LUKAcs TODAY SOVIETICA PUBLICATIONS AND MONOGRAPHS OF THE INSTITUTE OF EAST-EUROPEAN STUDIES AT THE UNIVERSITY OF FRIBOURG / SWITZERLAND AND THE CENTER FOR EAST EUROPE, RUSSIA AND ASIA AT BOSTON COLLEGE AND THE SEMINAR FOR POLITICAL THEORY AND PHILOSOPHY AT THE UNIVERSITY OF MUNICH Founded by J. M. BOCHENSKI (Fribourg) Edited by T. J. BLAKELEY (Boston), GUIDO KUNG (Fribourg) and NIKOLAUS LOBKOWICZ (Munich) Editorial Board Karl G. Ballestrem (Eichstiitt) Bernard Jeu (Lille) Helmut Dahm (Cologne) George L. Kline (Bryn Mawr) Richard T. DeGeorge (Univ. of Kansas) James J. O'Rourke (St. Anselm's) Peter Ehlen (Munich) Friedrich Rapp (Dortmund) Michael Gagern (Munich) Tom Rockmore (Duquesne) Philip Grier (Dickinson Coil.) Andries Sarlemijn (Eindhoven) Felix P. Ingold (ETH St. Gall) James Scanlan (Ohio State) Edward M. Swiderski (Fribourg) VOLUME 51 , LUKACS TODAY Essays in Marxist Philosophy Edited by TOM ROCKMORE Department of Philosophy, Duquesne University, U.S.A. D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY A MEMBER OF THE KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBUSHERS GROUP DORDRECHT / BOSTON / LANCASTER /TOKYO Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Lukacs today. (Sovietica; 51) Includes index. 1. Lukacs, Gyorgy, 1885-197l. I. Rockmore, Tom, 1942- . II. Series: Sovietica (Universite de Fribourg. Ost-Europa Institut); v. 51. B4815.L84L885 1987 199' .439 87-32339 ISBN-I3: 978-94-010-7805-4 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-009-2897-8 DOl: 10. 10071 978-94-009-2897-8 Published by D. Reidel Publishing Company, P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, Holland. Sold and distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada by K1uwer Academic Publishers, 101 Philip Drive, Norwell, MA 02061, U.S.A. In all other countries, sold and distributed by K1uwer Academic Publishers Group, P.O. Box 322, 3300 AH Dordrecht, Holland. All Rights Reserved © 1988 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 1988 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner CONTENTS Tom Rockmore, Introduction 1 PART I Lukacs' Marxist Thought M. Markovic, The Critical Thought of Georg Lukacs 14 M. Buhr, Georg Lukacs and the Bourgeois Mind in the Twentieth Century 30 M. Hevesi, Lukacs in the Eyes of Western Philosophy Today 42 PART II Themes in History and Class Consciousness J. Larrain, Lukacs' Concept of Ideology 52 L. Dupre, Objectivism and the Rise of Cultural Alienation 70 J. Grondin, Reification from Lukacs to Habermas 86 W.L. McBride, Reification Re-examined 108 A. Feenberg, The Question of Organization in the Early Marxist Work of Luk~ics. Technique or Praxis? 126 A.Ignatow, Is There a 'Proletarian Standpoint'? 157 J.M. Bernstein, Lukacs' Wake: Praxis, Prl~sence and Metaphysics 167 PART III Lukacs on Hegel T. I. Ojzerman, Lukacs' Hegel Interpretation 197 T. Rockmore, Lukacs on Modern Philosophy 221 PART IV Lukacs' Later Thought N. Tertulian, Lukacs' Ontology 243 INDEX 274 INTRODUCTION As this century nears an end, it has become increasingly clear that Georg Lukacs is one of the most ta.1ented intellectuals of our time, not only in the Marxist tradition, but in general. Lukacs' name is well known, and his views are increasingly attracting attention; but it cannot be said that his thought has so far been widely studied, or that it has been studied to the degree its place in the Marxist tradition warrants or its intrinsic interest demands. In the relatively short period since Lukacs' death, there have been a number of books and many articles devoted to his work. But, despite some efforts in that direction, there is still no adequate treatment of his work as a whole, surely a formidable task.! If, as I believe, Lukacs is the most important Marxist philosopher since Marx, and one of the most influential intellectual figures of this century, then surely his ideas are worth scrutinizing frequently and in detail. This is not the place to provide a general description either of Lukacs' life or of his work. Descriptions of his life, especially his early career, are widely available. For present purposes, it will suffice to provide only the barest mention of some biographical facts, together with a brief account of some items in his bibliography. Lukacs' early career has been extensively studied; but I do not believe that it has often been well-understood. He was born in Buda pest on April 13, 1885 and he died there on June 4, 1971. After a period in which Lukacs studied widely and wrote on such topics as literary criticism, aesthetics, drama, etc., he joined the just established Hungarian Communist Party in December 1918. From this moment until the end of his long life, he remained faithful to institutionalized Marxism, and he made numerous contributions to Marxist theory. Although his interpretation of Marxism evolved greatly during this lengthy period, there is no reason to believe that he ever doubted the wisdom of his decision to adhere to the Communist Party. Lukacs' bibliography is imposing by any standard. The complete list of his writings, including their translation into various languages, runs to more than seventy pages.3 It is not possible here to describe even the major writings in his entire corpus. Since our interest at pres ent is focussed on his contribution to Marxist philosophy, it will be useful to mention in passing several of the main texts from his Marxist period (1918-1971). Any account of Lukacs' Marxist thought must begin with History and Class Consciousness, which appeared in 1923. This work, which is widely thought of as his masterpiece, has continued to influence generations of Marxists, including most recently Jiirgen Habermas, the German social theorist. It is certainly difficult, indeed perilous, to T. Rockmore (ed.), Lukacs Today, 1-12. © 1988 by D. Reidel Publishing Company. 2 T. ROCKMORE evaluate the importance and influence of any book, especially one as controversial as this text. But I do not hesitate to say that History and Class Consciousness is one of the most significant theoretical texts in the Marxist tradition. And from the strictly philosophical perspective, I believe that this is the single most important contribution to Marxist philosophy since Marx. Like any book of seminal importance, History and Class Con sciousness is a difficult book to describe, especially so in brief compass. Suffice it to say that Lukacs here takes up a series of problems from an angle of vision located somewhere between the disparate perspectives of Lenin and Rosa Luxemburg. The interest in Luxemburg, symbolic of the politically unorthodox nature of the work, is one of the reasons for which it was strongly and immediately attacked, even before Lenin's Materialism and Empirio-Criticism, originally published in 1908, became available in German translation in 1927. In order to maintain and strengthen his ties to Marxist ortho doxy, Lukacs criticized and renounced his book. He realigned himself on Leninist orthodoxy, as it was known to him, as early as 1924, in a slim volume, entitled Lenin. History and Class Consciousness is a series of essays touching on many themes, some of which (e.g. alienation, totality, Hegel inter pretation, etc.) continue to recur in Lukacs' later writings. Lukacs here shows the importance of the concept of class consciousness for Marx' thought. He calls attention, prior to the publication of the Paris Manuscripts (in 1932), to the Marxian view of alienation, which he discusses in brilliant fashion under the heading of "reification". He also stresses the approach to Marx in terms of the Hegelian background. Lukacs' emphasis on the significance of Hegel for the interpretation of Marx was closely followed by Karl Korsch in his book Marxism and Philosophy, which also appeared in 1923. Lukacs and Korsch were the prime architects of the still widespread tendency to understand the philosophical dimension of Marx' thought mainly, or even solely, in relation to Hegel. Lukacs was certainly not the first writer to call attention to Hegel's importance for the comprehension of Marx. Even before Engels' famous remark about Marx' debt to German philosophy4, Marx had indicated the importance of this relation in the well-known comment in the Second Afterword to Capital.5 Here, in a celebrated passage, Marx unclearly suggested that his own position is to be grasped as the materialistic inversion of Hegelian idealism. It has always been recog nized that this passage is important for the interpretation of Marx' position, although it is difficult to specify the meaning of Marx' suggestion. In part for this reason, this passage has given rise to an extensive discussion, which need not detain us here. For present purposes, it will be sufficient to observe that although many participants, especially Marxist writers, were not well grounded in INTRODucrION 3 Hegel's thought, this was not the case for Lukacs. When he wrote History and Class Consciousness, he already possessed a fIrm grasp, from a Marxist perspective, of Hegel's thought, which he continued to explore in ever greater depth and detail in his later writings .. Lukacs' interest in Hegel later led to a major monograph on his thought, The Young Hegel. Studies in the Relations between Dialectics and Economics, which appeared in 1948. This book was conceived as a contribution to the history of classical German philosophy from the Marxist perspective. Although Lukacs explicitly acknowledges the importance of Hegel's approach, he constantly stresses that it is an "idealist distortion" which requires a "materialist transformation" in order to be adequate as an interpretation of social reality. According to Lukacs, the renaissance of Hegel studies in what Marxists call the "imperialistic" peI10d represents an attempt to utilize Hegel for what he regards as the "imperialistic, reactionary develop ment" of neo-Kantianism. Dilthey, in particular, has supposedly provided an influential contribution in the service of what from a Marxist angle of vision appears as reactionary imperialistic tendencies through his interpretation of Hegel in close relation to philosophical romanticism. From the Marxist perspective, Lukacs regards it as important to refute the legend of Hegel's romanticism in order better to understand his role as the predecessor of Marx. Lukacs' study is limited only to the social and historical com ponents of the historical problem of the development of the dialectic. From the historical perspective, he was principally concerned with the French Revolution and its consequences for Germany. According to Lukacs, Hegel's importance is not limited \0 his profound insight into the French Revolution and the Napoleonic period; Lukacs stresses that Hegel is above all interested in the problems of the industrial revolution in England and the problems of philosophy, upon which dialectic depends. Although his thought is "idealistic", and not "materialistic", Hegel was arguably the predecessor of Marx. Like Marx, Hegel strove to comprehend the veritable internal structure, and the veritable driving forces of capitalism, in order to ground the dialectic of its movement. This is the wider framework of Lukacs' Hegel study; it should not be confused with the study itself. In general terms, the book is an attempt to read the development of Hegel's concept of dialectic as the result of an effort to come to grips with political economy and the economic relations prevailing in England. As concerns Hegel, Lukacs' aim is not only to bring out the importance of the history of philosophy for philosophy; it is further to show in a concrete fashion, through reference to the social context and the historical background, the inner connection between economics and dialectic. Like virtually all of Lukacs' Marxist writings, the Hegel book is polemical; but it is also in every sense a major scholarly monograph - closely argued, solidly documented, highly original. It is no accident 4 T. ROCKMORE that Lukacs' Hegel monograph has had considerable influence on the subsequent Hegel discussion. It was followed in the same year (1948) by a much slighter, even scurrilous work, Existentialism or Marxism? Unlike the Hegel study, this book is not intended as a scholarly contribution; it is rather intended as an occasional Streitschrift in a manner well-represented in the Marxist tradition, where political broadsides abound. The occasion is the rancorous debate that broke out after the end of the Second World War among partisans of existentialism and Marxism. This debate, which was especially fierce in French circles6, played a major role in Sartre's concern, in his later thought, to come to the aid of Marxism from an existentialist perspective; it was equally important in Althusser's politically orthodox, Marxist effort, from a structuralist angle of vision, to distinguish between philosophical and scientific periods in Marx' thought. According to Lukacs, this type of debate is peculiar to the imperialistic stage of capitalism and represents the clash of two opposing forms of thought: that running from Hegel to Marx, and that which links Schelling to Kierkegaard, the latest form of which is existentialism. Like Lenin, Lukacs believes that philosophy cannot remain neutral; it must address practical concerns. From the Marxist perspective, the present philosophical combat consists in the confrontation between existentialism, which misleadingly presents itself as a "third way" between idealism and materialism, and historical materialism. This debate concerns three groups of problems, including: the search for objectivity, the effort to safeguard freedom, and the fight against nihilism. Some existentialists, for instance Sartre, like to draw a dis tinction between their perspective and bourgeois thought. But Lukacs believes that existentialism in all its forms carries the imprint of the same spontaneous nihilism which infects all of what Marxists call modern bourgeois ideology. In all his writings beginning with History and Class Conscious ness, Lukacs constantly relies on a Marxist approach to the history of philosophy. In the book on existentialism, he opposes a view which he regards as socially pernicious because of its intrinsic relation to "imperialism". He continues his attack on forms of what he labels as "bourgeois ideology" in a detailed study of the relation of non-Marxist philosophy and the rise of fascism, entitled The Destruction of Reason (1954). According to Lukacs, what he describes as irrationalism is the dominant tendency in so-called bourgeois philosophy in all its forms. He rejects what he regards as the idealist view that philosophical problems can be studied immanently, or wholly on the philosophical plane, in favor of the view that such problems are "located" in the con text circumscribed by the forces of production and historical develop ment. He further justifies his evidently anti-bourgeois, Marxist ap- INTRODUCfION 5 proach on the grounds that there is no "innocent" angle of vision ("unschu/dige" Weltanschauung), or neutral standpoint. Lukacs particularly stresses the unity of different forms of irrationalism which, from the Marxist angle of vision, he regards as the reactionary answer to the various problems arising out of class struggle. He believes that the fIrst important period of modern irration alism arose in the progression from Schelling to Kierkegaard, in the fIght against the dialectical and historical concept of progress found in German Idealism. Just as Marx studied the locus classicus of capital ism in England, so Lukacs thinks he can show that nineteenth- and twentieth-century Germany is the "classical" land of fascism. He is aware that the transformation of "philosophical irrationalism" into political fascism occurs on a non-philosophical terrain. Hence, his aim is not to equate "philosophical irrationalism" with fascism; his aim is rather to show that the possibility of a so-called fascist, aggressive reactionary ideology is contained in every philosophical form of "irrationalism" . The last work I will mention is the unfInished study of The Ontology of Social Being which properly belongs to his Nachlass. This immense work, more than two thousand pages long, is not well-known, even to Lukacs specialists, because of its length and an unfortunate publication delay. It was originally conceived as a kind of giant prolegomenon to a work on ethics, which Lukacs did not live to write. The main topic is, as the name implies, an ontology of social being, as distinguished from natural being which had been the concern of metaphysicians since Aristotle. Lukacs' task in this book is to develop a Marxist theory of social ontology by building upon insights drawn from the Marxist and non-Marxist sides of the philosophical tradition. The study is divided into two main parts: The Present State of the Problem' (Die gegenwiirtige Problemlage) and 'The most Important Problem Complexes' (Die wichtigsten Problemkomplexe). In the fIrst part, after a discussion of neopositivism and existentialism, Lukacs turns to the ontological approach favored by Nicolai Hartmann, who, with Heidegger, is one of the two main representatives of ontological thought in Germany in this century. Lukacs turns to Hartmann because of his importance for ontology, but also since, as was noted in The Destruction of Reason, Lukacs believes him to be the only non-Marxist thinker with a positive attitude towards dialectic.7 He ends the fIrst volume with a detailed account of the intrinsic contradictions of Hegelian "idealism" and Marx' allegedly decisive advance beyond idealism through the "materialist" concept of work. In the second volume, Lukacs develops this concept further. He works out in detail a teleological concept of work, with obvious roots in Aristotle. In this connection, we are reminded of Lukacs' belief that Marxism is a form of left-wing Aristotelianism. He also discusses in