ebook img

Levinas and Analytic Philosophy: Second-Person Normativity and the Moral Life (Routledge Research in Phenomenology) PDF

315 Pages·2019·1.368 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Levinas and Analytic Philosophy: Second-Person Normativity and the Moral Life (Routledge Research in Phenomenology)

Levinas and Analytic Philosophy “An innovative collection of essays written by an impressive group of scholars that demonstrates the important contribution that Levinas’s thought can make to discussions more commonly associated with the analytic philosophical tradition.” —Leslie MacAvoy, East Tennessee State University, USA “With the increasing need to build bridges among the different philosophical traditions and with the growing interest in Levinas’s work, this book will appeal to a significant number of scholars working in Levinas studies, moral philosophy, and philosophy of mind. Fagenblat and Erdur have assembled a first rate group of scholars whose essays will encourage discussions across intra-disciplinary boundaries.” —Claire Katz, Texas A&M University, USA This volume examines the relevance of Emmanuel Levinas’s work to recent devel- opments in analytic philosophy. Contemporary analytic philosophers working in metaethics, the philosophy of mind, and the metaphysic of personal identity have argued for views similar to those espoused by Levinas. Often pursued in isola- tion, Levinas’s account of “ethics as first philosophy” affords a way of connecting these respective enterprises by showing how moral normativity enters into the structure of rationality and personal identity. The volume shows how Levinas’s moral phenomenology relates to recent work on the normativity of rationality and intentionality and how it can illuminate a wide range of moral concepts including accountability, moral intuition, respect, conscience, attention, blame, indignity, shame, hatred, gratitude, and guilt. The volume also tests Levinas’s innovative claim that ethical relations provide a way of accounting for the irreducibility of personal identity to psychological iden- tity. The essays here contribute to ongoing discussions about the significance and sustainability of a naturalistic but nonreductive account of personhood. Finally, the volume connects Levinas’s second-person standpoint with analogous develop- ments in moral philosophy. Michael Fagenblat is Senior Lecturer at the Open University of Israel. He is the author of “Levinas and Heidegger: The Elemental Confrontation,” Oxford Handbook of Levinas (2019); A Covenant of Creatures: Levinas’s Philosophy of Judaism (2010); and other work in phenomenology and the philosophy of religion. Melis Erdur received her PhD in philosophy from New York University in 2013. She has held several postdoctoral fellowships in Israel and published articles in the area of moral philosophy, including “A Moral Argument Against Moral Real- ism,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 19 (3), 591–602, 2016, and “Moral Realism and the Incompletability of Morality,” The Journal of Value Inquiry, 52 (2), 227–237, 2018. Routledge Research in Phenomenology Edited by Søren Overgaard University of Copenhagen, Denmark Komarine Romdenh-Romluc University of Sheffield, UK David Cerbone West Virginia University, USA Phenomenology, Naturalism and Science A Hybrid and Heretical Proposal Jack Reynolds Imagination adn Social Perspectives Approaches from Phenomenology and Psychopathology Edited by Michela Summa, Thomas Fuchs, and Luca Vanzago Wittgenstein and Phenomenology Edited by Oskari Kuusela, Mihai Ometiţă, and Timur Uçan Husserl’s Phenomenology of Intersubjectivity Historical Interpretations and Contemporary Applications Edited by Frode Kjosavik, Christian Beyer, and Christel Fricke Phenomenology of the Broken Body Edited by Espen Dahl, Cassandra Falke, and Thor Erik Eriksen Normativity, Meaning, and the Promise of Phenomenology Edited by Matthew Burch, Jack Marsh, and Irene McMullin Politcal Phenomenology Experience, Ontology, Episteme Edited by Thomas Bedorf and Steffen Herrmann Levinas and Analytic Philosophy Second-Person Normativity and the Moral Life Edited by Michael Fagenblat and Melis Erdur For more information about this series, please visit: www.routledge.com/ Routledge-Research-in-Phenomenology/book-series/RRP Levinas and Analytic Philosophy Second-Person Normativity and the Moral Life Edited by Michael Fagenblat and Melis Erdur First published 2020 by Routledge 52 Vanderbilt Avenue, New York, NY 10017 and by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business © 2020 Taylor & Francis The right of the editors to be identified as the authors of the editorial material, and of the authors for their individual chapters, has been asserted in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A catalog record for this book has been requested ISBN: 978-1-138-61594-6 (hbk) ISBN: 978-0-429-46258-0 (ebk) Typeset in Sabon by Apex CoVantage, LLC Contents Analyzing Levinas vii MICHAEL FAGENBLAT PART I Second-Person Normativity 1 1 Second-Person Reasons: Darwall, Levinas, and the Phenomenology of Reason 3 STEVEN G. CROWELL 2 The Second Source of Normativity and Its Implications for Reflective Endorsement: Levinas and Korsgaard 29 MICHAEL BARBER 3 Grounding and Maintaining Answerability 55 MICHAEL FAGENBLAT 4 Buber, Levinas, and the I-Thou Relation 80 PATRICIA MEINDL, FELIPE LEÓN AND DAN ZAHAVI 5 Commanding, Giving, Vulnerable: What Is the Normative Standing of the Other in Levinas? 101 JAMES H. P. LEWIS AND ROBERT STERN PART II Ethical Metaphysics 123 6 The Concept of Truth in Levinas’s Totality and Infinity 125 MICHAEL ROUBACH vi Contents 7 Levinas and the Second-Personal Structure of Free Will 139 KEVIN HOUSER 8 Personal Knowledge 166 SOPHIE-GRACE CHAPPELL PART III Ethics and Moral Philosophy 191 9 Desire for the Good 193 FIONA ELLIS 10 On Sociality and Morality: Reflections on Levinas, Tomasello, Strawson, Wallace 210 MICHAEL L. MORGAN 11 Rethinking Vulnerability in a Levinasian Context 234 DIANE PERPICH 12 Between Virtue and the Theory of Subjectivity: Noddings’s Care, Levinas’s Responsibility, and Slote’s Receptivity 253 GUOPING ZHAO 13 Levinasian “Ethics as First Philosophy”: In Analytic Moral Philosophy 269 MELIS ERDUR 14 Against a Clear Conscience: A Levinasian Response to Williams’s Challenge 279 SØREN OVERGAARD Contributors 292 Index 295 Analyzing Levinas One would like to think that the “analytic/Continental” divide in phi- losophy is a thing of the past. Philosophers are increasingly overcom- ing the entrenched division, and much good work is coming out of this. Yet there has been almost no commerce between Emmanuel Levinas’s oh-so-Continental “ethics” and analytic philosophers working in moral philosophy.1 It would be unfair to ascribe this merely to disciplinary prej- udice. Heidegger is Levinas’s most important influence, Merleau-Ponty is his most admired contemporary, and both develop substantive positions that his work rivals. Their work, however, is exemplary of the ways and whys of crossing the analytic/Continental divide and have proven to be immensely valuable in approaching fundamental problems in the phi- losophies of mind and action. Why then has Levinas’s thought failed to make the passage from “ethics” to moral philosophy? Two explanations stand out, one concerning the style of Levinas’s writ- ings, the other their substance. Dermot Moran suggests that the “impres- sionistic style of prose with allusions to religious experience” is the reason why “Levinas’s work is largely ignored among analytic philosophers.”2 Michael Slote, a leading exponent of virtue ethics, concurs. Introducing his own account of how “the virtue of receptivity, preceding reason and knowledge” is “a touchstone for other values,” Slote acknowledges, in a footnote, that the idea is close to Levinas’s—but the French philoso- pher “does so in a metaphorical, evocative, highly abstract fashion.” Like Levinas, Slote wants to retrieve moral receptivity from the sway of exces- sive reasoning in ethics and thus aims “for a general critique of Western philosophical thinking,” but he wants to do so unlike Levinas: that is, “in ways that don’t rely on exaggeration or metaphor.”3 When Christine Korsgaard argued that the source of morality is the reflective endorsement of one’s practical identity, Bernard Williams took the liberty of recommending that “Korsgaard may want to consider someone who has tried to work out similar ideas in a different style, Levinas.”4 But she didn’t. It is not surprising then that when Korsgaard expanded her notion of “moral identity” in Self-Constitution and offered a rejoinder to Williams, she overlooked the alternative that Levinas offers viii Analyzing Levinas to Williams’s objection. The objection holds that theoretical and practi- cal reasoning are so thoroughly unlike each other that it is impossible to derive conclusions about what one ought to do by reflecting on what one, including oneself, ought to think about the nature of the world. Korsgaard’s response is to argue that reasoning about what I ought to do on the basis of my practical identity is “committed to deliberating together with others” and, since “both kinds of reasons are public,” they are not so unlike after all. But Levinas emphasizes an alternative Kantian- ism: it is not that practical reasoning is in the final analysis public but that theoretical reasoning is in the final analysis moral, and not because it is public but because it is personal, addressed to some hypothetical other person.5 Williams himself, however, might have noted that his distinction between “ethics” and “the peculiar institution of morality” is one that Levinas’s thought tracks. “The presentation of being in the face does not have the status of a value,” he writes, thus clearly marking the distinction between “ethics” and the domain of values. As he says later: “Responsi- bility is what first enables one to catch sight of and conceive of value.”6 One suspects that it is also Levinas’s style, though it may just be pru- dence, that confines Stephen Darwall to a footnote indicating the proxim- ity between his analysis of “the second-person standpoint” and Levinas’s account of the moral authority of the face. “A similar idea seems at work in the writings of Emmanuel Levinas about encountering the ‘other,’ ” Darwall diffidently suggests, before deferring to Hilary Putnam’s account of how “encountering an other ‘face to face’ involves a second-personal demand for respect.”7 Darwall’s sustained deployment of the history of moral philosophy, including outliers who are proximate to Levinas such as Fichte and Buber, suggests that it is not bias toward “Continental phi- losophy” that inhibits his engagement with Levinas. A similar reluctance is displayed by Samuel Scheffler, who makes do, again in a footnote, with third-hand reports of “related themes” in Levinas’s writings to his idea that valuing in the present is conceptually dependent on strangers who will live after one dies.8 Whether because of its style or for some other reason, Levinas’s thought has been confined to a footnote at the forefront of contemporary moral philosophy. The aim of this volume is to explore these and other roads not taken in order to begin to determine if Levinas’s thought and contemporary philosophy can engage in reciprocal critical appraisal. One way this is done, as the titles and abstracts to this volume make clear, is by engag- ing Levinas’s thought with the work of the thinkers mentioned so far, all of whom are considered in detail in chapters in this volume, as are the moral philosophies of others such as Simon Blackburn, Ronald Dworkin, Martha Fineman, John Gardner, Catriona Mackenzie, John McDowell, P. F. Strawson, Michael Tomasello, and R. Jay Wallace. Another approach applied in this volume consists in conceptual analy- sis of Levinas’s lush language. While its “impressionistic style,” as Moran Analyzing Levinas ix called it, has clearly repelled philosophers chary of its “incantatory force” and “unrestrained metaphorical rhetoric,” there is often a bias in such an appraisal.9 Consideration of Levinas’s fine attention to etymology, to say nothing of the substantive reasons for his choice of words, deployment of metaphor and allusion, and use of a style that emulates a direct first- person approach to the Other, can justly lead to an appreciation of his language as “admirable and most often—if not always—beyond rhetori- cal abuse,” as Derrida deemed it.10 Commendation of style by Derrida will surely not help the cause of Levinas’s philosophy. But conceptual analysis of his language can contribute to deciding between the two appraisals. The challenge of Levinas’s writings is in any case not only a matter of style. The substance of Levinas’s thought is also “counter-intuitive” to philosophers specializing in established sub-disciplines. For if it is clear that Levinas offers something close to but substantively different from notable positions in contemporary moral philosophy, it is not often understood that Levinas’s argument extends well beyond the domain of moral philosophy. Indeed, it is arguable that what Levinas calls “ethics” does not belong to the field of moral philosophy at all but to a more fun- damental level of analysis that we might call the metaphysics of meaning. The complex idea of “ethics as first philosophy” proposes that second- personal moral normativity is constitutive of the normativity of inten- tional content in general. It stands in the Kantian tradition according to which the objective measure of objects is enabled and constrained by formal conditions for the possibility of experience, modifying that tradi- tion by locating the transcendental conditions for intelligibility in the normative claim of an “Other” who makes it possible for me to subject objects to their various measures. One can therefore distinguish “ethics” from moral philosophy, even broadly conceived. Levinas is clearly not addressing himself to first-order moral problems or offering a normative moral theory. But nor is “ethics” a type of “metaethics,” since metaeth- ics supposes that the terms of moral experience are legitimate objects of analysis, whereas “ethics” seeks to show how they become so. On this view, the normativity demanded by “the Other” is constitutive of all intentional acts. Levinas’s thought has failed to make the passage from “ethics” to moral philosophy, then, not because it is moral philosophy à la mode française but because it is something else entirely, a groundwork for the metaphysics of meaning, not morals. If this is right, then the risk of talking at cross-purposes is undeniable, even considerable. It is also a risk worth taking, however. For Levinas’s substantive views about “ethics” include innovative contributions to the philosophy of mind, since he has a distinctive, even unique, conception of the grounds of meaning and truth, and to the metaphysics of personal identity, since he has a novel conception of the nature of free will and selfhood. Accordingly, in addition to relevant positions in moral philoso- phy, chapters in this volume engage Levinas’s work with philosophies of

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.