ebook img

Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism PDF

542 Pages·1972·17.482 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism

Walter Burkert Translated by Edwin L. Minar, Jr. Harvard University Press Cambridge, Massachusetts 1972 © Copyright 1972 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College All rights reserved English edition, translated with revisions from Weisheit und Wissenschafi: Studien zu Pythagoras, Philolaos und Platon, Copyright 1962 by Verlag Hans Carl, Nurnberg Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 70-162856 SBN 674-53918-4 Printed in the United States of America Preface to the German Edition If Pythagoras does not present himself to our rninds as a sharply outlined figure, standing in the bright light of history, this is not merely the result of accidents in the course of historical transmission. From the very beginning, his influence was mainly felt in an atmosphere of miracle, secrecy, and revelation. In that twilight period between old and new, when Greeks, in a historically unique achievement, were discovering the rational interpretation of the world and quantitative natural science, Pythagoras represents not the origin of the new, but the survival or revival of ancient, pre-scientific lore, based on superhuman authority and expressed in ritual obligation* The lore of number is multifarious and changeable. That which was later regarded as the philosophy of Pythagoras had its roots in the school of Plato. Outlines of an earlier reformulation of Pythagorean doctrine in the manner of the φυσιολογία of the fifth century can be detected in the fragments of Philolaus. As the old and the new interpenetrated and influenced each other, the picture of Pythagoras became distorted until, with the victory of rational science, he came to seem its true founder. To investigate these interrelationships is still a somewhat risky undertaking; but an attempt has been made to take more account than has previously been done of the variety in the kinds of evidence available and, above all, to clarify the ramifications and the divagations of the tradition. I am indebted for much advice and encouragement to my teachers Otto Seel, Reinhold Merkelbach, and Helmut Berve, as well as to Dr. Ludwig Koenen and to Dr. Burkhart Cardauns, who also helped me with the proofs. To all of these I offer hearty thanks. Erlangen Walter Burkert April 1962 In revising this book for translation, it has been impossible to add references to all the literature on the subject which has appeared since 1962.1 have tried to concentrate on the ancient evidence, to cut down polemics, and to incorporate whatever I have learned in these years, notably from some reviews of the German edition, and from continuous discussions with B. L. van der Waerden. In the question of the " discovery of the irrational," I have taken a stand which is less critical of the tradition; and more thorough acquaintance with ancient religion has pushed the concept of "shamanism'* further into the background. But though a good number of passages have been revised, and though there are some small rearrangements in the order of treatment, still the book has remained, in all the main lines, the same. New and comprehensive accounts of Pythagoreanism have been given by Kurt von Fritz, H. Dorrie, and B. L. van der Waerden in Pauly-Wissowa (XXIV 171-300; Supp. X 843-864), and by W. K. C. Guthrie in his History of Greek Philosophy, vol. I; and the same year (1966) saw the appearance of two books with the title Pythagoras and Early Pythagoreanism, by C.J. de Vogel and J. A. Philip. Discussion is certain to continue. I cannot claim to have provided a definitive history of Pythagoreanism, or a complete account of Pythagoras, the man and the genius. Still I trust that this book gives a full and perspicuous presentation of the evidence and thus will be useful even to those who are not inclined to draw the same conclusions from it. My special thanks are due to Edwin L. Minar, Jr., who not only completed the laborious task of translation in a spirit of most pleasant collaboration, but to whom is due the original initiative which brought about the English edition. The responsibility for the content, and for all that may be wrong in it, remains mine. Schwerzenbach-Ziirich Walter Burkert August 1970 Introduction ι I. Platonic and Pythagorean Number Theory 15 1. The Platonic Theory of Ideal Numbers 15 2. The Philosophy of the Pythagoreans according to Aristotle 28 3. The Later Non-Aristotelian Tradition and Its Sources, 53 Speusippus, Xenocrates, and Heraclides Ponticus 4. Pythagoreanism in Plato and the Origin in Platonism of the 83 Pythagorean Tradition I1I. .P ySthoaguorrasc ine t hPe Eraorlbieslte Tmradisti o9n 977 2. Historical Background 109 4. Acusmata 166 3. Metempsychosis and "Shamanism" 120 5. Acusmatici and Mathematici 192 6. Early Evidence for Pythagoras as a Scientist? 208 III. Philolaus 218 1. The Special Position of Philolaus* Book in the Pythagorean 218 Tradition 2. The Spurious and the Genuine in the Philolaus Fragments 238 3. Reflections of Pythagorean Philosophy in the Fifth 277 Century B.C.? IV. Astronomy and Pythagoreanism 299 1. The Structure of the World and the Planetary System 299 2. The Theory of Planetary Movements 322 3. The Cosmos of Philolaus 337 4. Harmony of the Spheres and Astral Immortality 350 Contents V. Pythagorean Musical Theory 369 1. Speculation, Experimentation, and Fiction 369 2. Number Symbolism and Calculation of Proportions in 386 Philolaus VI. Pythagorean Number Theory and Greek Mathematics 401 1. Did the Pythagoreans Lay the Foundations of Greek Mathe- 401 2.m aPticsy? thagorean Arithmetic 427 43. .P yNthaguormean bGeeomr eatryn andd MCathoemsamticaol Ssec r4ets6 4547 Abbreviations 485 Bibliography 493 Greek Words Discussed 509 Index of Passages 510 General Index 528 / Introduction The "Pythagorean question" has sometimes been compared with the Homeric question. Not that the details of the problem would especially suggest this; what does remind one of that most famous of philological controversies is the difficulty of the argument and the lack of agreement on methodology, as well as the multiplicity and contradictory character of the solutions advanced. Another similarity, and not the least striking, lies in the tremendous importance of the questions about the life, activity, and influence of Pythagoras of Samos. Over the origins of Greek philosophy and science, as over the beginning of Greek literature, lies the shadow of a great traditional name. The attempts of scholarship to grasp the underlying historical reality keep getting entangled in contradictions; where some think they discern the figure of a world-historical genius, others find little more than empty nothingness. Pythagoras' influence was a lasting one. The ancient tradition of the history of philosophy made him the ancestor of the "Italian School" and therefore, after Thales, the second, and more important, originator of philosophia—in fact, the inventor of the word. The doctrine transmitted under his name, that numbers are the principles of what exists, that the "One" is its primal ground, became part of the amalgam of Neoplatonism. In the trend set by Iamblichus, Pythagoras was the high priest, par excellence, of the divine wisdom^ He then became, in the trivializing school tradition of the Middle Ages, the master of the quadrivium, and in particular the inventor of arithmetic. The early modern period discovered Pythagoras as the creator of natural science, which was just then being reborn; what Copernicus and Galileo taught was regarded by their contemporaries as a revival of Pythagorean science.1 Subsequently, as research based on historical perspective increasingly 1E.g., Campanella in a letter to Galileo of Jan. 13, 1611 (T. Cainpanella, Lettere, ed. V. Spampanato [Bari, 1927] 165). Further literature in Capparelli, I 2QfF; see below, ch. IV 3, nn. 1-2. INTRODUCTION replaced the uncritical appropriation of ancient culture, the traditional picture of Pythagoras, imposing though also vague in outline, inevitably gave way more and more before criticism. In the scholarly controversy that followed scarcely a single fact remained undisputed, save that in Plato's day and then later, in the first century B.C., there were Pythagoreioi. The "wisdom of Pythagoras," however, has also had passionate defenders, who opposed to criticism a countercritique: one-sided, self-sufficient methodology, they protested, had substituted hypothesis for tradition. When we set out to survey the most important attitudes and trends in modern Pythagorean scholarship, the point of departure must be the work of Eduard Zeller.2 In it the material is not only collected, with a completeness scarcely to be surpassed, but sifted with uncommon methodological rigor. The criterion for the value of a tradition is its age, and Zeller arrives at the verdict, often cited since in agreement and disagreement: "The tradition about Pythagoreanism and its founder thus has more and more to tell, the further it lies, chronologically, from the events..." (I 364). This "expansion of the tradition" (ibid.) arose basically from "dogmatic preconceptions, partisan interests, dubious legends, and spurious writings'' (365). The most important source, nearly the only one which is left, is in the reports of Aristotle, in his surviving treatises. A second primary source is found in the fragments of Philolaus, in which August Boeckh, in his day, claimed to have found a firm foothold amidst the bog of Pythagorean pseud­ epigrapha.3 But Aristotle speaks of "Pythagoreans," not of "Pythagoras"; so the figure of the master fades off in a mist of nonhistorical legend. Pythagoras is still recognized as the "founder of a religious society" and teacher of transmigration (411), but all philosophical significance is denied his ethical and religious doctrines (557*0· Alongside this stands, without connection, the number philosophy of the Pythagoreans. This can be reconstructed from Aristotle and is confirmed by Philolaus, though aside from him the Pythagoreans remain anonymous and scarcely datable. Sharply separated from all this ancient material is the neo-Pythagorean school, which (Zeller thinks) arose, compounded of Platonic and Aristotelian elements, not before the first century B.C. (Ill 2.02fF). 21 361-617, III 2.92-254. The text is essentially that of the second edition (1856). Zeller summarized his position under the title "Pythagoras und die Pythagoraslegende," Vortr. u. Abh. I (Leipzig, 1865) 30-50. 3 But contrary to Boeckh, Zeller pronounced the fragment on the world soul (21) spurious (I 476.1); cf. below, ch. Ill 2, n. 21. 2 Introduction Zeller's work had a decisive influence, especially in Germany; it dominates Diels's arrangement of testimonia in the Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. In the chapter on Pythagoras (DK 14), the biographical reports $re assembled, along with the reports as to whether or not Pythagoras wrote anything.4 In the separate chapter on "The Pythagorean School" (DK 58), the most important section is the collection pf "ancient Peripatetic'' material (s8B),5 following Iambli­ chus' catalogue of Pythagoreans (58A), and itself followed by the acusmata (58C), the Pythagorikai apophaseis of Aristoxenus (58D), and the allusions to "Pythagorists" in the Middle Comedy (58E). Between these two chapters are found, in chronological order as far as possible, the testimonies on individual Pythagoreans, notably Hippasus (DK 18), Philolaus (DK 44), and Archytas (DK 47). Hermann Diels follows Zeller also in the question of the genuineness of the Philolaus fragments. Zeller's solution, however, left a number of problems unsolved, and later research entered in with supplement, modification, and criticism. Above all, a gap had opened between Pythagoras the religious founder and the number philosophy of anonymous Pythagoreans; to connect these disparate elements and to show their original unity was bound to be an extremely enticing challenge. For at this time the tide of system building in philosophy, which had borne the work of Zeller, was ebbing, and this very change made possible a deeper understanding of cultural history. As the boundaries of philosophy became fluid, the connections with pre-scientific, religious-mythical thought became clearer. So the task appeared to be to comprehend how religion and philosophy could be united in Pythagoras: mysticism and science (or at least the germ from which science sprang). Then came the high tide of the evolutionary idea, and it began to seem possible, with its help, to explain the contradictions of the tradition and to give everything its place in an extended and detailed history of Pythagoreanism. The direction was set by August Doring (1892); his thesis became most influential because he was followed by John Burnet in the later editions of his Early Greek Philosophy* The unity of science and religion is found in the ideal of catharsis; scientific activity is the highest form 4 Two doxographical reports are arbitrarily added (14.20, 21; cf. below, ch. IV 1, nn. 39-41; I 3, n. 151-153). 8 From the fifth edition on, the excerpt from the Hypomnemata has been added, as a result of the discussion of Max Wellmann (58Bia; cf. below, ch. I 3, n. 1). 6 Burnet refers to Doring (EGP 98 n. 3); as a result, the extent of what Burnet traced back to Pythagoras himself increased considerably after the first edition (London, 1892, I05ff). 3

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.