of this foreword to discuss both how we might think about the phenomenon of metanoia and some of the implications of the concept. In what follows I will use language and games as a launching point for discussing philosophy. In linguistic circles it is a commonplace to compare language to a game. Take a board game. A board game has the board upon which it is played, the pieces with which the game is played, and the rules of the game by which moves can be made. Simplifying matters dramatically, the pieces of the game in language would be phonemes, while the rules of the game would be the syntax by which those elements are composed into larger viii Foreword ix units such as semes, sentences, paragraphs and so on. Th ese would roughly be the paradigmatic and syntagmatic dimensions of language respectively. Competence here would consist in knowing how to make moves in this game; which is to say, knowing how to form sentences or engage in speech- acts. We can think of philosoph ies as similar to games and languages in this respect. Th ere is a Plato game, a Lucretius game, a Descartes game, a Hegel game, a Deleuze game, a Heidegger and Badiou game, and so on. Each one of these philosophies has its own “phonemes” or pieces that inhabit the game and each has rules for making moves in that game. One shows competence in any one of these games not when they can cite the intricacies of these philosophies chapter and verse, but rather when they can make a n ew move within those games according to the rules governing the game. Compare the Plato game and the Epicurean game, for example. Suppose we were to ask whether or not it is ethical to do the drug MDMA or ecstasy? Now clearly we will not fi nd an answer to this question in the writings of either Plato or Epicurus (or Lucretius) because the drug did not yet exist and therefore could not become a topic of ethical refl ection. It is likely that both Plato and Epicurus would be opposed to MDMA , but for entirely diff erent reasons. Th e goal of Plato’s philosophy is the purifi cation of the soul so that it will separate from the body at death and go on to the world of the forms. We achieve this goal by living a life of intellect and by turning away from the body and the fi ve senses. If Plato would be against MDMA , it would be for the same reasons that he rejects certain musical instruments, forms of art, and poetic meters in Th e Republic : they draw out the passions of the body, clouding the power of the intellect, just as the drum is among the anti-Platonic instruments p ar excellence because it evokes sensuous aff ects that lead our body to move involuntarily, emphasizing the body and its passions over the intellect. One need only think of the famous dance scene in Th e Matrix Reloaded to discern the power of the drum and bass. Like Plato, Epicurus would probably be against the use of MDMA , but for entirely diff erent reasons. In Epicurus the goal of the game is to live the most pleasurable life possible (because pleasure is the moral good) and to minimize anxiety as much as we can. However, while Epicurus treats the pleasurable as the moral good and the painful as the moral wrong, he nonetheless argues that we should avoid forms of pleasure that are either too much trouble to fi nd or that cause pain as a consequence. For Epicurus, the question would then be