ebook img

Louis Althusser, Letter to the Communist Party of France Central Committee PDF

20 Pages·2008·0.19 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Louis Althusser, Letter to the Communist Party of France Central Committee

Historical Materialism 15 (2007) 153–172 www.brill.nl/hima Letter to the Central Committee of the PCF, 18 March 19661 Louis Althusser † Louis Althusser 45, rue d’Ulm Paris 5th A Letter to Comrades on the PCF’s Central Committee Dear Comrades, I have taken very careful note of the resolution2 passed at the last Central Committee meeting. Th is resolution contains several theses of both theoretical and practical importance. To give only one example: the CC [Central Committee] had the merit to adopt theses on theoretical work, the development of Marxist theory and research, the conditions of this research (and the practical measures planned to further this research), as well as the role of intellectuals and their participation in the work of the Party, etc. Th ese theses, which resume and 1. Th e translator gratefully thanks the Institut Mémoires de l’Édition Contemporaine for permitting this letter to be published and especially thanks José Ruiz-Funes for his research help and editorial suggestions. Th e original is held at the IMEC in Paris under the code ALT2. A42- 04.02 under the heading ‘Lettre à Comité Central d’Argenteuil, 11–13 Mars 1966’. On both the translation and note, G.M. Goshgarian unselfi shly provided excellent advice. Any errors that remain are the translator’s. [Editorial note: To maintain typographic consistency, we have changed Althusser’s underlined emphases to italics.] 2. Th e offi cial title of the document has ‘resolution’ in the singular and most documents that refer to the resolution follow this pattern. Idiosyncratically, Althusser sometimes refers to the resolution in the plural, as a series of resolutions. He is not, however, consistent and, by the end of the letter, begins referring to the whole document in the singular. Th e translator has elected to retain Althusser’s references to Resolutions I, II, and III. However, these should be taken only as references to diff erent sections of one resolution, not to separate resolutions. He has also changed all of Althusser references to ‘resolutions’ to the singular, ‘resolution’, so that the letter is internally consistent and in accord with standard usage. © Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2007 DOI: 10.1163/156920607X192110 HHIIMMAA 1155,,22__ff99__115522--117722..iinndddd 115533 55//2222//0077 11::4455::5522 PPMM 154 L. Althusser / Historical Materialism 15 (2007) 153–172 develop the declarations of the PCF’s Seventeenth Congress, should give a certain ‘lift’ to our theoretical work, a boost whose importance is widely recognised today. Nevertheless, alongside these theses and occasionally in the very act of stating them, the resolution contains a certain number of developments, declarations, and arguments that appear to me to be – I cannot hide the fact – doubtful, poorly grounded, or seriously off the mark when viewed from the standpoint of Marxist-Leninist principles.3 I would like to explain my concerns to you very simply and frankly. I have in mind only the interests of the Party’s Marxist-Leninist theory and would ask that you consider the following remarks in the spirit in which they are intended. Th at is, I would ask that you take them as a critique inspired by the acknowledged principles of Marxism-Leninism and as a contribution to the defi nition of a certain number of diffi cult but very important questions. I. Th e resolution contains a contradiction I will begin by examining a contradiction that the resolution appears to me to contain. Resolution III affi rms that the development of science requires argument and research. Th e Communist Party will neither impede such debates nor impose its own a priori truths. Still less will it settle ongoing debates between specialists in an authoritarian fashion. It is obvious that this theoretically and politically correct thesis bears not only on mathematics, the natural sciences, and the social sciences, but also on the Marxist science of history (historical materialism) and Marxist philosophy (dialectical materialism). Indeed, the CC insists forcefully on the necessity of stimulating research into Marxist theory. It does so in order to bring this theory up to the level at which it can handle the diffi cult tasks before us. Th us it is only natural that, regarding still unresolved points of Marxist theory on which theoretical research is underway and absolutely certain and acknowledged results have not been attained, the CC should recall that the Party ‘will not impose its own a priori truths and, still less, settle ongoing discussions between specialists in authoritarian fashion.’ 3. All emphases are Althusser’s. HHIIMMAA 1155,,22__ff99__115522--117722..iinndddd 115544 55//2222//0077 11::4455::5522 PPMM L. Althusser / Historical Materialism 15 (2007) 153–172 155 It is important to make this point very clear. In question here is not the substance of our theory as it stands today, the principles of Marxism-Leninism and the knowledge it has already defi nitely acquired. In the domain of established Marxist-Leninist theory, the Party cannot suspend judgement; on the contrary, it is its duty to intervene in order to recall the principles and knowledge acquired and developed by theory and class struggle, and to defend them against all the revisions and deviations that menace them. If the Party failed to do so, it would be renouncing its mission. But what is in question here is something else entirely: namely, theoretical problems which remain open and upon which the great teachers of Marxism (beginning with Marx) did not or are said not to have taken a position. Th ese are problems that have not been, or are said not to have been, posed or resolved and, for this reason, problems about which we still do not possess, or are said not to possess, reliable Marxist knowledge. Th is is, precisely, the case with theoretical research on problems that remain open, and on which the Party has good reason to suspend judgement. It must not ‘settle matters in an authoritarian fashion’ before research has produced demonstrable results, results that are incontestable and uncontested. Now, this is where it seems to me that there is a contradiction: the same resolution that rightly invokes the principle of non-intervention on theoretical questions that remain open, does in fact intervene on several questions that, for the last few years, have been the object of theoretical research and discussion among specialists. Allow me to explain myself. Sometimes in casual formulae and sometimes in more categorical ones, the resolution does in fact take sides, directly or indirectly, on several questions that one can, at the very least (with a reservation that I will come to in a moment), consider to be still open. Th ese questions are those of the epistemological ‘rupture’ between science and ideology, between the Marxist science of history and philosophies of history, and between Marxist philosophy and pre-Marxist idealism. Th ey also include questions about the meaning of the expression ‘Marxist humanism’ as well as others about the Marxist theory of art and culture, and so on. I shall show this in detail in my letter. Th e fact is that, on these questions that are of immense importance for Marxist theory and practice, the resolution does not suspend judgement. Instead, it ‘settles’ a theoretical debate that is still in progress, and, in so doing, it takes a stand in favour of conceptions defended by certain comrades (Garaudy, Aragon), and against others defended by other comrades (one of whom is the author of this letter). Formally, this partisanship brings the resolution into contradiction with itself; one cannot square the principle of non-intervention into ongoing HHIIMMAA 1155,,22__ff99__115522--117722..iinndddd 115555 55//2222//0077 11::4455::5522 PPMM 156 L. Althusser / Historical Materialism 15 (2007) 153–172 research and discussion with intervention into the very same research and discussion. Hence it is impossible not to ask: ‘Why this contradiction?’ Examining the questions on which the resolution takes a position and developing [where and how] these theses lead (or can lead) to theoretical errors should allow us to make this question more precise. I will analyse three errors in turn: an error by omission (II); an error by suppression (III); and an error by ‘creation’ (IV). II. An error by omission: the thesis on Marxist humanism Resolution II approaches the question of ‘Marxist humanism’ by way of the affi rmation that ‘there is a Marxist humanism’. Th is affi rmation of existence only makes sense if one situates it correctly, in the context of a polemic. It can only be understood as an affi rmation opposed, word for word, to another, one of the ilk: Th ere is no Marxist humanism. If one tries to discover the above-mentioned thesis (‘there is not a Marxist humanism’), in our ‘ongoing research’, one will not fi nd it in this form. However, one will fi nd in my essay ‘Marxism and Humanism’, as well as in [the journal] La Nouvelle Critique,4 a very precise and very diff erent thesis, one that is the object of a long discussion in the collective work Reading ‘Capital’. Th is thesis affi rms that the Marxist science of history and Marxist philosophy were only able to constitute themselves on the basis of a rupture with the humanist philosophies and anthropologies that preceded them. It maintains that Marxism is, theoretically speaking – that is to say, from the point of view of its philosophical and scientifi c concepts – an anti-humanism, or, more precisely, a theoretical a-humanism. When we affi rm this principle, we have something extremely precise in mind: namely, that, in Marx’s mature theory (science and philosophy) we do not fi nd and will never fi nd, among the scientifi c and philosophic principles comprising the base of this theory, any anthropological or humanist concepts. Th ese concepts do fi gure in Marx’s early work (e.g., the concepts of humanism, alienation, disalienation, the ‘loss of human spirit’, etc.). At the time they were formulated, they were an organic part of the still ideological theory that Marx worked up out of existing philosophies, history, and even a critique of political economy (e.g., the 1844 Manuscripts). After the ‘rupture’ that began in 1845 and was only realised after years of work, Marx rejected the (theoretical ) humanist/anthropological conceptions of his youth. Th ese ideological concepts 4. Most probably a general reference to the anti-humanist arguments made in La Nouvelle Critique. See especially number 164 (May 1965). HHIIMMAA 1155,,22__ff99__115522--117722..iinndddd 115566 55//2222//0077 11::4455::5522 PPMM L. Althusser / Historical Materialism 15 (2007) 153–172 157 disappeared and were replaced by other concepts. Th ese are the well-known concepts of historical materialism: mode of production, juridical, political, and ideological superstructure, etc. Th e ‘humanist’ concept of ‘alienated labour’ disappeared as well, to be replaced by the scientifi c concept of ‘wage- labour’. Marx no longer needed these dated ‘humanist’ concepts. He had perceived that, far from yielding knowledge, these old concepts prevented him from producing knowledge of his object (the history of societies and the history of worldviews). Th at is why he rejected them clearly and decisively once he saw that he had to forge other, totally diff erent concepts, in order to make good the claim to produce knowledge of his object. Th e declaration of this rupture may be found in black and white in Th e German Ideology, but it necessarily took many years before the rupture was totally ‘accomplished’. To say that Marxism is, theoretically speaking, an anti-humanism or a-humanism, is quite simply to observe that, in Marx’s mature thought, theoretical-humanist concepts are absent and are replaced by new scientifi c concepts. Th is is a matter of fact. And we may add that neither Engels nor Lenin ever re-introduced into Marxism the concepts of theoretical humanism that Marx had rejected. One looks in vain in Engels or Lenin for even a single mention of concepts such as alienation, alienated labour, ‘the reappropriation of human nature’, etc. It is quite remarkable that neither Marx, nor Engels, nor Lenin, nor Stalin ever declared that ‘Marxism is a humanism’. True, Gorky employed this formula; but we know that Lenin deemed Gorky to be a petty-bourgeois revolutionary because of his ideology. We also know that the concepts of theoretical humanism, already present in Dühring, Bernstein, and the Russian populists, were put back on the communist agenda in the 1920s by the left revisionists (e.g., the young Lukács) and the right revisionist social democrats (e.g. Léon Blum). Here is the thesis that I and many other comrades have defended: that the theoretical concepts of Marxist philosophy and science have nothing to do with the concepts of theoretical humanism. Th is thesis, I repeat, was the object of an extended demonstration in Reading ‘Capital’. It has yet to be seriously contested. Th at is to say, it has yet to be contested by a serious historical and philosophical argument. In fact, it would be an extremely diffi cult thesis to contest. In the same texts in which this demonstration is made, I pointed out that, while the concept of humanism (along with its sub-concepts) is not a scientifi c concept, it is an ideological notion – and a moral ideological notion at that. Th e ideological validity of this concept is therefore not in question. In Marxism, when we speak of ideology, we are aware that ideology (e.g. moral ideology) is not a pure illusion, but a representation that, albeit skewed and illusory, nevertheless alludes to something real, whose existence it designates without, HHIIMMAA 1155,,22__ff99__115522--117722..iinndddd 115577 55//2222//0077 11::4455::5533 PPMM 158 L. Althusser / Historical Materialism 15 (2007) 153–172 however, providing (scientifi c) knowledge of it. Th erefore, we can, to a certain extent, make use of, say, the expression ‘socialist humanism’ as an ideological expression, in order, preliminarily and roughly, to designate the existence of a number of practical eff ects expected to arise from the revolutionary activity of a Bolshevik party, such as the end of class exploitation, the improvement of the lot of the exploited, the disappearance of class exploitation, the end of political and ideological domination, etc. We can, to a certain extent, utilise this ‘humanist-socialist’ or ‘humanist- Marxist’ formula, but only after making three very important reservations. Th e fi rst reservation is that we steep ourselves in the fundamental truth that this formula has no theoretical value, in other words, no value as scientifi c knowledge. Th e second reservation is that we recognise that we should use much better formulae, ones that are closer to scientifi c knowledge than this humanist formula and its corollaries. For example, we say something much more precise when we speak of wage-labour rather than of ‘alienated’ labour (a humanist formula); we do the same when we speak of class exploitation rather than of ‘economic alienation,’ and so on. Th is second reservation is extremely important. For we have learned from Marx and Lenin that one cannot use such ideological formulae with impunity. When, ignoring the scientifi c formulae at our disposal, we employ ideological formulae (such as humanist formulae), we risk being contaminated by them and relapsing from science into ideology (as did the revisionists Dühring, Bernstein, and Léon Blum, ‘humanists’ all). Ideology is not inactive, but acts on those who accept it: that is why the ideological struggle, the struggle against ideology, is one of the principal parts of Marxism. Of course, in order to distinguish ourselves from the barbarians in the world, we can call ourselves ‘humanists.’ However, that which makes us communists is not just the fact that we are not barbarians. Th ere is a deeper reason that both requires and enables us not to be barbarians: possession of scientifi c knowledge of the historical process. We do not content ourselves with moral principles and declarations but, rather, link these moral principles, these principles of moral ideology (for example, humanist principles) to the reality of the relations of production and the relations between social classes. What makes us communists is that we see clearly into moral ideology and that we call things by their proper names. Communists can really be human because they are not ‘humanists,’ because our actions do not rest upon moral (and therefore ideological ) principles, but upon scientifi c ones. We can therefore perfectly well do without the ideological concepts of humanism, even from a practical standpoint. Indeed, if we are not to expose our scientifi c theory to the contagion of their ideology and end up falling back on HHIIMMAA 1155,,22__ff99__115522--117722..iinndddd 115588 55//2222//0077 11::4455::5533 PPMM L. Althusser / Historical Materialism 15 (2007) 153–172 159 pre-Marxist, pre-scientifi c positions, it is very much in our interest to do without the ideological concepts of humanism even at the practical level. Why, then, should we ever make use of the term ‘humanism,’ and of the concepts derived from it? We should do so carefully, under well-defi ned conditions, and only in order to make ourselves understood when fi rst approaching those people whom we need to address and who conceive their ideal in terms of (petty-bourgeois or Christian) humanist ideologies. I repeat: carefully and on a fi rst approach, for our theory runs real risks if we systematically employ these formulae and if we conceive our own theory in humanist terms. Th is is naturally a temptation when one systematically employs such formulae. It is here that my third reservation comes into play. If we ask why neither Marx (in Capital and afterwards), nor Engels, nor Lenin, nor Stalin ever declared that ‘Marxism is a humanism’, we will see that they did not do so for crucial political reasons. As soon as words and expressions are used in the political and ideological class struggle, they cease to be simple concepts and become weapons, and will be for a long time yet, in a veritable fi ght unto death, a veritable class struggle. To be precise: the term ‘humanism’ has always been employed by bourgeois and petty-bourgeois ideology – including petty- bourgeois interpretations of Marxism – in mortal combat with another term, one which is absolutely vital for revolutionaries: class struggle. It is this reality, verifi ed a thousand times over in the practice of class struggle, which explains why Marx, Engels, Lenin, and Stalin were never willing to proclaim that ‘Marxism is a humanism’. To sum up: 1) Th e concepts of theoretical humanism (humanism, the human essence, alienation, disalienation, loss of the human essence, reappropriation of the human essence, the Whole Man, the generic essence of man, etc.) are foreign to Marxist theory. Both in its historical-materialist and dialectical-materialist aspects, Marxist theory comprises completely diff erent scientifi c concepts that bear no relationship at all to the ideological concepts of humanism. 2) As ideological concepts, humanistic concepts can have a practical value. Nevertheless, we have every interest in avoiding such concepts (and, in any case, in carefully controlling them when it is indispensable that we use them at the pragmatic level ). For, inasmuch as they are ideological, these concepts can contaminate our theory and expose this theory to serious dangers, including that of theoretical revisionism. Th e ideological danger represented by the pragmatic usage of these humanist concepts has in the last analysis to do with the very deep (petty-bourgeois) class nature of humanist ideologies. HHIIMMAA 1155,,22__ff99__115522--117722..iinndddd 115599 55//2222//0077 11::4455::5533 PPMM 160 L. Althusser / Historical Materialism 15 (2007) 153–172 3) We must recall the political, class reasons that have barred the classics of Marxism from declaring that ‘Marxism is a humanism’, and we must draw the appropriate consequences. Now that this has been made clear, what do we fi nd in Resolution II? We fi nd a few phrases on ‘Marxist humanism,’ without a single allusion to the two fundamental problems that the concept of humanism (and its sub-concepts) poses for Marxism: 1) the problem of the bases for its claims (scientifi c or ideological); 2) the problem of the ideological struggle between humanism and class struggle. Resolution II declares that ‘there is a Marxist humanism’, that it is not ‘abstract’ like bourgeois humanism (but this provides no response to the question of the bases for its claims – and the opposition of abstract and concrete is not, understood in this way, a Marxist distinction); that it ‘fl ows from the historical task of the working class’, that it ‘in no way signifi es the rejection of an objective conception of reality for the sake of a vague impulse of the heart’, that, on the contrary, ‘it bases its approach on a rigorously scientifi c conception of the world’, etc. 1) Th e fi rst problem, the question of the bases for humanism’s pretensions (which is precisely the object of ‘ongoing research’ and debate), is not posed. 2) Th e second question, which does not need to be made the object of research (for it summarises all the experience of the communist movement), is not evoked. Th is double silence is regrettable and, as we shall see, its consequences are not long in coming. Simply omit these two problems, and a spiritualist ideology familiar to all of us will leap into Marxism through the breach of the omission – the spiritualist ideology which holds that Marxism is a ‘philosophy of man’, a ‘philosophy of the creation of man by man’, etc. It does not limit itself to one role or to one practical use, but lays claim to being the theoretical truth of Marxism itself. Let us speak clearly. Th is ‘Marxist’-humanist ideology is today represented by the philosophy of our comrade Garaudy. By reminding us that Marxism is founded ‘on a scientifi c conception of the world,’ and must not be confused with a ‘a vague impulse of the heart’, Resolution II proposes to limit the scope HHIIMMAA 1155,,22__ff99__115522--117722..iinndddd 116600 55//2222//0077 11::4455::5533 PPMM L. Althusser / Historical Materialism 15 (2007) 153–172 161 and the eff ects of this ideology. However, it only limits this ideology’s eff ects (just as Resolution III limits its eff ects with respect to religion) without undermining its existence, since the decisive question of the non-validity, from a scientifi c standpoint, of ‘humanist’ concepts is passed over in silence. I speak directly and frankly. Resolution II is stated in terms that refl ect the theoretical compromise concluded with the humanist ideology of our comrade Garaudy. It reminds him that he must not go too far. However, in exchange, nothing is said about the philosophical question as to whether the grounds for the claims of humanist theory are ideological or scientifi c. In addition, nothing is said about the crucial problem of humanism versus class struggle. Th us, the fl oodgates are left open to this ideology. As we will soon see in connection with art and culture, this ideology loses no time turning all this to its advantage. I do not say theoretical compromise by accident. Both Marx, in his ‘Critique of the Gotha Programme’, and Lenin have taught us that, in order to forge unity (with no trace of class collaboration), communists can make almost any sort of compromise, with one exception: theoretical compromise. Th is is because a theoretical compromise is always made between theory and an ideology. Th is type of compromise always ends up turning against theory, never against ideology. In a moment, we will see the proof of this proposition. III. An error by suppression: the thesis of ‘the absence of a rupture in the vast creative movement of the human spirit’ It is Resolution I that proclaims this thesis. Th e thesis is stated in terms that have nothing at all to do with Marx, but that inevitably bring to mind the language of idealist philosophers of history (Hegel, Brunshvicg). To be more precise, they bring to mind the language of certain spiritualist philosophers of creation (V. Cousin, Bergson, etc.). Every attentive reader will wonder why this sentence surges up here, altogether unexpectedly, at the end of a paragraph on art and culture (a paragraph I will soon discuss). In order to begin to understand this sentence, one has to compare it with another from Resolution II, which states that: ‘Marxism is no more an alien body in the world of culture than the proletarians are barbarians camping in the city. Marxism is born from the development of culture and it gives meaning to all that humanity has achieved.’ Yet drawing a connection between these two passages does not make everything perfectly clear. In order to understand the implications of these sentences, we need to know something about the ‘ongoing research’ in which the resolution intervenes, and takes sides. HHIIMMAA 1155,,22__ff99__115522--117722..iinndddd 116611 55//2222//0077 11::4455::5544 PPMM 162 L. Althusser / Historical Materialism 15 (2007) 153–172 In fact, what the declarations condemn are specifi c theses advanced about the ‘break’ or ‘epistemological rupture’ that have been argued at length in For Marx and Reading ‘Capital’. Th e theses I defend are intended to shed light on a reality that Marx clearly recognised in his scientifi c work and that has to do, above all, with the ‘epistemological break’ that separates a science from the ideology which gave birth to it. Th ese theses also bring out other ‘ruptural’ phenomena (‘qualitative leaps,’ dialectical ‘threshold’, etc.) that have occurred in the history of the development of human knowledge. Th e most famous instance of these theses is provided by Marxist theory itself. On the basis of a detailed argument that has yet to be seriously contested, and by following Marx very carefully, I have shown that Marxist science [historical materialism] and Marxist philosophy [dialectical materialism] were only able to constitute themselves on the basis of an ‘epistemological rupture’ with previous ideological theories, namely, the philosophy of history and classical philosophy. Th is is, in the Marxist-Leninist tradition, a perfectly classical thesis. When Marx declared that the conception of the essential principles of the science of history had only been made possible by a ‘settling of accounts with his former philosophical conscience’,5 he himself became the fi rst to recognise the reality and necessity of this rupture. Here, too, I have done no more than to return to the terms and the contents of Marx’s work and to the classical- Marxist tradition in order to comment on them with some precision. It is to this set of theses, theses organically bound up with Marxist-Leninist theory, theses that it is impossible to dissociate from Marxist-Leninist theory, theses indispensable to Marxist-Leninist theory, that Resolution II opposes the calm affi rmation of ‘the absence of a rupture in the vast creative movement of the human spirit’. Everyone knows that the concepts at work in the expressions ‘human spirit’, ‘movement of the human spirit’, and ‘creative movement’ have their place, not in Marxist theory, but in the idealist and spiritualist philosophies of Hegel, Bergson, Teilhard de Chardin, etc. However, if we can, let’s leave the words aside and proceed to their contents. One wonders what becomes of the fundamental distinction between science and ideology (and all its consequences, especially those involving Marx) in this ‘vast creative movement without rupture’. One also wonders how to think, without rupture, the law of development by qualitative leaps.6 5. Marx 1977, pp. 261–5. 6. Althusser may be referring here to Engels’ argument in Herr Eugen Dühring’s Revolution in Science (Anti-Dühring) (Engels 1939, p. 53); but he probably also means to refer to Stalin’s schematisation of dialectical law (Stalin 1972, pp. 304–5). Every Committee member would no HHIIMMAA 1155,,22__ff99__115522--117722..iinndddd 116622 55//2222//0077 11::4455::5544 PPMM

Description:
(Garaudy, Aragon), and against others defended by other comrades (one of whom is the author of this letter). Formally, this partisanship brings the
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.