MEASURES INDUCED BY UNITS GIOVANNIPANTIANDDAVIDERAVOTTI 3 Abstract. Thehalf-openrealunitinterval(0,1]isclosedundertheordinary 1 multiplication and its residuum. The corresponding infinite-valued proposi- 0 tionallogichasasitsequivalentalgebraicsemanticstheequationalclassofcan- 2 cellativehoops. Fixingastrongunitinacancellativehoop—equivalently,in theenvelopinglattice-orderedabeliangroup—amountstofixingagaugescale n for falsity. In this paper we show that any strong unit in a finitely presented a J cancellative hoop H induces naturally (i.e., in a representation-independent way) an automorphism-invariant positive normalized linear functional on H. 0 SinceHisrepresentableasauniformlydensesetofcontinuousfunctionsonits 1 maximal spectrum, such functionals —in this context usually called states— amounttoautomorphism-invariantfiniteBorelmeasuresonthespectrum. Dif- ] O ferent choices for the unit may be algebraically unrelated (e.g., they may lie indifferentorbitsundertheautomorphismgroupofH),butoursecondmain L resultshowsthatthecorrespondingmeasuresarealwaysabsolutelycontinuous . w.r.t.eachother,andprovidesanexplicitexpressionforthereciprocaldensity. h t a m [ 1. Introduction 3 A cancellative hoop is an algebra (H,+,−·,0) satisfying v 3 commutative monoid identities for +,0, 1 x−· x=0, 5 2 (x−· y)−· z =x−· (y+z), 3. x+(y −· x)=y+(x−· y), 0 (x+y)−· y =x. 2 1 The above identities have manifold appearances, and can be seen from various : v points of view. i First of all, they characterize the equational theory of truncated addition. In- X deed, the class CH of cancellative hoops coincides with the equational class gen- ar erated by (R≥0,+,−·,0), where x −· y = max{0,x−y}. Therefore, they suffice to capture all identities valid in the positive reals. Also, cancellative hoops are pre- cisely the positive cones of lattice-ordered abelian groups ((cid:96)-groups for short), the latter being the abelian groups (G,+,−,0) endowed with a lattice order (G,∧,∨) on which the group translations act as order automorphisms. Actually, more is true: the assignment G(cid:55)→G ={g ∈G:g ≥0} is functorial, and provides a cat- ≥0 egoricalequivalencebetweentheclassofall(cid:96)-groups(whichisgeneratedbyR,and is equational in the language +,−,0,∧,∨), and CH [6, Theorem 1.17]. Note that thelatticeoperationsaredefinableinthehooplanguagebyx∨y =x+(y −· x)and Key words and phrases. cancellativehoop,lattice-orderedabeliangroup,MV-algebra,strong unit,uniformdistribution,Cesa`romean. 2010 Math. Subj. Class.: 03G25;06F20;11K06. 1 2 G.PANTI,D.RAVOTTI x∧y = x −· (x −· y). The prototypical examples of (cid:96)-groups —and hence, taking positive cones, of cancellative hoops— are the sublattice-subgroups of the (cid:96)-group C(X)ofallreal-valuedcontinuousfunctionsonacompactHausdorffspaceX,with componentwise operations. Reversing the order and changing notation provides a second point of view, of a logical nature. Let exp(r) = cr, for some arbitrarily fixed real number 0 < c < 1. Then exp is an order-reversing isomorphism between (R ,+,−·,0) and ≥0 the residuated lattice ((0,1],·,→,1); here (0,1] is the half-open real unit interval endowed with the usual order and multiplication ·, and → is the residuum of ·, characterized by the adjunction z ≤ x → y iff z ·x ≤ y. An easy checking gives x → y = min{1,y/x}, and the cancellative hoop axioms translate to the familiar logical identities commutative monoid identities for ·,1, x→x=1, z →(y →x)=(z·y)→x, x·(x→y)=y·(y →x), y →(x·y)=x. The many-valued logical system defined by the above identities has the interval (0,1] as its set of truth-values, and is called the logic of cancellative hoops [11], [26], [21, §6.4]; it is what remains of Hajek’s product logic [15] once the falsum is removed. A third facet of the matter arises from the observation that the addition opera- tion + and its residuum −· capture the process of production and consumption of resources in a Petri net under the firing of a transition. In the classical setting the resources at each place of a Petri net are marked by an element of Z , and this ≥0 setting is readily generalizable to arbitrary cancellative hoops which are called, in this setting, Petri algebras. See [1] and references therein. AnelementofthecancellativehoopH whosemultipleseventuallydominateany element of H is traditionally called a strong unit or, sometimes, an order unit. Since we are not dealing with the related notion of weak unit, we will simply say unit. So, explicitly, a unit is an element u ∈ H such that for every h ∈ H there existsapositiveintegerk withh≤ku. AnelementuofahoopoftheformC(X) ≥0 is a unit iff u(x) (cid:54)= 0 for every x ∈ X (remember that X is compact Hausdorff by definition). Units arise in all contexts cited above: they are archimedean elements in the (cid:96)-group enveloping H, gauge scales for falsity in falsum-free product logic, and universal bounds in bounded Petri nets. Upon defining x⊕y = u∧(x+y), ¬x=u−x,x(cid:12)y =¬(¬x⊕¬y),theintervalΓ(H,u):={h∈H :h≤u}isanMV- algebra, namely the equivalent algebraic semantics of L(cid:32) ukasiewicz infinite-valued logic. Inthefollowingweassumesomefamiliaritywith(cid:96)-groups,cancellativehoops and MV-algebras, referring to [5], [6], [8], [11], [24] for all unproved claims. Let u be a unit in the cancellative hoop H. A state on the pair (H,u) is a monoid homomorphism m:H →R such that m(u)=1; states on (H,u) corre- ≥0 spond in a 1–1 canonical way to states on the unital (cid:96)-group enveloping H and to states on the MV-algebra Γ(H,u) [22, Theorem 2.4]. We are naturally interested in automorphism-invariant states, namely those states m such that m◦σ =m for every automorphism σ of H that fixes u. This is a quite natural requirement, since MEASURES INDUCED BY UNITS 3 its lacking makes impossible to assign an “average truth value” to propositions in infinite-valued L(cid:32) ukasiewicz logic in a representation-independent way. The first re- sultinthiscontextis[22,Theorem3.4],sayingthatintegrationw.r.t.theLebesgue measure is an automorphism-invariant state on the free MV-algebra over finitely many generators Free (MV); this has been generalized in [23, Theorem 4.1] to all n finitelypresentedMV-algebras. Asamatteroffact,integrationw.r.t.theLebesgue measure is the only (modulo certain natural restrictions) automorphism-invariant state on Free (MV); this has been proved in [27] using ergodic theory, and in [20] n using algebraic means. The set M of all states on (H,u) is compact convex in RH; let E ⊆ M be u u u the set of extremal states. Then m ∈ E iff m is a hoop homomorphism [14, u Theorem 12.18]. As in [14, p. 70], we say that e ∈ E is discrete if e[H] is a u discrete subhoop of R : this happens iff e[H] = b−1·Z for a uniquely defined ≥0 ≥0 integer b≥1, which we call the denominator of e. Let H be any finitely presented cancellative hoop, and let u∈H be any unit. Our first main result, Theorem 4.2, says that for every enumeration of the discrete extremal states of (H,u) according to nondecreasing denominators, the corresponding Ces`aro mean converges, does not depend on the enumeration, and determines an automorphism-invariant state m on (H,u). The definition of m is thus intrinsic, because it is not based on any u u given representation of H. Of course the proof of the above properties is heavily basedontherepresentationtheoryof(cid:96)-groups(aswellasontoolsnewinthiscircle of ideas, namely uniform distribution theory and the Ehrhart theory). Let now a representation of H as a separating subhoop of some C(X) be ≥0 given. Contrary to standard usage, we do not assume that the elements of H are represented by piecewise-linear functions on X, nor that u is represented by the constant function 1l (note however that the representing space X is determined by H up to homeomorphism; see §2). By Lemma 2.1(iv) the state m defined by u Theorem 4.2 corresponds to a unique Borel finite measure µ on X. Let now v be u any other unit of H, and let m ,µ be the corresponding state and measure. In v v contrast with the vector lattice case [4, Lemma 4.2], the automorphism group of H does not act transitively on the set of units, so u and v may be algebraically unrelated. Nevertheless, our second main result, Theorem 6.1, says that µ and µ u v are absolutely continuous w.r.t. each other, and computes explicitly the reciprocal density in terms of u,v, and the dimension of X —again, a number intrinsically determined by H. We thank the referee for his attentive reading and detailed comments on a pre- vious version of this paper. 2. Representations and relative volume Wefixnotationbyrecallingafewbasicdefinitionsandfacts;sincethecategorical equivalencebetween(cid:96)-groupsandcancellativehoopspreservesalltheusualnotions of homomorphism, subalgebra, dual space, ..., we shall use freely well-known facts from the theory of (cid:96)-groups. ThemaximalspectrumofthecancellativehoopH isthespaceMaxSpecH whose elementsarethemaximalidealsofH (i.e.,thekernelsofthehoophomomorphisms fromH toR ),endowedwiththehull-kerneltopology,namelythetopologygener- ≥0 atedbyallsetsoftheform{m∈MaxSpecH :h∈/ m},forhvaryinginH. Allhoops we consider are representable in the following restricted sense: H is representable 4 G.PANTI,D.RAVOTTI ifitisnonzeroandthereexistsaninjectivehoophomomorphismρ:H →C(X) , ≥0 for some compact Hausdorff space X, such that for every x (cid:54)= y ∈ X there exists h∈H with (ρh)(x)=0 and (ρh)(y)(cid:54)=0. Lemma 2.1. Let H be a cancellative hoop. Then: (cid:84) (i) H is representable iff it contains a unit and MaxSpecH =0. (ii) Letρ:H →C(X) bearepresentationandu∈H aunit. Thenthethree ≥0 spacesE ,MaxSpecH,X arecanonicallyhomeomorphicviathemappings u X (cid:51)x(cid:55)→m ={h∈H :(ρh)(x)=0}∈MaxSpecH; x MaxSpecH (cid:51)m(cid:55)→(cid:0)the unique hoop homomorphism e:H →R ≥0 (cid:1) whose kernel is m and such that e(u)=1 ∈E ; u (cid:0) (cid:1) X (cid:51)x(cid:55)→ h(cid:55)→(ρh)(x)/(ρu)(x) ∈E . u (iii) Given two representations ρ : H → C(X ) , for i = 1,2, let R : X → i i ≥0 1 X be the homeomorphism obtained by composing the maps in (ii) (this 2 amounts to saying that Rx is the unique point in X such that, for every 2 h ∈ H, (ρ h)(x) = 0 iff (ρ h)(Rx) = 0). Then there exists a unit f ∈ 1 2 C(X ) such that, for every h∈H, 1 ≥0 (cid:0) (cid:1) ρ h=f · (ρ h)◦R . 1 2 Moreover, R is the only homeomorphism : X → X satisfying this prop- 1 2 erty. (iv) Let ρ,u be as in (ii). Then ρ induces a canonical bijection between the set of states on (H,u) and the set of regular Borel measures on X (since X is compact, such measures are necessarily finite). If H is countable, all Borel measures on X are regular. Proof. (i) and (ii) are well known [33]. (iii) Let x ∈ X ; then {(ρ h)(x) : h ∈ H} and {(ρ h)(Rx) : h ∈ H} are 1 1 2 isomorphic nonzero subhoops of R under the natural isomorphism (since they ≥0 both are isomorphic to H/m ). By [17, Proposition II.2.2], any isomorphism of x subhoops of R is given by multiplication by a positive real number. Therefore ≥0 (cid:0) (cid:1) thereexistsf(x)>0suchthat(ρ h)(x)=f(x)· (ρ h)(Rx) ,foreveryh∈H. The 1 2 (cid:0) (cid:1) function x (cid:55)→ f(x) is continuous because it is the quotient f = (ρ u)/ (ρ u)◦R 1 2 of two continuous never 0 functions (u being any unit of H). Since f is never 0 and X is compact, f is a unit of C(X ) ; in general f does not belong to ρ H. 1 1 ≥0 1 Let T :X →X be a homeomorphism such that, for some unit g of C(X ) and 1 2 1 ≥0 (cid:0) (cid:1) every h ∈ H, we have ρ h = g · (ρ h)◦T . Let x ∈ X ; since (ρ h)(x) = 0 iff 1 2 1 1 (ρ h)(Tx)=0 for every h∈H, we have Tx=Rx. 2 (iv) Every state m on (H,u) obviously corresponds to the state m ◦ ρ−1 on (ρH,ρu). As proved in [27, Proposition 1.1] using the lattice version of the Stone- Weierstrass theorem, m◦ρ−1 can be uniquely extended to a state on all of C(X). By the Riesz representation theorem there exists a 1–1 correspondence between states on C(X) and Borel regular measures on X; denoting with µ the measure corresponding to m◦ρ−1 we thus have (cid:90) m(h)=(m◦ρ−1)(ρh)= ρhdµ, X MEASURES INDUCED BY UNITS 5 for every h∈H. If H is countable then X is second countable, whence metrizable and every open set is σ-compact; hence every Borel measure on X is regular [30, Theorem 2,18]. See [18], [27], [9], [13], [24, Chapter 10] for details and further developments. (cid:3) AMcNaughtonfunctionoverthen-dimensionalcube[0,1]n isacontinuousfunc- tion f :[0,1]n →R for which the following holds: ≥0 there exist finitely many affine polynomials f ,...,f , each f of the form 1 k i f =a1x +a2x +···+anx +an+1, witha1,...,an+1 integers, suchthat, i i 1 i 2 i n i i i for each w ∈[0,1]n, there exists i∈{1,...,k} with f(w)=f (w). i The free cancellative hoop over n+1 generators Free (CH) is then the sub- n+1 hoop M([0,1]n) of C([0,1]n) whose elements are all the McNaughton func- ≥0 ≥0 tions, the free generators being x ,...,x ,1l − (x ∨ ··· ∨ x ); here x is the 1 n 1 n i i-th projection [26, Theorem 1]. Also, the free MV-algebra over n generators is Free (MV)=Γ(Free (CH),1l), the free generators being x ,...,x . Extending n n+1 1 n the above notation, we will write M(W) for the hoop of restrictions of Mc- ≥0 Naughton functions to the closed subset W of [0,1]n. We write points of [0,1]n as n-tuples w = (α ,...,α ), and points of Rn+1 as 1 n column vectors w = (α ···α )tr. We also use boldface to denote functions on 1 n+1 subsetsofRn+1;inparticularx ,...,x arethecoordinateprojections. Weoften 1 n+1 embed [0,1]n in the hyperplane {x =1} of Rn+1 in the obvious way. The point n+1 w is rational if it belongs to Qn+1, and is integer if it belongs to Zn+1. In the latter case, w is primitive if the gcd of its coordinates is 1. The denominator of w∈Qn+1 is the least integer b≥1 such that bw∈Zn+1. The cone over W ⊆[0,1]n ⊂Rn+1 is Cone(W)={αw :α∈R and w ∈W}. >0 Anyf ∈M(W) givesrisetoitshomogeneouscorrespondentf :Cone(W)→R ≥0 ≥0 (cid:0) (cid:1) viaf(w)=x (w)·f w/x (w) ,whichisapositivelyhomogeneouspiecewise- n+1 n+1 linearmap,allofwhoselinearpieceshaveintegercoefficients. Insyntacticalterms, f is obtained by writing f as a term (either in the (cid:96)-group language +,−,0,∨,∧ or in the hoop language) built up from the projections x ,...,x and the constant 1 n function 1l, and replacing each x with x , and 1l with x . i i n+1 Definition 2.2. A McNaughton representation of the cancellative hoop H is a representation ρ : H → C(W) such that W is a closed subset of some cube ≥0 [0,1]n and the range of ρ is M(W) . We then write h:Cone(W)→R for the ≥0 ≥0 homogeneous correspondent of ρh. Given a unit u of H, we set W = Cone(W)∩ 1 {u = 1}. The map h (cid:55)→ h (cid:22) W is a representation ρ : H → C(W ) , and the 1 1 1 ≥0 projectionw(cid:55)→w/u(w)fromW toW isthehomeomorphismRofLemma2.1(iii). 1 Lemma 2.3. Let H,u,ρ be as in Definition 2.2. Then the homeomorphism F : 1 E →W of Lemma 2.1(ii) amounts to F(e)=w iff e(h)=h(w) for every h∈H. u 1 Moreover, given any integer b≥1, F induces a bijection between: (a) the discrete states e∈E of denominator b; u (b) the rational points w∈W of denominator b; 1 (c) the primitive points in Cone(W)∩{u=b}. In particular, each of the above three sets is finite. Proof. Since u (cid:22) W = 1l, the statement about F is obvious. Let h ,...,h ,h 1 1 n n+1 be the ρ-counterimages of the generators x (cid:22)W, ..., x (cid:22)W, 1l(cid:22)W of M(W) . 1 n ≥0 Then H is generated by h ,...,h , and h = x , for i = 1,...,n+1. Let now 1 n+1 i i 6 G.PANTI,D.RAVOTTI F(e) = w = (α ···α )tr ∈ W . Then e(h ) = α , and e[H] is the intersection 1 n+1 1 i i of R with the subgroup of R generated by α ,...,α . Therefore e is discrete ≥0 1 n+1 of denominator b iff the subgroup of R generated by α ,...,α is b−1 · Z iff 1 n+1 bα ,...,bα ∈ Z and the group they generate is all of Z iff bα ,...,bα are 1 n+1 1 n+1 relativelyprimeintegersiffw isarationalpointofdenominatorb. Thisestablishes thebijectionbetween(a)and(b). Toeveryrationalpointw∈W therecorresponds 1 (cid:0) (cid:1) the unique primitive point den(w)w ∈ Cone(W), and u den(w)w = den(w) · u(w)=den(w), so (b) and (c) are in bijection. (cid:3) We need some further tools from piecewise-linear topology: see [29], [34], [12] for full details. A rational polytope S is the convex hull of finitely many points of Qn+1; its (affine) dimension is the maximum integer d = dim(S) such that S contains d+1 affinely independent points. The affine subspace A=aff(S) of Rn+1 spannedbyS isthend-dimensionalanddefinedoverQ(i.e.,itisthe0-setoffinitely many affine polynomials with rational coefficients). A face of S is S itself or the intersection of S with an hyperplane π such that S is entirely contained in one of the two closed halfspaces determined by π; the empty set is a face, and every face different from S is proper. The index of S is the least integer b ≥ 1 such that bA∩Zn+1 (cid:54)=∅[3,p.518],andtherelativeinterior ofS,relint(S),isthetopological interior of S in A or, equivalently, the set of all points of S which do not lie in a proper face. Definition 2.4. LetS,A,bbeasabove. Ifd=0,thenS =A={w}forsomew∈ Qn+1, and we define ν (S) = 1. Assume d > 0. Then there exists a (nonunique) A affine isomorphism ψ : bA → Rd that maps bA∩Zn+1 bijectively to Zd. Let us abuse language by writing b:A→bA for the map w(cid:55)→bw. We define the relative volume form Ω on A as A 1 (cid:0) Ω = · the pull-back via ψ◦b of the standard A bd+1 volume form dx¯=dx ∧···∧dx on Rd(cid:1). 1 d Thisamountstosayingthat,foreverycontinuousfunctionf :A→Rwithcompact support (more generally, every Riemann-integrable function), we have (cid:90) 1 (cid:90) fΩ = f ◦b−1◦ψ−1dx¯. (1) A bd+1 A Rd Up to sign Ω does not depend on the choice of ψ, and we always assume that ψ A (cid:82) has been chosen so that fΩ ≥ 0 for f ≥ 0. The measure ν induced by Ω A A A A on A is then the d-dimensional Lebesgue measure, appropriately normalized. Given a Riemann-measurable subset E of A, the identity (1) yields the explicit formula (cid:90) ν (E)= 1l Ω A E A A 1 (cid:90) = 1l ◦b−1◦ψ−1dx¯ bd+1 E Rd (2) 1 (cid:90) = 1l dx¯ bd+1 ψ[bE] Rd = 1 λd(cid:0)ψ[bE](cid:1), bd+1 MEASURES INDUCED BY UNITS 7 where λd is the usual d-dimensional Lebesgue measure on Rd. Example 2.5. For the reader’s convenience we give here a direct construction for themapψ ofDefinition2.4,andprovideanexample. Adoptingtheabovenotation, assume that w ∈ bA∩Zn+1. Then bA−w is a d-dimensional linear subspace of Rn+1, and is defined over Q (equivalently, over Z). It follows that there exists a Z-basis m ,...,m ,m ,...,m of Zn+1 whose first d elements constitute a 1 d d+1 n+1 Z-basisfor(bA−w)∩Zn+1. Lete ,...,e denotethestandardbasisofRd andlet 1 d ϕ : Rn+1 → Rd denote the unique linear map sending m to e if i ≤ d, and to 0 i i otherwise. Thenthemapψ(v)=ϕ(v−w)isanaffineisomorphismasdescribedin Definition 2.4. Any other isomorphism ψ(cid:48) : bA → Rd sharing the same properties must be of the form ψ(cid:48) =t◦g◦ψ, where g is a linear automorphism of Rd induced by a matrix M in the group GL Z of all invertible d×d matrices with integer d entries (this corresponds to choosing a basis for (bA−w)∩Zn+1 different from m ,...,m ), and t is the translation by some vector in Zd ⊂Rd (this corresponds 1 d to choosing an element of bA∩Zn+1 different from w). By multilinear algebra, changing ψ with ψ(cid:48) merely replaces Ω with det(M)Ω and, since det(M) = ±1, A A up to sign Ω does not depend on ψ. A As an example, consider the following five simplexes in R3: • S = the convex hull of (0,1/3,1), (1/3,1,1), (1/9,8/9,1); 1 • S = the convex hull of (1/2,1/4,1), (1,1/2,1); 2 • S = the convex hull of (1/3,3/5,1), (1/3,1,1); 3 • S ={(1/2,1/2,1)}; 4 • S ={(2/7,1/7,1)}. 5 All of S ,...,S lie in the unit square of the hyperplane {x = 1}; we provide a 1 5 3 sketch for the reader’s convenience S 3 S 1 S 4 S 2 S 5 Let λ2,λ1,λ0 be the usual 2-dimensional, 1-dimensional, 0-dimensional Lebesgue √ measures on {x = 1}; we have λ2(S ) = 1/18, λ1(S ) = 5/4, λ1(S ) = 2/5, 3 1 2 3 λ0(S )=λ0(S )=1. 4 5 Now, the affine span of S is all of {x = 1}, which intersects Z3 nontrivially; 1 3 hence the index of S is 1 and ν = λ2. The affine span of S again contains 1 aff(S1) 2 pointsinZ3,e.g.,w=(0,0,1). Anappropriateaffineisomorphismψ :aff(S )→R 2 (i.e.,onethatestablishesabijectionbetweenaff(S )∩Z3 andZ⊂R)isdetermined 2 8 G.PANTI,D.RAVOTTI bymappingw to0andv=(2,1,1)to1. Thelinesegment[w,v]hasthusν - √ √ aff(S2) measure 1 and λ1-measure 5, so that ν =( 5)−1λ1. aff(S2) TheaffinespanofS doesnotcontainpointsinZ3,andneitherdoes2aff(S ). On 3 3 the other hand, 3aff(S ) is the line passing through w=(1,0,3) and v=(1,1,3), 3 so the index of S is 3; we can take ψ :3aff(S )→R as the unique affine map that 3 3 sends w to 0 and v to 1. By (2) we have length of ψ[3S ] ν (S )= 3 . aff(S3) 3 9 One easily checks that ψ[3S ] is the interval [9/5,3] in R and concludes that 3 ν (S )=2/15; since λ1(S )=2/5, we have ν =3−1λ1. aff(S3) 3 3 aff(S3) Finally, ν =ν =λ0 by definition. aff(S4) aff(S5) If d > 0 and b = 1 then ν (S) is the relative volume of S [2, §5.4]. More aff(S) generally we have the following lemma. Lemma 2.6. Let d > 0 and let S be a d-dimensional simplex, not necessarily rational, whose vertices w ,...,w lie on {a = 1}, for some a ∈ Hom(Zn+1,Z). 1 d+1 Assume that the subspace V spanned by w ,...,w in Rn+1 is defined over Q, 1 d+1 and let m ,...,m be a Z-basis for the free Z-module Zn+1 ∩ V. Let M ∈ 1 d+1 GL R be defined by (w ···w ) = (m ···m )M. Then for every affine d+1 1 d+1 1 d+1 function f :S →R we have (cid:90) |det(M)|(cid:0)f(w )+···+f(w )(cid:1) 1 d+1 fdν = . aff(S) (d+1)! S (cid:82) Proof. It is obvious that fdλ, where λ is any multiple of the d-dimensional S Lebesgue measure, is the product of λ(S) and the average value of f over the vertices of S. Since ν is such a multiple, we just need to check the stated aff(S) formula for f =1l, namely |det(M)| ν (S)= . (3) aff(S) d! Writing b for the least positive integer such that baff(S) contains an integer point, we have by definition ν (S) = b−(d+1)ν (bS), so everything boils down to aff(S) aff(bS) proving |det(bM)| ν (bS)= . (4) aff(bS) d! Now, the strip V ∩{0 < a < 1} does not contain integer points and hence nei- ther does the strip V ∩ {0 < a < b}. It follows that Zn+1 ∩ V has a Z-basis (r ,...,r ) with r ,...,r ∈V ∩{a=0} and r ∈V ∩{a=b}=aff(bS). Let 1 d+1 1 d d+1 (bw ···bw )=(r ···r )R; then R∈GL R has last row (1···1). 1 d+1 1 d+1 d+1 AsinExample2.5wedefineψ :aff(bS)→Rd bysendingr to0andr +r d+1 i d+1 tothei-thelemente ofthestandardbasisofRd. Thusν (bS)istheordinary i aff(bS) volume of ψ(bS) in Rd, namely |det(P)|/d!, where P is the (d+1)×(d+1) matrix (see, e.g., [32]) whose last row is (1···1) and whose upper d×(d+1) minor P(cid:48) is defined by (ψbw ··· ψbw )=(e ··· e )P(cid:48). 1 d+1 1 d We claim that P = R. Indeed, let U be the (d+1)×(d+1) matrix that has 1 along the main diagonal and the last row, and 0 otherwise. Then (bw ··· bw bw )=(r +r ··· r +r r )U−1R, 1 d d+1 1 d+1 d d+1 d+1 MEASURES INDUCED BY UNITS 9 and each column of U−1R adds up to 1 (because (1···11)U−1 =(0···01), and R has last row (1···11)). Hence we get (ψbw ··· ψbw ψbw )=(e ··· e 0)U−1R=(e ··· e 0)R. 1 d d+1 1 d 1 d Therefore the d×(d+1) upper minor of R is P(cid:48), and since the last row of R is (1···1) we have P =R, as claimed. We have thus proved (4) for a specific choice —namely (m ···m ) = 1 d+1 (r ···r ), whence bM = R— of the basis of Zn+1∩V. But any other choice is 1 d+1 theimageof(r ···r )byamatrixinGL Z, and hence(4)remainsvalid. (cid:3) 1 d+1 d+1 Example 2.7. Let S ,S ,S be as in Example 2.5; we can take a = x . The 1 2 3 3 subspace V spanned by the vertices of S is all of R3, so we can take the standard 1 1 basis of R3 as m ,m ,m , whence 1 2 3 0 1/3 1/9 M1 =1/3 1 8/9. 1 1 1 By (3) we have ν (S ) = |det(M )|/2! = 1/18, in agreement with the direct aff(S1) 1 1 checking of Example 2.5. Thesubspace V spannedby theverticesof S is {x −2x =0}, thatintersects 2 2 1 2 Z3 is the free Z-module Z(0,0,1)+Z(2,1,0). The matrix M is then determined 2 by 1/2 1 0 2 1/4 1/2=0 1M2, 1 1 1 0 hence (cid:18) (cid:19) 1 1 M = , 2 1/4 1/2 and ν (S )=|det(M )|/1!=1/4. The computation for S is analogous. aff(S2) 2 2 3 Definition 2.8. A d-dimensional rational polytopal complex is a finite set Σ of rational polytopes in Rn+1 such that each face of each element of Σ belongs to Σ, every two elements intersect in a —possibly empty— common face, at least one element is d-dimensional and none is l-dimensional, for d < l ≤ n+1. If all the elements of Σ are simplexes, we say that Σ is a simplicial complex. For 0≤l ≤d, let Σmax(l) be the set of all l-dimensional polytopes of Σ which are not properly contained in any element of Σ. A rational polytopal set W is the underlying set (cid:83) W = Σ of some rational polytopal complex Σ. (cid:83) (cid:83) Lemma 2.9. Let W = Σ= Π be a polytopal set. Then: (i) If S ∈Σ is l-dimensional, then Π ={F ∩P :F is a face of S and P ∈Π} S is a pure polytopal complex (i.e., (Π )max(r)=∅ for every r <l). S (ii) If S ∈ Σmax(l), then there exists P ∈ Πmax(l) such that S ∩ P is l- dimensional. (iii) (cid:83)Σmax(l)=(cid:83)Πmax(l), for every l. (iv) Σ and Π have the same dimension. Proof. (i) Clearly Π is a polytopal complex [29, 2.8.6]. Let R ∈ (Π )max(r) for S S some r ≤l, and let w be a point in relint(R). Then w ∈/ R(cid:48) for any R(cid:54)=R(cid:48) ∈Π , S and therefore there exists an open ball B ⊂ Rn+1 centered at w and such that (cid:83) B∩R=B∩ Π =B∩S. The latter set is l-dimensional, and hence r =l. S 10 G.PANTI,D.RAVOTTI (ii)LetR∈(Π )max(l)beasin(i). ThenR=S∩P forsomeP ∈Πmax(p),with S l ≤ p. By (i), Σ is a pure p-dimensional complex, and hence S ∩P is contained P in some p-dimensional element S(cid:48) ∩P of Σ . Therefore (S ∩S(cid:48))∩P = S ∩P is P p-dimensional and l≥dim(S∩S(cid:48))≥p; thus P ∈Πmax(l). (iii) Let S ∈ Σmax(l). Then S = (cid:83)Π = (cid:83)(Π )max(l), and by the proof of (ii) S S everyR∈(Π )max(l)iscontainedinsomeP ∈Πmax(l). Thisshowstheleft-to-right S inclusion, and the other inclusion is analogous. (iv) is immediate from (iii). (cid:3) Definition 2.10. The dimension of the polytopal set W is the dimension of any polytopal complex Σ of which W is the underlying set; this makes sense because of Lemma 2.9(iv). Let 0 ≤ l ≤ d = dim(W). The l-dimensional support of W is the set of all hyperplanes of the form aff(S), for some S ∈ Σmax(l). The set A ,A ,...,A ofl-dimensionalsupportinghyperplanesisfinite—possiblyempty— 1 2 rl and, by Lemma 2.9(ii), depends on W only. For every l such that W has at least onel-dimensionalsupportinghyperplane,andforeveryBorelsubsetB ofW,define νl (B)=ν (cid:0)A ∩B∩(cid:83)Σmax(l)(cid:1)+···+ν (cid:0)A ∩B∩(cid:83)Σmax(l)(cid:1). W A1 1 Arl rl Since ν (A ∩A ) = ν (A ∩A ) = 0 for i (cid:54)= j, one checks easily that νl is a Ai i j Aj i j W Borel finite measure on W. Note that ν0 is the counting measure on the set of isolated points of W. As we W will be concerned with the measures νl , for l < d, only in the last section of this W paper, we save notation by writing ν for νd . W W 3. Asymptotic distribution of primitive points From Lemma 2.3 it is clear that in order to deal with Ces`aro means of discrete statesweneedsomeunderstandingofthedistributionofprimitivepointsinrational cones. For d ≥ 1 Jordan’s generalized totient ϕ : N → N is the arithmetical d function defined by (cid:18) (cid:19) (cid:18) (cid:19) (cid:88) k (cid:89) 1 ϕ (k)= µ hd =kd 1− , d h pd h|k p|k pprime whereµistheM¨obiusfunction,definedbyµ(k)=0ifk isnotsquarefree,µ(k)=1 if k is the product of an even number of distinct prime factors, and µ(k) = −1 otherwise. Clearly ϕ is Euler’s totient. We have 1 (cid:88) 1 Φ (k)= ϕ (t)= kd+1+O(kd); (5) d d (d+1)ζ(d+1) t≤k herethefirstidentityisadefinitionwhilethesecondone,whichinvolvesRiemann’s zeta function ζ, is well known [25, pp. 193–195]. (cid:0) (cid:1) As usual, the meaning of identities α(k) = β(k)+O γ(k) such as (5) above is that there exists a constant C > 0 satisfying |α(k)−β(k)| < Cγ(k) for every k. (cid:0) (cid:1) (cid:0) (cid:1) Analogously, α(k) = β(k)+o γ(k) means that lim α(k)−β(k) /γ(k) = 0. k→∞ We will need the following fact about Ces`aro convergence. Lemma 3.1. Let α:N→R be bounded, let 0=n <n <n <··· be a strictly 0 1 2 increasing sequence of natural numbers, and let β ∈R. Then: