ebook img

Mathematical Structures of Natural Intelligence PDF

168 Pages·2017·1.481 MB·english
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Mathematical Structures of Natural Intelligence

Yair Neuman Mathematical Structures of Natural Intelligence Yair Neuman The Department of Brain and Cognitive Sciences and the Zlotowski Center for Neuroscience Ben-Gurion University of the Negev Beer-Sheva, Israel ISSN 2522-5405 ISSN 2522-5413 (electronic) Mathematics in Mind ISBN 978-3-319-68245-7 ISBN 978-3-319-68246-4 (eBook) https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-68246-4 Library of Congress Control Number: 2017957645 © Springer International Publishing AG 2017 Preface For many years, I have been interested in identifying general struc- tures underlying the various expressions of the human mind, from psychology to art and language. This interest has naturally led me to an intensive reading of texts such as those of the gestalt psychologists and of Jean Piaget and Gregory Bateson, whose interdisciplinary approach has had a great influence on my work. The idea of writing a book on “mathematical structures” of “natural intelligence” has slowly grown in my mind, always accompanied by two main concerns. The first concern is that, in the postmodern and post-structuralist phase of the Western “intelligentsia,” such a venture might be consid- ered both anachronistic and pretentious. I have tried to address these concerns first by presenting a neo-structuralist approach that addresses some of the difficulties that were associated with the old structuralist venture and second by putting aside unjustified pretensions toward developing a grand theory. In contrast with some such grand theories of the past, this book is framed from a much more reflectively humble perspective. The second major concern that bothered me is that, in the context of studying the human mind, “mathematical structures” may be a nice metaphor in some cases but it can also be an empty abstraction. Learning about past attempts to “mathematicize” the human mind, such as those of Kurt Lewin and his field theory, has left me with a strong and sour taste of disappointment. Mathematics is such an abstract field that, beyond the powerful technical tools it provides for outsiders, its ability to provide informative structures for modeling the human mind is extremely limited. We may enjoy ideas such as “topological psychology,” but these intellectual games seem to lead nowhere. In this book, I use the term “mathematical structures” to describe in an abstract language several configurations that may be highly infor- mative in illuminating some aspects of our mind in fields ranging from neuroscience to poetry. The reader may therefore not find herein any attempt to introduce the “mathematics of natural intelligence.” However, I still aim to identify general abstract structures that may be used for modeling “natural intelligence” (a term that is briefly intro- duced below and then clarified in Chap. 1). Having said that, and being highly cognizant of the limits of a neo- structuralist venture, the final decision to write the book crystallized in my mind when I visited the beautiful city of Naples for a confer- ence. One night, and while sitting near the window of my hotel room and observing the sea with its repeating patterns of waves, some threads wove together in my mind. I suddenly realized how deeply interconnected are several ideas that have interested me for many years, from Russell’s definition of a number to the mathematical con- cept of the groupoid. From there, this book naturally emerged in the form you are currently reading. Given this context, the book’s organization is as follows. The first part of the book introduces the justification for studying general struc- tures that we may use to model “natural intelligence.” The term “intel- ligence” is used in the broad sense of computing patterns, and the adjective “natural” is used to draw a boundary between intelligence as it is evident in natural living systems and intelligence as it is studied in artificial systems and models. In fact, computation is the leading metaphor for studying the mind (Crane, 2015), and the inevitable question is: What is the difference between mathematical and compu- tational modeling of the mind? This is quite a serious question that deserves an in-depth discussion which is beyond the scope of this book. However, while computational models of the mind attempt to understand human cognition in metaphorical/analogical terms of an abstract Turing machine, and/or to produce computational models of specific cognitive processes, in this book, I model human cognition by drawing on the very abstract theorization of category theory. Differences and similarities between computational models and the mathematical models presented in this book can be easily found, but the important point is that my theoretical point of departure for under- standing the human mind is totally different. I present Piaget’s heroic venture to lay the grounds for a theory of structure but critically point to his failure. To address Piaget’s failure, I introduce and use the language of category theory, a field of mathe- matics that has great relevance as a powerful tool for building models. The book is self-contained, in that it doesn’t assume any prior knowl- edge of mathematics in general or of category theory in particular. However, I am aware of the fact that the book is extremely challeng- ing in its level of theorization and abstraction and that it will require effort from the reader to struggle with some of its abstract formula- tions. I believe, though, that the intellectual benefits of these efforts are justified. Using category theory, I argue that a certain mathemati- cal structure – the groupoid – may be used to address Piaget’s main problem and to serve as a building block of structure. To illustrate the explanatory power of this conceptualization, I use the field of neuro- science and explore an unresolved question, which is why we observe local and recurrent cortical circuits in the mammalian brain. The second part of the book aims to take us a step further by delv- ing deeper into the power of category theory’s conceptualization in modeling structure. I explain why natural intelligence is deeply “rela- tional” and how structures such as natural transformation may model these relational processes. Moreover, I explain that natural intelli- gence is not only relational but also value laden and explore the gestalt aspect of structure by using a variety of category theory tools. In this part, I also introduce a novel principle that I describe as the natural transformation modeling principle and explain how it can serve as an alternative concept for studying uncertainty “in the wild.” The third and concluding part of the book is the least mathematical and involves the application of the general principles and ideas pre- sented in the first two parts, in order to reach a better understanding of the three challenging aspects of the human mind. In this part of the book, I try to explain the human representation of the number system and specifically why our counting ability is different from the ability evident among non-human organisms and why it is so difficult to grasp the idea of zero. I also model the process of analogical reason- ing and metaphor by pointing to its underlying relational structure and its deep grounding in episodic memory and in cultural semiotic threads necessary for understanding the complexity of metaphors. Taking this idea a step forward, in this third section of the book and following the theory of Ignacio Matte-Blanco, I adopt the idea of the “unconscious” as expressing creative processes of symmetrization and illustrate how deeply connected these processes are to the general themes presented in the book and how they may be used to broaden our understanding of metaphorical processes and the creativity of the human mind. As the reader may have already realized, the book is intellectually challenging, and for this reason, only the efforts required to cross the bridge of mathematical abstraction seem to be fully justified. To ease the cognitive load the reader may experience, I have added a bullet summary at the end of each chapter. In addition, I have not overloaded the reader with references or footnotes, which are sometimes used to express the author’s “deep mastery” in his academic field. An etymology1 of “mastery” in the English language explains that mastery appeared as a transitive verb (i.e., a verb with a defined object) in 1225 and was used in the sense of “overcoming,” in the military sense of defeating an enemy. The learned scholar, the “úþwita” (Old English), who is beyond (i.e., úþ) the ordinary wisdom of human beings is therefore the one who “defeats” and “conquers” the object of knowledge. But can we really conquer knowledge? The old Jewish rabbis who read the book of Ecclesiastes encoun- tered the following text: “All the rivers run into the sea, yet the sea is not full; unto the place whither the rivers go, thither they go again.” They metaphorically interpreted “rivers” as “wisdom” and “sea” as corresponding to one’s heart. According to this interpretation, one may gain wisdom, but wisdom cannot be conquered, defeated, or “mastered” as if it were a beast to be tamed. Throwing the metaphor of mastery aside, we may step into the river. Beer-Sheva, Israel Yair Neuman 1 All references to the etymology of words are drawn from The Historical Thesaurus of English unless stated otherwise. Contents Part I 1 I ntroduction: The Highest Faculty of the Mind . . . . . . . 3 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11 2 W hat Is Structure? Piaget’s Tour de Force . . . . . . . . . . . 13 Piaget on Structure . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 14 Reversibility and Irreversibility . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29 3 C ategory Theory: Toward a Relational Epistemology . . 31 Universal Constructions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 36 The Co-product . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 46 4 H ow to Trick the Demon of Entropy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 47 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51 5 N eural Networks and Groupoids . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 62 Part II 6 N atural Intelligence in the Wild . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 65 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 70 7 N atural Intelligence Is About Meaning . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 71 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 8 From Identity to Equivalence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 77 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 84 9 O n Negation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 85 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 91 10 M odeling: The Structuralist Way . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 93 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 102 11 O n Structures and Wholes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 103 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 117 Part III 12 Let’s Talk About Nothing: Numbers and Their Origin . 121 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 130 13 King Richard Is a Lion: On Metaphors and Analogies . 131 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 146 14 T he Madman and the Dentist: The Unconscious Revealed . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 147 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 154 15 D iscussion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 155 References ......................................... 163 About the Author. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 167 Author Index . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 169 Subject Index . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 171 Figures Fig. 2.1 Smiley’s face ............................................................... 16 Fig. 2.2 Smiley’s disorganized face ......................................... 16 Fig. 3.1 A map illustrating the permutation of three boxes ..... 32 Fig. 3.2 A structure with three isomorphic objects .................. 38 Fig. 3.3 Projections of A × B ................................................... 39 Fig. 3.4 The commuting diagram ............................................. 39 Fig. 3.5 The taxonomy of Chair ............................................... 40 Fig. 3.6 The product as a pattern .............................................. 41 Fig. 3.7 The co-product ............................................................ 41 Fig. 3.8 The Würstchen and the Hotdog .................................. 45 Fig. 4.1 The product’s projections ........................................... 48 Fig. 4.2 Product and identity .................................................... 48 Fig. 4.3 The co-product of sets ................................................ 48 Fig. 4.4 The proof .................................................................... 48 Fig. 4.5 The groupoid ............................................................... 49 Fig. 4.6 A two-cell network ..................................................... 49 Fig. 6.1 An apple in transformation ......................................... 67 Fig. 6.2 The first three phases of consumption ........................ 67 Fig. 6.3 The consumption as a groupoid .................................. 67 Fig. 6.4 A functor between the transformations functors ........ 68 Fig. 7.1 The mapping between the differences and value categories .................................................................... 74 Fig. 8.1 Functors between the apples ....................................... 79 Fig. 8.2 A functor between functors F and G .......................... 80 Fig. 8.3 Natural transformations .............................................. 81 Fig. 8.4 Two mappings from the first appearance of the apple ................................................................. 82 Fig. 8.5 Adjointness ................................................................. 84 Fig. 8.6 Adjointness in Köhler’s hen experiment ..................... 84 Fig. 9.1 The sub-object diagram .............................................. 88 Fig. 11.1 A dragonfly ................................................................. 105 Fig. 11.2 Sub-objects of the dragonfly ....................................... 106 Fig. 11.3 The center of the dragonfly ......................................... 107 Fig. 11.4 A checkerboard ........................................................... 108 Fig. 11.5 A rotating disk ............................................................ 111 Fig. 11.6 A diagram of US elections .......................................... 112 Fig. 11.7 The eye ....................................................................... 117 Fig. 12.1 The formation of a number ......................................... 125 Fig. 13.1 The structure of analogical reasoning ......................... 134 Fig. 13.2 The formation of a metaphor ...................................... 144 Fig. 14.1 A triangle .................................................................... 152

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.