MARXISM AND ALTERNATIVES SOVIETICA PUBLICATIONS AND MONOGRAPHS OF THE INSTITUTE OF EAST-EUROPEAN STUDIES AT THE UNIVERSITY OF FRIBOURG/SWITZERLAND AND THE CENTER FOR EAST EUROPE, RUSSIA AND ASIA AT BOSTON COLLEGE AND THE SEMINAR FOR POLITICAL THEORY AND PHILOSOPHY AT THE UNIVERSITY OF MUNICH Founded by J. M. BOCHENSKI (Fribourg) Edited by T. J. BLAKELEY (Boston), GUIDO KONG (Fribourg), and NIKOLAUS LOBKOWICZ(Munich) Editorial Board Karl G. Ballestrem (Munich) Bernard Jeu (Lille) HelmutDahm (Cologne) George L. Kline (Bryn Mawr) Richard T. DeGeorge (Kansas) James J. O'Rourke (Manchester, N.H.) Peter Ehlen (Munich) Friedrich Rapp (Berlin) Michael Gagern (Munich) Tom Rockmore (New Haven) Philip Grier (Carlisle, Pa.) Andries Sarlerirljn (Eindhoven) Felix P. Ingold (St. Gall) James Scanlan (Columbus) Edward Swiderski (Ox/orc!) VOLUME 45 TOM ROCKMORE WILLIAM J. GAVIN Yale University University of Southern Maine JAMES G. COLBERT THOMASJ.BLAKELEY Boston State College Boston College MARXISM AND ALTERNATIVES Towards the Conceptual Interaction Among Soviet Philosophy, Neo-Thomism, Pragmatism, and Phenomenology D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY DORDRECHT: HOLLAND I BOSTON: U.S.A. LONDON: ENGLAND Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Main entry under title: Marxism and alternatives. (Sovietica ; v. 45) Includes index. 1. Dialectical materialism. 2. Neo-Scholasticism. 3. Pragmatism. 4. Phenomenology. I. Rockmore, Tom, 1942- II. Series: Sovietica (Universite de Fribourg. Ost-Europa Institut) ; v.45. B809.8.M3733 146'.32 81-12153 ISBN-l3: 978-94-009-8497-4 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-009-8495-0 DOl: 10.1007/978-94-009-8495-0 Published by D. Reidel Publishing Company, P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, Holland. Sold and distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada by Kluwer Boston Inc., 190 Old Derby Street, Hingham, MA 02043, U.S.A. In all other countries, sold and distributed by Kluwer Academic Publishers Group, P.O. Box 322,3300 AH Dordrecht, Holland. D. Reidel Publishing Company is a member of the Kluwer Group. All Rights Reserved Copyright © 1981 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1s t Edition 1981 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any informational storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgements vii Introduction ix PART ONE: THE IMMANENCE OF MARXISM-LENINISM 1 1. Emergence of the "New Soviet Man" 3 2. The Scientific-Technological Revolution 28 3. Dialectical Logic 42 4. The Dialectic of Nature 54 5. Meta-Marxism 62 PART TWO: THE TRANSCENDENCE OF NEO-THOMISM 65 6. Natural Law and the Common Good 67 7. Nature and Knowledge 89 8. Logic and Knowledge 98 9. Immateriality 106 10. The ''Predicamental'' Perspective 113 PART THREE: THE CONCRETENESS OF PRAGMATISM 121 11. Context 123 12. Science and Progress 132 13. Making Logic Practical 150 14. Nature and the.Natural 165 15. "Context" as a Philosophical Concept 177 PART FOUR: THE TRANSCENDENTALISM OF PHENOMENOLOGY 187 16. The Phenomenological Movement 189 17. An Approach to Social-Context 211 18. Phenomenological Methodology 227 19 _ An Ontological Phenomenology? 240 20. Meta-Phenomenology 255 vi T ABLE OF CONTENTS PART FIVE: CONCLUSION 265 Notes 277 Index of Names 305 Index of Subjects 309 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would like to acknowledge with gratitude the following permissions to reprint parts of my essays: To Prof. Norris Clarke, S. J., Editor, International Philosophical Quarterly, Fordham University, New York, N.Y., for parts of 'William James on Language' (Vol. XVI No.1, March, 1976); to the D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, The Netherlands, for permission to reprint some pages from Chapter VI, 'Underlying Themes and the Present Cultural Context'. This later appeared as part of the volume co-authored with Professor Blakeley, and entitled Russia and America: A Philosophical Comparison (Dordrecht, 1976); to the D. Reidel Publishing Company for permission to use parts of my article 'The Importance of Context: Reflections on Kuhn, Marx, and Dewey', which appeared in their journal Studies in Soviet Thought (Vol. 21 No.1, Feb. 1980); to Martinus NijhoffPublishers, The Hague, The Netherlands, for permission to use parts of my article entitled 'James' Meta physics: Language as the House of "Pure Experience" , which appeared in their journal Man and World, An International Philosophical Review (Vol. 12, No.2,1979). WILLIAM J. GAVIN Portland, Maine 1981 vii INTRODUCTION Contemporary philosophy is by its nature pluralistic, to a perhaps greater extent than at any moment of the preceding tradition, in that there are multiple forms of thought competing for a position on the center of the philosophic stage. The reasons for this conceptual proliferation are numerous. But certainly one factor is the increasing development of contemporary means of publication and communication, which in turn make possible the rapid dissemination of ideas as well as an informed reaction to them. And this in turn has increased the possibility for serious philosophic exchange by enhancing the available opportunities for the interaction of competing forms of thought. But, although informed philosophic interaction has in principle become increasingly possible in recent years, the frequency, scope and quality of such discussion has often been less than satisfactory. Contemporary philosophic viewpoints tend not to interact in a Hegelian manner, as complementary aspects of a totally satisfactory and a-perspectival view, facets of a singly and all-embracing true position. Rather, contemporary philosophic viewpoints tend to portray themselves as mutually exclusive alternatives only occasionally willing to acknowledge the possible validity or even the intrinsic interest of other perspectives. Thus, although the multiplication of different forms of philosophy in principle means that there are greater possibilities for meaning ful exchange between them, in practice the tendency of each of the various philosophic positions to raise claims to philosophic truth from its point of view alone has had the effect of impeding such interaction. This point can be illustrated through a brief glance at the generally hostile Marxist-Leninist reception of other philosophic tendencies. The touchstone of all forms of Marxism - as species of neo-Hegelianism - is the dialectic. In the case of Marxist-Leninist philosophy this has taken the specific form of dialectical logic, where the "subjective dialectic" reflects the "objective dialectic"; and the proletariat creates its revolutionary method and historical world, subject only to the removal of man's alienation from nature and other men. All non-Marxisms - as well as other Marxisms - are judged, assessed, and condemned on the basis of their incapacity for handling one aspect or the other of the dialectical-1ogical world view . ix x INTRODUCTION From the Marxist-Leninist perspective, to take a series of examples, neo Thomism sins on the side of "objective idealism" through misplaced and non-dialectical concretion of fictitious entities; pragmatism fails correctly to identify the dialectical and historical character of human practice; and phenomenology robs the dialectic of any concrete (read "material") referent. Initially, Soviet preoccupation with neo-Thomism came from the latter's connection both with certain political' movements in Eastern Europe and in Latin America, and its involvement with the Catholic religion, the most militant opponent of Communism throughout the world. These extra-philosophic linkages of neo-Thomism not only discredit it in Soviet eyes (as well as in those of many pragmatists and phenomenologists) as reactionary but also are said to fmd expression in its philosophic ideas on concreation and "double truth". Through the neo-Thomistic doctrine of double truth (viz. truths of reason cannot contradict truths of faith) man is robbed of his integrity and made to depend on figments of his imagination, namely God, saints, etc. In concreation, the human being who is said to collab orate with divine creativity loses his revolutionary vigor and practical auton omy; religious otherworldliness destroys man's efficacy in the real world. Even more destructive within neo-Thomism, for the Marxist-Leninists, is its denigration of human nature through the doctrine of sin and its assignment of nature in general to the realm of the Devil. As there are two truths, there are two worlds, and man has no need to make revolutionary efforts in the here and now. He need only study theology and let the Church take care of the rest. The set of philosophic views that the Marxist-Leninists see as posing perhaps the greatest threat to a truly dialectical-lOgical worldview belongs to the heirs of the Vienna Circle - variously called ''neopositivists'' or "analytic philosophers". The verificationism, conventionalism and physicalism of Anglo-American philosophy are rejected as so many "subjectivisms", as so many attempts to reach some sort of certainty that reduces science to formal logical, Cartesian validity and, hence in principle, rejects the Marxist-Leninist dialectical model Even the assimilation of ideas from pragmatism does not help such neo positivism in its effort to link up with the real world. In fact, there is a tend ency on the part of the Marxist-Leninist simply, but misleadingly, to identify neopositivism and pragmatism. Neopositivism on this interpretation fails because the ':praxis" of pragmatism is abstract - it is the merely rational practice of an ahistorical agent, instead of the world-historical practice of the proletariat. INTRODUCTION xi Were neopositivism-pragmatism able to identify a historical agent, it would not lose itself in interminable disputes on questions of method. Its method is abstract and subjective. It is grounded purely and simply in a Humean belief, lodged in a Berkeleyan mind, with no links to history or society. Because of this methodological commitment, neopositivism-pragmatism is incapable of giving any answer to the question "what do we know about what we know beyond what we know about it?". In other words, they cannot account for a reality beyond the immediate knower. Nor can neopositivism-pragmatism say anything about human misery or alienation, because it has no account of a nature beyond the knower, and reduces the human context to the biological constitution of the same knower. The Soviet critique of phenomenology and existentialism contains some of the same elements as their critique of pragmatism because both existen tialism and pragmatism have roots in nineteenth-century Lebensphilosophie. Just as the Marxist-Leninists sometimes find it difficult to distinguish between neopositivism (which is basically a view of science and method) and prag matism (which can be described as an account of man and his world), so they are often not too clear about the distinction between contemporary pheno menology (which stresses a method and view on science, originating with Husserl) and existentialism (concerned mainly with man and his hostile world). What is clear to the Marxist-Leninist who criticizes phenomenology and existentialism from a dialectical-logical perspective is that these latter join neopositivism-pragmatism in failing correctly to identify the human context. For this reason they cannot explain nature or man's relationship to it; which is why their extensive commentaries on the symptoms of man's alienation remain abstract and unconvincing. The failure of existentialism to explain man, nature, and history parallels and may be caused by the subjectivist methodology of the phenomenologist. According to Soviet accounts, the anti-psychologism, doctrine of the life world and transcendental reduction of phenomenology remain on the level of pure description. Phenomenology is Cartesian in the worst sense; and neither Ingarden nor Sartre has been able to do anything to remedy this. It is the work of the later Sartre that the Marxist-Leninists see as demon strating the final bankruptcy of phenomenology-existentialism. In effect, they argue, if Sartre's version of dialectical reason cannot justify the praxis of history, then it is clear that the "constitutivity" of the phenomenologists is historically meaningless. In sum, the Soviets see all non-Marxist-Leninist philosophies as falling
Description: