Liberty and Self in the political argument of republicanism, liberalism and postmodernism Duncan Mackenzie Ivison Presented for the degree of PhD Government Department London School of Economics and Political Science April 1993. UMI Number: U062724 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Dissertation Publishing UMI U062724 Published by ProQuest LLC 2014. Copyright in the Dissertation held by the Author. Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. ProQuest LLC 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 r 70*4-0 xc2 1106^60 Abstract: This thesis examines the relationship between the concepts of liberty and self in three different contexts - republicanism, liberalism, and post-modernism - all of which are products of particular historical traditions, and which present themselves as alternative 'languages' and practices in political argument today. I attempt to delineate the relation between the self and the concept of liberty within which it operates in each context, and more generally, questions concerning the relationship between personality and polity. The tendency of much recent historical and analytical scholarship when looking at these issues, has been to emphasize the radical differences between the traditions and their conceptual foundations, especially between republicanism and liberalism. Without minimizing the obvious differences, I have sought rather in this thesis to emphasize some important similarities in the way each approaches the issues of agency, liberty, and the role and justification of social arrangements. This entails a distinctive reading of some aspects in the history of the development of republican and liberal political argument, particularly in John Locke. An important theme here is the tension between assumptions of natural liberty and autonomy, and the role of the community and government in constructing, fostering, and disciplining the very autonomy that is presupposed. Arguing that the differing accounts of the relation between liberty and self are, in important ways, constitutive of the debate between 'communitarians' and 'proceduralists', I turn to contemporary Rawlsian liberal political theory to see if we can't stand back from this conventional way of looking at the problem and re-think the relations. [Towards this end I make some remarks on the relation between the history of political thought and (so- called) 'analytical' political theory.] I argue that liberal political theory must be 'perfectionist', though not in the way that communitarians argue, and not in the way that liberals fear. Indeed it must be so if it is to have any chance for success, though 'perfectionism' is a particularly inappropriate way of talking here, and has been taken up too easily and uncritically in the literature. Civic republican practices have something to teach us in this context, though not simply the way they respect the 'negative liberty' of individuals within a scheme of mutually enforcing rights and duties. This leads me in part, to consider how liberalism tries to make transparent elements of not only state coercion, but institutional, social, and non-juridical forms of power which work on, or through, citizens of modem democracies, and how these power relations manifest themselves in modem concepts of liberty, and conceptions of the self. Finally, I consider some aspects of the work of Michel Foucault, particularly a series of lectures and papers he gave on liberalism and 'neo-liberalism' to see if he offers a vantage point (if anything) from which to evaluate our conventional ways of talking about, and acting on, our concepts of liberty and self. Ackno wle dgements It was Charles Taylor and James Tully who first inspired and encouraged me to carry on in political theory, and (for better or worse), I am indebted to them for it. James Tully has been of particular help: always interested and supportive, he has remained an important influence ever since I left Montreal. At the LSE my greatest debt has been to John Charvet. He has supervised me from the beginning, and his careful, patient, and meticulous readings and supervisions have never been less than excellent. Brian Barry has cast a critical eye and ear to various drafts and presentations, and gave me the opportunity to expound on my vague formulations in his seminars, with great patience and generosity. I am grateful to he and Anni Parker for their many kindnesses. Janet Coleman was an enthusiastic discussant, and patient listener, when I was struggling to find my way. I am also greatly indebted to all my fellow graduate students, who endured my seminar ramblings and inchoate papers with good humour and sharp, critical acumen. I am especially grateful to Russell Bentley, Robert Dickinson (who also provided superb last minute help), Matt Matravers, Tim Stainton, and James Willson, for reading, or discussing with me, most of what is here: I always learned from them. I would like to acknowledge how much I am indebted to various presentations I have heard, or discussions I have had, in the course of writing this thesis, with Richard Aschraft, John Dunn, Stephen Mulhall, Pasquale Pasquino. Richard Rorty, and Richard Tuck. Robert Dickinson, Tim Stainton, Brendan and Caroline O'Duffy, Dave Powell, Ashley Taggart, and Paula Grasdal, deserve special mention, for all the good times and good friendship. Diana Irving literally saved me, and though she came in near the end, has made it all seem worthwhile. It would not have been possible without her. My greatest debt is to my mother and father (and Deb and Rob too), and not only for all the usual reasons. Their contribution has been such that I find it hard to express just how much they have been part of these past few years, even though I've been on the other side of the ocean. The thesis is dedicated to them, with love. Whatever is of worth herein is almost entirely due to all these good people. Table of Contents Preface...........................................................................................i Part 1 (Ad fontes)...................................................................6 Introduction..................................................................................7 Chapter 1: Ciceronian Themes..................................................20 1.0 Introduction 1.1 A system of libertas. 1.2 Ad exterioribus ad interior a 1.3 What am I now? 1.4 To stylize a freedom Chapter 2: Humanism's change of heart.................................59 2.0 Introduction 2.1 Forms of Ciceronianism 2.2 Change of heart: Christian Humanism and the self Chapter 3: Machiavelli and Liberty..........................................89 3.0 Introduction 3.1 A Machiavellian world-picture 3.2 Moral personality and virtuous action 3.3 Machiavelli and modernity Chapter 4: Liberty and virtue.....................................................127 4.0 Introduction 4.1 Virtuous structures: Rome, Athens, or Jerusalem? 4.2 The juridical 4.3 John Locke, republicanism, and the juridical mode of government Chapter 5: John Locke and the government of men............197 5.0 Juris-prudence 5.1 Foundations 5.2 Be not conformed... 5.3 Civic liberalism Interlude..........................................................................................248 Part 2.................................................................................................261 Chapter 6: Michel Foucault: Early and late modern arts of government.........................262 6.0 Introduction 6.1 Anxious questions and the enlightenment 6.2 Foucault on power - 1 6.3 Foucault on power - II 6.4 Liberal discipline Chapter 7: Liberal conduct............................................................319 7.0 Introduction 7.1 Natural foundations 7.2 The personal is political? 7.3 Liberal circumstances 7.4 Perfecting liberal autonomy Conclusion........................................................................................365 Bibliography.....................................................................................381 The passage from the state of nature to the dvil state produces a truly remarkable change in the individual. It substitutes justice for instinct in his behaviour, and gives his actions a moral basis which formerly was lacking/ Jean Jacques Rousseau, (The Social Contract). 1 don't believe in the old dirges about decadence, the lack of good writers, the sterility of thought, the bleak and foreboding horizon ahead of us. I believe, on the contrary, that our problem is one of overabundance; not that we are suffering from an emptiness, but that we lack adequate means to think all that is happening/ Michel Foucault, (1980). Preface In the last paragraphs of his speech to the Athenee Royal in 1819, Benjamin Constant, after having spent the bulk of his time carefully distinguishing between the liberty of the ancients' and the 'liberty of the moderns', a distinction which would become a horizon (if not a spectre) hovering over the political theory of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, moved to summarize his argument: Therefore, Sirs, far from renouncing either of the two sorts of freedom which I have described to you, it is necessary, as I have shown, to learn to combine the two together...The work of the legislator is not complete when he has simply brought peace to the people. Even when the people are satisfied, there is much left to do. Institutions must achieve the moral education of the citizens. By respecting their individual rights, securing their independence, refraining from troubling their work, they must nevertheless consecrate their influence over public affairs, call them to contribute by their votes to the exercise of power, grant them a right of control and supervision by expressing their opinions; and by forming them through practices for these elevated functions, give them both the desire and the right to discharge these.1 For the most part, we have concentrated on Constant's distinctions when trying to understand our own concepts and conceptions of liberty, and this plea for the reconstruction of the two sensitivities - in the full glare of the modem condition and not in some blinkered 'appeal to an appeal' of an ancient polis - has tended to be ignored, if not ruled out of the conceptual court. Isaiah Berlin's seminal re statement of the main thrust of Constant's speech in his distinction between 'negative' and 'positive' freedom has nothing of the sociological edge of Constant's observations, nor does it take up the ambiguous tension Constant established between the ancient and modem world-pictures, or even the concern for the juridical framework of modem liberty.2 Constant's plea was not for an 1 Benjamin Constant, ‘The liberty of the ancients compared with that of the modems*, in B. Fontana ed. Benjamin Constant: The Political Writings, Cambridge University Press, 1988, pp. 309-328, at p. 328. 2 Isaiah Berlin, Four Essays on Liberty, Oxford University Press, 1969. As is well known, it has been subject to a vast critical literature: see for example, John Gray, ‘On negative and positive liberty’, Political Studies, 28,1980, pp. 507-26; Charles Taylor, ‘What’s wrong with negative liberty’, in Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2, Cambridge University Press, 1985; Gerard MacCallum, ‘Negative and Positive Freedom’, The Philosophical Review, 76,1967,312-34. On the importance of constitutional issues for Constant, especially the structure of representative government, see Pasquale Pasquino, ‘Emmanuel Sieyes, Benjamin Constant et le ‘Gouvemement des Modemes’, Revue Francaise abjuration of government in favour of the unchallengeable primacy of individual right, or the endless pursuit of private interest, but rather to understand the nature of the times, and the need for greater respect for 'customs...affections [and] the independence of individuals', i.e. for a new 'art of government' suited to the 'progress of civilization'; '[government's] must handle all these issues with a lighter and more prudent hand'.3 But it would be too harsh to say that, strictly speaking, Berlin got anything wrong in his defence of the relation between pluralism and negative liberty, for there is no doubt that he too caught a significant sense of Vesprit de Vage, though one we might sense that is now beginning to pass, or at least mutate into something quite different.4 However it is not my goal here, nor will it be in the pages that follow, to pursue the debate over the concept of liberty in terms of choosing one concept over another, nor will I try to isolate some linguistically pristine formulation which answers to its 'real' value-free status.5 Rather, my interest lies in situating the concept of liberty in three specific forms of political argument - republicanism, liberalism, and postmodernism - all of which are elements of our contemporary discourse as a whole, though each providing a distinct approach and purchase on that discourse from different historical and analytical vantage points.6 My other interest lies in the relation between conceptions of liberty and conceptions of self, which as Berlin (and de Science Politique, 37,1987,214-22. 3 Constant 1988, pp. 324, 327; see B. Fontana’s helpful ‘Introduction’, pp. 1-42. 4 Though Berlin saw fit to make certain adjustments to his claims in different contexts; the 1969 edition speaks of the dangers of negative liberty fostering ‘great and lasting social evils’ such as ‘economic individualism and unrestrained capitalist competition’, though in the end these dangers were always less pressing than those he identified with positive liberty (pp. xlv- xlvi). 5 For that, see for example, Felix Oppenheim, Political Concepts: A Reconstruction, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1981; cf. Hillel Steiner, ‘Individual Liberty’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 1974/5. See the essays in David Miller ed., Liberty, Oxford University Press, 1991. 6 Cf. Donald R. Kelley, ‘The Private Life of Liberty’, in J. Klaits M. Haltzel (eds.), LibertyILiberte: The American and French Experiences, Baltimore and London, The Woodrow Wilson Centre Press/ Johns Hopkins University Press, 1991,11-20: ‘true “enlightenment” needs memory as well as reason, and “liberty” is serious and complicated enough to deserve critical historical examination as well as political commemoration’ (p. 19).
Description: