ebook img

Linguistic Creativity: Exercises in ‘Philosophical Therapy’ PDF

201 Pages·2000·4.646 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Linguistic Creativity: Exercises in ‘Philosophical Therapy’

LINGUISTIC CREATIVITY PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES SERIES VOLUME 81 Founded by Wilfrid S. Sellars and Keith Lehrer Editor Keith Lehrer, University ofA rizona, Tucson Associate Editor Stewart Cohen, Arizona State University, Tempe Board of Consulting Editors Lynne Rudder Baker, University of Massachusetts at Amherst Radu Bogdan, Tulane University, New Orleans Allan Gibbard, University of Michigan Denise Meyerson, University of Cape Town Franc;ois Recanati, Ecole Poly technique, Paris Stuart Silvers, Clemson University Nicholas D. Smith, Michigan State University LINGUISTIC CREATIVITY Exercises in 'Philosophical Therapy' by EUGEN FISCHER Institute for Philosophy, Ludwig-Ma ximilians-Unive rsity, Munich, Germany r... " SPRINGER SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. A c.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-94-010-5841-4 ISBN 978-94-011-4243-4 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-011-4243-4 Printed an acid-free paper AII Rights Reserved © 2000 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 2000 Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover Ist edition 2000 No part ofthe material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner PREFACE Both linguists and philosophers have wondered how it is that we can understand the sentences we hear or reacl. While linguists tended to concentrate more on the question of how we can recognise those sentences as structured in a certain way, as systematic concatenations of familiar words and phrases, philosophers focused on the obvious follow-up question of how we can get to know the meaning of a sentence we have thus recognised. Our achievements seem all the more remarkable the moment we remind ourselves that the rules of our mother tongue allow for infinitely many sentences we have not yet encountered, indefinitely many of which we could understand if we encountered them. The philosophers' question concerning this impressive competence is put, more properly, as that of how it is that a speaker can get to know the meaning of any of indefinitely many sentences he has never encountered before. Together, the philosophers' and the linguists' query confront us with what is known as the 'problem of linguistic creativity'. The philosopher's part of the problem might thus be called the 'problem of semantic creativity'. This problem is the topic of this book. Its aim is not so much to solve that problem, or to answer the questions that confront us with it. Rather, this book starts out, more modestly, as an attempt to say a bit more clearly than before what our problem is. As we consider more closely the questions that articulate it, we shall find that these questions, and some others that go with them, are not particularly good ones to ask. Indeed, this exercise will not only make us give up our initial questions, it will also reveal that the questions we are left with do not pose any such thing as a 'problem of semantic creativity'. In a sense to be made precise by working through the example, we will thus not solve, but 'dissolve' that problem. To this end, we will use a method first outlined by Ludwig Wittgenstein's collaborator Friedrich Waismann, and will develop a new technique that might come close to something Wittgenstein had in mind himself, when speaking of 'philosophical therapy'. If they prove fruitful, success will lend charm to these at first sight unattractive methods. The dual aim of this book is to dissolve the problem of semantic creativity; and to develop, and explore the potential VI of, the unfamiliar methods employed to this end. The aim is, more generally, to cope with a core problem in the philosophy of language; and, by reflecting on this paradigm, to get more clear on one way of practising philosophy as an activity of clarifying thoughts. The prime value of this undertaking, if successful, should lie in bringing out the philosophical virtues of being modest and unpretentious. Of always asking oneself whether one really knows what one means by one's words. Of drawing as few cheques on future scientific progress as possible, in explaining what exactly one is saying now. Of preferring vocabulary one not only knows how to use in the lofty heights of abstract argument but is also able to relate to down-to-earth talk about concrete situations. Of being more interested in coping with specific problems than in framing general theories. Of bothering as much about how one got into the problem as about how to get out of it. Of paying close attention to what kind of problem one is dealing with, before rushing to deal with it. And, again and again, of taking small steps, and of being prepared to make them yet smaller, should the need arise. Those who survived this sermon might even enjoy the practice that tries to live up to the preaching. This book is the descendant of an Oxford DPhil-thesis. My department, of the Ludwig-Maximilians-University, Munich, kindly reduced my administrative obligations and left me with ample time in which to turn a thesis into a book. During my doctoral work, I enjoyed the generous financial support of the Studienstiftung des deutschen Volkes. For academic support, I am indebted to Martin Davies, Stephen Williams, and Timothy Williamson, whose comments on various drafts saved me from error again and again. Peter Sullivan and Jose Bermudez prevented the process of redrafting from coming to a premature end. Gordon Baker supervised my thesis-work throughout, read each draft of this book, and persistently encouraged new ideas even at embryonic stages at which one might well have had little patience with them. I take pleasure in recording my gratitude. CONTENTS PREFACE. ................................................................................................ V CONTENTS ............................................................................................ vii ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS .......................................................... viii PARTONE- THEPROBLEM CHAPTER 1 - THE ORTHODOX PERSPECTIVE: A PROBLEM OF LINGUISTIC CREATIVITY .................................................... 3 CHAPTER 2 - THE PHILOSOPIllCAL PROBLEM: THE PLIGHT OF ORTHODOXy ................................................................... 20 PART TWO - NEW METHODS CHAPTER 3 - PHILOSOPIllCAL DISSOLUTION: UNINTELLIGIBLE QUESTIONS ..................................................................... 49 CHAPTER 4 - PHILOSOPIllCAL THERAPY: A SENSE OF WONDER AND A CHANGE OF ASPECT .............................................. 79 PART THREE - A THERAPY CHAPTER 5 - SEMANTIC CREATIVITY: THE PHILOSOPIllCAL PROBLEM AGAIN ........................................................... 111 CHAPTER 6 - SEMANTIC CREATIVITY: PROBLEM-DISSOLUTION AND THERAPY ............................................................... 143 POST-SCRIPT -DISSOLVING PHILOSOPIllCAL PROBLEMS ........................ 179 NOTES ................................................................................................. 189 BIBliOGRAPHy .................................................................................... 191 ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER 1- THE ORTHODOX PERSPECTIVE: A PROBLEM OF LINGUISTIC CREATIVITY 1. The Root of the Problem: Initial Reasoning, Arithmetical Analogy - formulates the questions that confront us with the problem of semantic creativity, and spells out a trite line of reasoning and a compelling analogy that lead us to ask them: that make us wonder what sort of unconscious semantic information-processing is going on in competent speakers ................................................................................................. 3 2. Formal Theories of Meaning for Natural Languages - clarifies the idea of 'semantic information-processing' involved, by explaining the notion ofs emantic theories for natural languages ............................................ 7 3. Computational Explanation - clarifies the idea of 'unconscious information-processing' involved, by explaining the notion of computational explanation and its intended application in the explanation ofb eliefs about what expressions mean. ............................ 12 4. Aim and Structure of the Book - outlines the agenda: Chapter 2 will isolate the philosophical problem of semantic creativity from among the empirical issues outlined so far. Each of the next two chapters will then introduce a method required for 'dissolving' that problem. The two final chapters will then deploy these methods, chapter 5 to work the problem into shape for such a 'dissolution " chapter 6 to effect that 'dissolution '. 17 ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS IX CHAPTER 2- TIIE PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEM: TIIE PLIGHT OF ORTIIODOXY 1. What We Want - brings out that our Initial Reasoning has us ask not for just any computational explanation of speakers' competence, but for accounts that render them intelligible as finite and epistemically conservative beings .............................................................................. 20 2. Rational Reconstruction: Requirements - develops a requirement to be met if reference to such conscious semantic information-processing as we have in mind when asking our first heuristic question (Q) is to provide us with such an account: Any pertinent canonical derivation in any correct compositional semantic theory has to enhance the semantic knowledge of any theorist competent with that theory ................................................ 23 3. A Compositional Semantic Theory - shows that a certain theory of truth T can do duty as a compositional semantic theory of meaning for a fragment L of 'Loglish '. ....................................................................... 27 4. The Plight of the Semantic Theorist - establishes that the crucial reqUirement is not met: There is a theorist competent with T whose semantic knowledge about L is not enhanced by derivations in that theory. ................................................................................................. 32 5. Computational Explanation: Requirements - spells out what such unconscious semantic information-processing as we have in mind in asking our second heuristic question (Q') amounts to, and builds up to a reqUirement to be met if reference to such processing is to provide us with the sort ofa ccount we seek. .......................................................... 37 6. The Plight of the Computer - establishes that accounts of the form we had in mind flout this reqUirement, even though they may well be acceptable as computational explanations ofs peakers 'competence ..... 41 7. The Philosophical Problem - sums up: Accounts along the orthodox lines explored cannot render speakers intelligible as finite and epistemically conservative beings, even if empirically successful. The 'philosophical problem' that may thus stay with us even once we have solved the empirical problem of semantic creativity is the topic of this book. .................................................................................................... 43 x ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER 3- PHILOSOPHICAL DISSOLUTION: UNINTELLIGIBLE QUESTIONS 1. Stage-setting: What Do You Mean by 'Mean'? - isolates a dimension of indeterminacy of our talk of 'knowledge of meaning', viz., relative to ascriptions of linguistic competences, and shows that, within certain limits, it is to be removed by fiat ........................................................ .49 2. Preparing for the Job: Tools - explains how this dimension of indeterminacy is to be removed by piecemeal, local, ordinary, and potentially innovative explanations of meaning that define possession of semantic knowledge in terms ofm astery of 'game '-roles ...................... 53 3. Plain Answers for LJ - develops an intuition as to how to ascribe semantic knowledge about a first object-language which many philosophers working with formal theories of meaning are likely to share, and thus arrives at a first proposal ofh ow to define possession of semantic knowledge in terms ofm astery ofg ame-roles ........................ 58 4. Some More Plain Answers for LJ -develops another popular intuition to yield an alternative set of such definitions, and follows up some 'objections' to them that yield yet further alternatives .......................... 62 5. A First Conclusion - is that all the definitions developed so far entail that semantic information about a sentence of LJ is not, in any epistemically relevant sense, 'new' relative to semantic information about all of the sentence's elementary constituents. So that neither of the heuristic questions we ask with respect to that language makes sense. 67 6. A First Problem-Dissolution - explains the sense in which these questions are therefore 'unintelligible', and retraces the steps we took to thus 'dissolve' the problem they seemed to present us with. This yields the conception of philosophical 'problem-dissolution' first outlined by Friedrich Waismann ............................................................................ 73 CHAPTER 4- PHILOSOPHICAL THERAPY: A SENSE OF WONDER AND A CHANGE OF ASPECT 1. A Sense of Wonder - induces a sense of wonder in us by showing that our finding is neither superficial nor due to verbal trickery, and then

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.