Licensing long-distance wh-in-situ in Malayalam The MIT Faculty has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation Aravind, Athulya. “Licensing Long-Distance Wh-in-Situ in Malayalam.” Natural Language & Linguistic Theory, vol. 36, no. 1, Feb. 2018, pp. 1–43. As Published http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11049-017-9371-2 Publisher Springer Netherlands Version Author's final manuscript Accessed Thu Nov 15 11:44:15 EST 2018 Citable Link http://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/113876 Terms of Use Article is made available in accordance with the publisher's policy and may be subject to US copyright law. Please refer to the publisher's site for terms of use. Detailed Terms NALA9371_source [06/07 12:34] SmallExtended, Chicago, NameYear, rh:Option 1/45 NonamemanuscriptNo. (willbeinsertedbytheeditor) Licensing long-distance wh-in-situ in Malayalam AthulyaAravind Received:30May2016/Accepted:20March2017 Abstract Itisgenerallythoughtthatwh-in-situ,likeovertmovement,ispotentially unbounded.Atthesametime,certainlanguageshavebeenarguedtodisallowlong- distance wh-in-situ. This paper argues that even in languages that show apparent clause-boundednesseffects,wh-in-situ,likewh-movement,caninprinciplecrossan arbitrarynumberofclauses.Failuretolicenseawh-phraseacrossaclauseboundary, when it occurs, can be shown to result from the interaction between wh-agreement andindependentoperationsaffectingembeddedclauses.Evidencewillbedrawnpri- marilyfromMalayalam(Dravidian),whichhasbeenarguedtodisallowlong-distance wh-in-situwithfiniteembeddedclauses.Iwillshowthattherelevantfactorforwh- licensingisnotfiniteness,butA¯-movementofembeddedclauses,anoperationthatis commonwithfiniteCPs.ThecoreoftheproblemliesinthefactthatinterrogativeC isageneralized[A¯]-probethatcaninteractwithanumberoffeaturallymorespecific goals,includingthe[A¯]-featuresontheheadofthemovingclause.Itwillbeshown that this approach can account for a number of facts about Malayalam wh-question formation,includingselectivetransparencyofcertainfiniteclausesforlong-distance wh-licensing. Keywords wh-in-situ·Malayalam·Clause-boundedness·Long-distancequestion- formation·Relativizedprobes 1 Introduction Languages can be broadly categorized into two types with respect to wh-question formation. There are those that overtly move one or all wh-phrases to the front of the clause and those that leave them in-situ. In principle, both wh-strategies can be unbounded. Consider the long-distance wh-questions in English (1a) and Japanese (1b). Though the wh-expressions differ in surface position, the interpretation is the same—thewh-phraseoriginatingintheembeddedclausetakesscopeovertheentire sentence. DepartmentofLinguisticsandPhilosophy,MIT,Cambridge,MA,USA NALA9371_source [06/07 12:34] SmallExtended, Chicago, NameYear, rh:Option 2/45 2 AthulyaAravind (1) a. WhatdidJohnsay[Marybought ]? b. Hideki-ga [Kyoko-ga nani-o kat-ta to] it-tano Hideki-NOM[Kyoko-NOMwhat-ACCbuy-PAST]say-PASTQ ‘WhatdidHidekisayKyokobought?’ Thebasicgeneralizationisthatthistypeofparametricvariationwithrespecttowh- movement does not create deep differences in the kind of questions speakers of the differentlanguagescanform.Islandenvironmentsaside,bothmovementandin-situ strategiesareinprincipleunboundedandallowspeakerstoasklong-distanceques- tionsofarbitrarylength. However,ithasbeenobservedthatinanumberoflanguages,wh-in-situappears to be subject to locality restrictions that are unique to this question-formation strat- egy, an observation which, if true, raises doubts about the generalization above. In languageslikeHindi-Urdu(Mahajan1990;Dayal1996),Bangla(Bayer1997;Simp- sonandBhattacharya2003)andIraqiArabic(Wahba1991;Ouhalla1996;Simpson 2000), in-situ wh-expressions inside finite complements seem restricted to clause- bound scope. On the basis of the apparent strict locality of wh-in-situ in these lan- guages, a number of researchers have suggested that languages can parametrically vary with respect to the locality conditions on wh-licensing (Ouhalla 1996; Naka- mura1998;Simpson2000). Simpson (2000), for example, argues that the domain for wh-feature checking mayvaryacrosslanguages,proposingthefollowingthree-wayclassification(2). (2) Wh-licensingdomains(Simpson2000:109,ex.(58)) a. TypeA:Romanian,Bulgarian Spec,CP b. TypeB:IraqiArabic,Hindi-UrduImmediatetensedomainofthe+QC0 c. TypeC:English Thesentence OfparticularrelevanceforourpurposesisthedistinctionbetweenTypeBandType Clanguages.OnSimpson’sproposal,TypeBlanguageslikeIraqiArabicandHindi- Urdu disallow long-distance wh-in-situ because a wh-phrase that remains inside a finiteembeddedclausecannotbeaccessedforwh-feature-checking,sincetheinter- rogative C cannot see past its immediately local tense domain. Long-distance wh- movement in these languages, then, is in-part motivated by the need to get the em- beddedwh-phraseintoanaccessiblewh-licensingdomain. A similar proposal is put forth in Ouhalla (1996), who attributes the locus of parametricvariationtopropertiesofthewh-phrasesthemselves.Morespecifically,he argues that wh-phrases in languages like Iraqi Arabic and Hindi-Urdu are anaphors thatcannotbeboundacrossafiniteclause. I will refer to those languages claimed to have clause-boundedness restrictions onwh-in-situ(whetheritberestrictionsonwh-licensingdomainsorbindingrequire- mentsonthewh-phraseitself)asrestricted-scopelanguages,andlanguageslikeEn- glish,Japanese,MandarinandKoreanasunrestricted-scopelanguages.Thepropos- alsoutlinedabove,thoughpresentingstraightforwardexplanationsforwhywh-in-situ may be more constrained in restricted scope languages than wh-movement, presup- posethatfinitenessistherelevantfactorintheseasymmetries.Oneofthemainclaims NALA9371_source [06/07 12:34] SmallExtended, Chicago, NameYear, rh:Option 3/45 Wh-in-situinMalayalam 3 inthispaperisthatfinitenessisnotdirectlycorrelatedwithclause-boundednessef- fects in restricted scope languages. I will argue instead that wh-in-situ is uniformly non-clause-bound,andthatapparentclause-boundednesseffectsareepiphenomenal. IdrawprimarilyonevidencefromMalayalam(Dravidian),alanguagethathasbeen argued in the past to have only clause-bound wh-in-situ (Hany Babu 1997; Sriku- mar1992;Jayaseelan2003,2004;Srikumar2007;Madhavan2013).Iwillshowthat therestrictedscopeofin-situwh-phrasesisnotduetoageneralclause-boundedness constraint,butisinsteadtheresultofaperniciousinteractionbetweenwh-Agreement andA¯-operationsaffectingembeddedclauses.Specifically,licensingofawh-phrase isdisruptedbyA¯-movementoftheclausethatcontainsit,anoperationthatishighly favoredandsometimesobligatorywithfiniteCPs.IdevelopaMinimality-basedanal- ysisthatexplainsthisinteraction.Licensingin-situwh-phrasesrequiresestablishing anAgreerelationshipbetweentheinterrogativeCandthewh-phrase1(Simpson2000; Watanabe2006).Thefeaturesontheheadofthemovingclause,however,aresuffi- cientlysimilarto[wh]-featurestointerveneforAgreebetweenthehigherCandthe embeddedwh,aninterventionthathascascadingeffectsonthederivationasawhole. Crucially, when thisillicit configuration can be avoided, long-distancewh-in-situ is possible in Malayalam, demonstrating that potential differences in the scope-taking abilitiesofembeddedwh-phrasesincertainenvironmentsneednotreflectaradically differentsyntaxofwh-in-situinthislanguage. Theremainderofthispaperisorganizedasfollows.Ibeginbypresentingagen- eralpictureofwh-questionformationinMalayalam,includingthefactthatincertain multi-clausalconstructions,long-distancewh-in-situisdisallowed.Iwillthenshow that the ungrammaticality of long-distance wh-questions reflects a general inability ofwh-phrasestotakescopeoutofembeddedclauses—finiteornon-finite—thatun- dergo clausal fronting, an A¯-operation common in the language. I then present the coreofmyanalysis.IarguethatinterrogativeCinMalayalamisageneralizedprobe that can interact with any number of featurally more specific goals, including those on the head of the fronting clause. As a result, in configurations where the clause dominating the wh-phrase bears [A¯]-features relevant for fronting, the interrogative C erroneously makes contact with it. Next, I turn to cleft questions, which provide furtherevidencethatrestrictedscopebehaviorofwh-in-situistheresultoffatalin- teractionsamongA¯-operations.Incleftconfigurations,unlikesimpleclauses,in-situ wh-phrases can take scope out of finite clauses, a pattern I will argue is due to the factthattheillicitinteractionconfigurationiscircumventedinclefts.Iconcludewith aadiscussionofpossibleextensionsofthepresentaccounttootherrestrictedscope languages,aswellasunrestrictedscopelanguageslikeJapanese. 1Thesyntaxofin-situwh-expressionsismuch-debated.Atleastthreecampsofanalysiscanbefoundin theliterature:(i)wh-phrasescovertlymovetoC(e.g.Huang1982),(ii)someQ-relatedoperator,notthe wh-elementitself,undergoesmovement(Hagstrom1998;Cable2010)and(iii)thereisnomovement atall(Baker1970;Reinhart1998).Aswillbeshowninsection2,acovert-movementanalysisisnot supportedbytheMalayalamdata.Forpresentpurposes,IwillassumethatMalayalamwh-phrasesremain intheirbaseposition.Thesyntacticlinkbetweenthewh-expressionanditsscopepositionistakentobe establishedviaAgree. NALA9371_source [06/07 12:34] SmallExtended, Chicago, NameYear, rh:Option 4/45 4 AthulyaAravind 2 In-situwh-expressionsinMalayalam ThemainquestionformationstrategyinMalayalaminvolveswh-in-situ.Insimplex sentences,wh-phrasescanbeleftintheirbasepositionandyieldaquestioninterpre- tation.Weseethisin(3). (3) a. EethukuTTiee pustakamvaayi-chu? which childthis book read-PERF ‘Whichboyreadthisbook?’ b. Ramaneethupustakamvaayi-chu? Ramanwhich book read-PERF ‘WhichbookdidRamanread?’ In-situ wh-phrases in Malayalam do not appear to be island-sensitive, as illus- trated by the fact that they are acceptable inside relative clauses (4a) and adjuncts (4b),bothislandsforovertmovement: (4) a. Raman[ aaruthann-a] pustakamvaayichu? RelC Raman[ who gave-REL]book read? ‘WhichxissuchthatxgaveRamanabookandRamanreadthatbook?’ b. NeeRaman-e [ enthuparanja-ppol]shakaarichu? TempC you Raman-ACC[ what said-while] scolded? ‘WhatissuchthatyouscoldedRamanwhenhesaidit?’ Thissectionwillpresentafullerpictureofwh-questionformationinMalayalam as necessary background. I will start out by providing evidence showing that wh- phrases in Malayalam remain in their base position and do not covertly move to C. I will then show that despite not involving movement, in-situ wh-phrases appear to showpuzzlinglocalityrestrictionsthatappearuniquetothisstrategy. 2.1 Malayalamwh-phrasesasgenuinelyin-situ FocusInterventioneffectscanestablishthatin-situwh-phrasesinMalayalamremain in their base position at the time of interpretation. Focus intervention is the name giventothephenomenonwherein-situwh-phrasesareforbiddenfromappearingin thescopeofcertainscopalorfocus-relatedelements,likenegationoronly.InBeck (2006), focus intervention is argued to be at the source of the ungrammaticality of the Korean sentence in (5), where the wh-phrase nuku-lul ‘who-ACC’ occurs in the scope of the focus sensitive operator man ‘only’. Observe that scrambling the wh- phrasepasttheoffendingelementtoahigherposition,asin(6),seemstorepairthe otherwiseillicitstructure. (5) *Minsu-mannuku-lul po-ss-ni? Minsu-only who-ACCsee-PAST-Q ‘WhodidonlyMinsusee?’ NALA9371_source [06/07 12:34] SmallExtended, Chicago, NameYear, rh:Option 5/45 Wh-in-situinMalayalam 5 (6) Nuku-lul Minsu-man po-ss-ni? who-ACCMinsu-onlysee-PAST-Q ‘WhodidonlyMinsusee?’ (BeckandKim2006) InBeck’s(2006)analysisofsucheffects,whichbuildsonearlierworkbyRooth (1985) and Hamblin (1973), both wh-phrases and focus phrases introduce focus- alternatives into the computation. Intervention occurs when the alternatives intro- duced by the wh-phrase are “picked up” by another operator before they can reach theappropriateinterrogativeoperator.Itisstraightforwardwhymovement,overtor covert,should repairthe illicitconfiguration—thealternatives generatedby thewh- phrasearenolongerinthescopeoftheoffendingoperator,andthuscannotbeacci- dentallyaccessedbyit. FocusInterventioneffectshavebeenarguedtodistinguishbetweencovertmove- ment and in-situ composition of wh-phrases, sometimes within the very same lan- guage(e.g.Pesetsky2000;Cable2010;Kotek2014).Forinstance,observingthatin- situwh-phrasesinEnglishSuperiority-violatingquestions(7a),butnotSuperiority- obeying(7b)questions,weresubjecttointerventioneffects,Pesetsky(2000)argued that the two types of questions differed in where the in-situ wh-phrases were inter- preted. (7) a. *WhichprofessordidonlyFredintroducewhichstudentto ? b. WhichstudentdidonlyFredintroduceto whichprofessor? Though in both cases, the second wh-phrase is pronounced in its base position, in caseslike(7b),itwasarguedtoundergocovertmovement,suchthatatthepointof interpretation,itisnolongerinthescopeofthepotentialintervener. Iftheseargumentsareontherighttrack,focusinterventioneffectscanserveasa usefultoolfordeterminingthepositionofawh-phraseatthetimeofinterpretation, even when this is not transparent from the actual pronunciation site. When we ap- plythediagnostictoMalayalam,wefindthatthelanguagepatternswithKoreanand Superiority-violatingEnglishquestionsindisplayingtheinterventioneffect.When- ever a focus-related element occurs to the left of an in-situ wh-phrase, the resulting structureisungrammatical,asillustratedbythecontrastbetween(8a)and(8b).Asin Korean,scramblingthewh-phrasetoahigherpositionrepairstheviolation(8c). (8) a. Rajanpustakangalaar-kke koduthu? Rajanbooks-ACC who-DATgave ‘WhoalldidRajangivebooksto?’ b. *Rajanpustakangalmaatramaar-kke koduthu? Rajan books only who-DATgave ‘WhoalldidRajangiveonlybooksto?’ c. Rajanaar-kke pustakangalmaatramkoduthu? Rajanwho-DATbooks only gave ‘WhoalldidRajangiveonlybooksto?’ NALA9371_source [06/07 12:34] SmallExtended, Chicago, NameYear, rh:Option 6/45 6 AthulyaAravind IftheresearchtraditionofPesetsky(2000).Beck(2006)andtheirsuccessorsiscor- rect,thesusceptibilityofMalayalamwh-phrasestointerventioneffectssuggeststhat theydonotraisetoC,overtlyorcovertly. 2.2 Wh-asymmetries Thewh-in-situstrategy,whichwesawtobeunproblematicinmono-clausalconstruc- tions,neverthelessfailsincertainbi-clausalconstructions.Inparticular,wh-phrases inside finite clausal complements appear to be highly restricted.2 In (9), where the wh-phraseisembeddedinthecomplementofknow,whichcantakebothinterrogative anddeclarativecomplements,onlytheembeddedquestioninterpretationisavailable. (9) [Sitaeethupustakamvaayikk-umennu]Raman-u ariyaam [Sitawhichbook read-FUT that] Raman-DATknow EmbeddedQ:‘RamanknowswhichbookSitawillread.’ (cid:55)MatrixQ:‘ForwhichbookxdoesRamanknowthatSitawillreadx?’ A verb like vicaarikk- ‘think’, on the other hand, cannot take question comple- ments. When an embedded wh-phrase occurs inside its complement, the resulting structureisungrammatical,asneitheranarrowscopenorwidescopereadingseems tobeavailable. (10) *[Sitaeethupustakamvaayikk-umennu]Ramanvicaarichu? [Sita whichbook read-FUT that] Ramanthought (cid:55)EmbeddedQ:‘RamanthoughtwhichbookSitawillread.’ (cid:55)MatrixQ:‘WhichbookdidRamanthinkSitawillread?’ Thisrestrictionispuzzlinginlightofthefactthatthesameclauseistransparentfor overt extraction, at least in the case of bridge verbs like say or think. Example (11) showsthatlong-distancerelativizationfromfinitecomplementsispossible.In(12), weseethatclefting3fromafiniteembeddedclauseispossible. (11) [[Sita vaayikk-umennu]Ramanparanj-a ]pustakamivideunde [[Sita read-FUT that ]Ramansaid-REL]book here COP ‘ThebookthatRamansaidSitawillreadishere.’ (12) WarandPeaceaane[Sita vaayikk-umennu]Ramanvicaaarich-athe WarandPeaceCOP [Sita read-FUT that] Ramanthought-NOMNL ‘It’sWarandPeacethatRamanthoughtSitawillread.’ In addition, as we see below in (34), embedded wh-phrases seem to be able to takematrixscopeoutofnon-finiteclauses. 2ThereisdebateastowhatcountsasafiniteclauseinMalayalam.Forinstance,AmritavalliandJayaseelan (2005)arguesthatonlyclausesthatcanhostcertainmodals,moodmorphologyand“high”negationcan beconsideredfinite.Thoughthisdebateisnotcrucialtotheissuesinthispaper—itwillbeshownshortly thatfinitenessisnotarelevantfactorforwh-scope—therelevantfiniteclausesintheexamplesusedin thissectionsatisfytheaforementionedcriteriaoffiniteness. 3Seesection5forevidencethatMalayalamcleftsinvolveovertmovement. NALA9371_source [06/07 12:34] SmallExtended, Chicago, NameYear, rh:Option 7/45 Wh-in-situinMalayalam 7 (13) Raman[eethupustakamvaayikk-aan]shramichu? Raman[whichbook read-INF] tried ‘WhichbookdidRamantrytoread?’ OnemightjumptotheconclusionatthispointthatitisacorefactaboutMalay- alam that finite clauses are scope islands for wh-expressions. One possibility, pur- sued by some previous analyses of the phenomena (e.g. Madhavan 2013), resorts to the Phase Impenetrability Condition (PIC) (Chomsky 2001) as an explanation. Perhaps the matrix C cannot Agree with an embedded wh-in-situ because it is too low within another phase to be accessible. However, there are cross-linguistic and Malayalam-specific reasons to believe that languages have mechanisms for accom- plishing long-distance Agree without violating the PIC. For instance, as mentioned earlier,languageslikeJapaneseandKoreandoallowlong-distancewh-in-situacross a phase boundary. More crucially for present purposes, even in Malayalam, long- distance wh-in-situ across a finite-clause boundary is sometimes possible. The in- tendedquestionin(10)canbeformedbycleftingtheentireembeddedclause.Aswe see in (14), a wh-phrase inside a finite embedded clause can receive wide scope in thisconfiguration. (14) [Sitaeethupustakamvaayikk-umennu]aaneRamanvicaarich-athe? [Sitawhichbook read-FUT that] COP Ramanthought-NOMNL ‘WhichbookwasitthatRamanthoughtSitawillread?’ It seems, therefore, that we need another explanation for the ungrammaticality of questionslike(10). Observethatexampleslike(10)arespecialinanotherway:inadditiontobeing finite, the embedded clauses in such examples appear in a preposed position rather thanthecanonicalobjectposition.Thisraisesanimportantquestion:whichofthetwo factors—finitenessorfrontedclauseposition—isresponsiblefortheunavailabilityof wide scope? I will argue that it is fronted clause position and not finiteness that is directlyrelevantforwh-scope.Wefindthatwhenclausesappearinanimmediately preverbalobjectposition,wh-phrasesinsidethemcantakematrixscope;whenthey appearinafrontedposition,thisisnotpossible.Thenextsectionexaminesinmore detailthecorrelationbetweenclausal-frontingandwh-scope. 3 Clausalfrontingandwh-in-situ Malayalam is an SOV language, but clausal complements can and sometimes must appearsentence-initially,resultinginanOSVorder,asalreadyseenin(9)and(10). Itisoftenthoughtthereisastrictcorrespondencebetweenobligatorinessoffronting andfiniteness—finiteclausesmustfront,whereasfrontingisoptionalfornon-finite clauses (e.g. Srikumar 2007; Menon 2011). If this were the case, then it would be particularly difficult to ascertain which factor is directly responsible for the disrup- tionofwh-scope.Iwillshow,however,thatfrontingdoesnotdirectlycorrelatewith finiteness:notallfiniteclausesmustfrontandnotallnon-finiteclauseshavetheop- tiontoremaininanon-frontedposition.Whatisrelevantforfronting,instead,isthe NALA9371_source [06/07 12:34] SmallExtended, Chicago, NameYear, rh:Option 8/45 8 AthulyaAravind prosodicheavinessoftheclauseinquestion.Inparticular,Iwillsuggestthatprosodic constraintsoperativeinthelanguageinteracttoprohibitcertainheavyclausesfrom appearing in a medial position.4 Later in this section, I will offer a precise charac- terizationofheavinessrelevanttofronting.Whatiscrucialforusisthatwecannow construct examples in which finiteness and clausal fronting can be divorced. Once wedoso,weareabletoestablishthatitisfrontingandnotfinitenessthatisdirectly responsibleforthewh-scopepatternswefindinthislanguage. Thissectionisorganizedasfollows.Iwillfirstdemonstratethatfrontingisfeature- drivensyntacticmovement,specificallyA¯-movement.Next,Idiscussthequestionof why certain clauses should possess the features relevant for fronting. I will suggest that the obligatoriness of fronting correlates with prosodic considerations, in par- ticular, the weight of the embedded subject. Embedded clauses with overt subjects cannot remain in their base position, for reasons that I will argue relate to prosodic ill-formedness of such structures. But clauses with unpronounced subjects, finite or non-finite, can remain in-situ, and in such cases, embedded in-situ wh-expressions canfreelytakematrixscope. 3.1 Syntacticpropertiesoffrontedclauses The fronted clause is generally the leftmost element in a given sentence. Previous analysesoffrontedclausesgenerallytakethemtooccupyaspecificdesignatedleft- peripheral position (Hany Babu 1997; Srikumar 2007), an analysis I will adopt in thispaper.Iwillargue,furthermore,thatclausesundergoovertA¯-movementtothis position. Evidence comes from obligatory reconstruction, syntactic locality effects andparasiticgaplicensing,whichIdetailbelow. 3.1.1 Frontedclausesobligatorilyreconstructforbinding Consider(15)below;apronouninsidetheembeddedclausecanbeboundbyaquan- tifierinthematrix,eventhoughthepronounlinearlyprecedesitsbinder5.Thegram- maticalityof(15),then,showsusthatfrontedclausescaninprinciplereconstructfor bindingandthusarguesformovement. (15) [avarude kuTTiaaneclass-il onnaamanennu]oroosthree-um vicaarichu i i [heri child COP class-infirst that] eachwomani-UMthought ‘Eachwomanthoughtthatherchildisfirstinclass.’ EvidencethatthismovementisoftheA¯-typecomesfromPrincipleCeffects.Itis well-knownthatreconstructionforPrincipleCisrequiredforA¯-movement(Lebeaux 1988;Chomsky1995).Theungrammaticalityof(16a)illustratesthatfrontedclauses inMalayalammustreconstruct. 4See Dryer (1991) for a typological survey showing that movement of medial clauses to a peripheral positioniscommonplaceforSOVlanguages. 5Mohanan(1982)arguesthatwhatmattersforbindinginMalayalamislinearprecedence.Thisdoesnot seemtobethecaseforthedialectspokenbymyinformants(fromthePathanamthittaregionofKerala, India). NALA9371_source [06/07 12:34] SmallExtended, Chicago, NameYear, rh:Option 9/45 Wh-in-situinMalayalam 9 (16) a. *[Raman aaneclass-il onnaamanennu]avan vicaarichu i i [Ramani COP class-infirst that] hei thought ‘HethoughtthatRamanisfirstinclass.’ b. ?[avan aaneclass-il onnaamanennu]Raman vicaarichu i i [hei COP class-infirst that] Raman thought The examples in (16) do not contrast perfectly, as the embedded coindexed pro- nounin(16b)issomewhatdegraded.Thisdegradednessisduetoablockingeffect. Malayalam has a long-distance reflexive, taan, which takes human antecedents and is subject-oriented (e.g. Jayaseelan 1998). When the conditions for using taan are met,astheyareinthesubjectpositionofthecomplementofanattitudeverb,speak- ers of Malayalam prefer to use the reflexive instead of a bound pronoun. Thus, the counterpartof(16b)withtaan,asin(17),isjudgedmoreacceptable. (17) [taan aaneclass-il onnaamanennu]Raman vicaarichu i i [SELFi COP class-infirst that] Raman thought Caseslike(16b)areneverthelessjudgedgrammaticalbyspeakers,soItakeittobe sufficientevidencethattheembedded clausereconstructsforbinding.Theexample in (17) gives further support for a reconstruction analysis, since the anaphor can be boundbyamatrixelement,evenwhenitiscontainedwithinafrontedclause. 3.1.2 Argument2:Clause-frontingisisland-sensitive IfclausalfrontingisA¯-movement,weexpectittoobeylocalityconstraintsonmove- ment.Wefindthatthisisindeedthecase.Relativeclausesandtemporaladjunctsare islandsforA¯-extractioninMalayalam,asillustratedbytheimpossibilityofclefting outofthemin(18). (18) a. *SitaaaneRaman[ thann-a] pustakamvaayich-athe RelC Sita COP Raman[ gave-REL] book read-NOMNL Intended:‘It’sSitathatRamanreadabookthatshegavehim.’ b. *SitaaaneRaman[ wann-appol] santhoshich-athe TempC Sita COP Raman[ came-when] become.happy-NOMNL Intended:‘It’sSitathatRamanbecamehappywhenshecame.’ Clausalfrontingissimilarlyrestrictedwhentheclauseisinsideanisland.Asshown below,frontingoutofrelativeclauses(19a)andtemporaladjuncts(19b)isungram- matical. (19) a. *[SitaWarandPeacevaayikk-umennu] njaan[t t paranj-a] CP i CP [Sita WarandPeace read-FUT that] I [ said-REL] aaL-e kandu i person-ACCsaw Intended:‘IsawthepersonwhosaidthatSitawillreadWarandPeace.’
Description: