ebook img

Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity PDF

423 Pages·2021·2.113 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity

Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity Richard T. W. Arthur https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192849076.001.0001 Published: 2021 Online ISBN: 9780191944345 Print ISBN: 9780192849076 FRONT MATTER Copyright Page  https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192849076.002.0003 Page iv Published: December 2021 Subject: Philosophy of Science, History of Western Philosophy Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © Richard T. W. Arthur 2021 The moral rights of the author have been asserted First Edition published in 2021 Impression: 1 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: 2021943456 ISBN 978–0–19–284907–6 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192849076.001.0001 Printed and bound by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon, CR0 4YY Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only. Oxford disclaims any responsibility for the materials contained in any third party website referenced in this work. ForThomasandAlexander Preface IfirstdiscoveredhowinterestingaphilosopherLeibnizwaswhileworkingonmy PhDdissertation on time andthe foundations of physics atWestern inLondon, Ontario in the late 1970s. Reading his discussion of space and time in his controversy with Samuel Clarke, I found I was finally getting some insight into how to interpret the ‘t’ that physicists manipulated in their equations. On my returntoWesternafter ayear inCalabar,Nigeria, myteachingappointments in the Department of Applied Mathematics allowed me leeway to follow up this interestinearnest.IauditedRobertButts’graduateseminaronLeibniz,andgavea talkonLeibniz’stheoryoftimetothePhilosophyDepartment. Initially I had assumed, perhaps naively, that when Leibniz wrote about “the phenomena” in physics he simply meant “what are observed,” and that his accountofphenomenalbodiesasresultingfrommorebasicentities,hismonads orsimplesubstances,wasanalogoustothesituationinmodernphysics.Theidea that the extendedness of bodies is not fundamental, but derives from more primitive entities having the nature of force, did not seem a far cry from the situation as described by quantum physics. Similarly, his notion of the states of substances following one another in a continuous series as a result of their “appetition”(ortendencytowardssubsequentstates)seemedtohaveananalogue in quantum theory, where the Hamiltonian operator acts on a given quantum stateofanisolatedsystemtogeneratelaterstatesofthesamesystem. The more I learned of Leibniz’s metaphysics, however, the more perplexing I found it. As is well known, Leibniz insisted that substances do not strictly speaking interact with one another. He equated their states with perceptions, where perception is taken in the broad sense of a monad’s representation of the universe(moreorlessconfusedly)fromitsparticularpointofview,makingtheir appetition more like a generalization of desire, and rendering monads decidedly mind-like. Yet, Leibniz held, physical bodies are infinite aggregates of monads, andanychangeoccurringinsuchcompositespresupposeschangeinthequalities ofthesimple.Howcouldthisbe?Bodiescouldnotbecomposedfromminds,nor physicalchangesfrompsychicones(asLeibnizhimselfstressed).¹ ¹ Fortheimpossibilityofsuchcompositions,wehavetheauthorityofLeibnizhimself.Ashewrote toJohannBernoulli(September30,1698):“Youwereafraidthatmatterwouldbecomposedofnon- quanta.Irespondthatitisnomorecomposedofsoulsthanofpoints”;andtoMichelangeloFardellain 1690:“itshouldnotbesaidthatindivisiblesubstanceentersintothecompositionofabodyasapart, butratherasanessentialinternalrequisite”(AVI4,1669/AG103),and“asoulisnotapartofmatter, butabodyinwhichthereisasoulissuchapart”(AG105). viii  Puzzlementaboutthewaybodiesandtheirchangesresultfrommonadsis,of course, par for the course. But at least as perplexing for me was the general consensus that Leibniz excluded relations from his fundamental ontology. FollowingRussell,itiswidelybelievedthat,appearancestothecontrary,Leibniz denied relations at the deepest level of his metaphysics. Since it is incontestable thatheregardedspaceandtimeasrelational,thiswould(itisthought)accountfor hisregardingthemasideal.Monads,onthisinterpretation,couldhavenolocation in space and time, and would exist timelessly, like Kant’s noumena, only in the intelligible realm. But such an interpretation, it seemed to me, was directly contradicted by Leibniz himself in many places. In 1703 he assured his corres- pondent De Volder, for example, that there is a place for all changes of both spiritual and material things both “in the order of coexistents, that is, in space,” and“intheorderofsuccessives,thatis,intime”(LDV266/267).Eventhoughthey arenotthemselvesextended,simplesubstancescannotexistwithoutabody,“and tothatextenttheydonotlacksituationororderwithrespecttoothercoexisting thingsintheuniverse”(LDV266–269).Itwasonthisfoundation—namely,onthe mutual situations of coexisting substances through their extended bodies—that Leibnizbuilthistheoryofspace,asheexplained(alltoobriefly)toClarke.Here,it istrue,one may argue that since monads areonlysituated throughtheirbodies, andbodiesarephenomena,thentheserelationsareonlyamongthephenomena andnotamongmonadsthemselves.Itisdifferentwithtime,however,sincethere (as I have long argued) Leibniz bases temporal relations directly on relations among monadic states. This calls into question the idea that the ideality of relations precludes theexistence of monadsin time,or that temporal succession appliesonlytothestatesofphenomena.Butifmonadicstatesareorderedintime, and each state expresses the situations of the bodies of coexisting monads, providing the basis for their spatial ordering, this suggests that space and time arenotmerementalconstructions,butalsohavesomebasisinreality.Howthis couldbeso,andinwhatsense,hasmotivatedthelineofresearchIhavepursued thathasculminatedinthisbook. ItbeganasthreechaptersofaprojectedvolumeonLeibniz’sLabyrinthofthe Continuum,whichIhadoriginallytitledAriadneanThreads.Theideawastohave each chapter corresponding to one of the topics Leibniz himself had included under the rubric of a book project he had conceived in 1676 ‘de Compositione continui,tempore,loco,motu,atomis,indivisibilietinfinito’(AVI3,77/DSR90)— that is, on the composition of the continuum, time, place, motion, atoms, the indivisible,andtheinfinite.Thatproject,however,becametoobigandunwieldy, so I separated off what was pertinent to the theory of substance as a solution to the labyrinth of the continuum, and published that in 2018 as Monads, Composition, and Force, postponing the treatment of time, space, and the more mathematical topics for another volume. Now that remainder has undergone a furtherfission,asIrecognizethatatreatmentoftime,space,andmotion—allof  ix them relational—would form a coherent monograph all by itself, saving treat- ments of the mathematics of the infinite and the infinitely small for further projects. How the arguments of the present work relate to and depend on those ofthepreviousoneIdescribeindetailintheintroductionbelow. In addition to that introduction, this book is comprised by three substantial chapters, each of seven sections, with its own introduction and conclusion, and supplemented by four appendices and a glossary of the technical terms Leibniz used, particularly in relation to the infinite. I have chosen to write a conclusion specifictoeachchapterratherthanwritingageneralconclusion,andIincludein eachsomeobservationsonhowLeibniz’sviewsrelatetomodernthinkingonthe samesubject. Chapter1isbuiltaroundmyfirstpublicationonLeibniz(‘Leibniz’sTheoryof time’, 1985), which I had extensively reworked for intended inclusion in AriadneanThreadsin2008–9.Itissupplementedbymaterialfrommytreatment of the causal theory of temporal precedence (2016) in response to criticisms, as well as from a forthcoming paper on vague states and discontinuous change to appearinaforthcomingFestschriftforMassimoMugnai(thanksareduehereto PeterMomtchiloffforgrantingmepermissiontousemuchofthematerialin§1.5 for that paper). This chapter also includes substantial new material on time and contingency,andonreductionandthenatureofLeibniz’snominalismabouttime. I present a formal exposition of the theory in Appendix 1: the relational core in two versions, compossibility, temporal counterparts, and Leibniz’s complex and innovative views on change and the continuity of time. On this last topic in particular,IbelieveIhavebrokennewgroundhere. Chapter2 builds upon my ‘Leibniz’s Theory of Space’ (2013b)—which itself drew on ideas from my(1987) and (1994b)—although it mainly consistsin new material.IexpanduponthegenesisofLeibniz’sviewsonspace,presentasuccinct accountofthemainfeaturesofanalysissitusasamathematicaltreatmentofspace, andtwosectionsonhowthisrelatestohismetaphysicsofspace.Leibniz’sanalysis situs remained an unfinished project, and our understanding of it will almost certainlyundergochangesandimprovementsasthecollectionandeditingofhis manuscriptsonitproceeds.ButifIhavesucceededingivingsomesemblanceof anaccountofitcompatiblewithmyreadingofLeibniz’smetaphysics,illuminated by the contrast with De Risi’s phenomenalistic interpretation, I will be well satisfied. Chapter3 is a substantial reworking of a paper I finished in the summer of 2019, ‘Causes and the Relativity of Motion in Leibniz’. That paper drew on my (1994a),andincorporatedelementsofotherpapersIpublishedwhileworkingon it,(2013c),(2015a),and(2015b),butitturnedouttobetoolongforpublicationin a journal. It is now about twice as long as it was in 2019, since it incorporates a newsectiononCopernicanismandinstrumentalism,andasubstantialtreatment of the whole question of whether Leibniz’s space could accommodate motion x  throughspaceandtime,andwhatkindof‘spacetime’isimplicitinthis.Idoubtif this is the last word on Leibniz’s views on the relativity of motion, but I believe Ihaveatleastmadeitseemfarmorecoherentthanitisgenerallyportrayedtobe. Since the status of relations in Leibniz’s thought is both crucial to the inter- pretationIgiveinthechapters,andyettooinvolvedforinclusioninthemaintext, Ipresentanessaytreatingthisquestioninthesecondappendix.Inthethird,Igive translations of extracts from Leibniz’s writing on analysis situs over the years, since there is very little available in English translation. In the fourth, I give translations of three drafts Leibniz wrote in Rome in 1689 on the question of therelativityofmotion,CopernicanismandtheCensure.Finally,intheglossary IexplainsomeofthetechnicaltermsLeibnizused,particularlyinconnectionwith theinfinite. It is a pleasure to acknowledge the generous feedback I have received from colleaguesondraftsofthiswork.PreeminentamongthesehasbeenVincenzoDe Risi, with whom I have been discussing and corresponding about Leibniz’s metaphysics of space (and learning from him) ever since I was an examiner for his PhD thesis at the Scuola Normale Superiore in Pisa in 2005. In response to materialIhadaskedhimtolookover(thepenultimateversionsofchapter2and section3.5),hesentmeanexquisite13-pageessay,whichwashugelyhelpfulfor meinclarifyingmyownviewsaswellashis;healsoprovidedemendationsforthe glossary.OsvaldoOttavianialsoreadthroughthewholemanuscriptandprovided me with extremely valuable responses, sources, links, and corrections. Many thanks, too, to the OUP readers, for their feedback on the draft manuscript IsubmittedinSeptember2020,andsuggestionsforitsimprovement.Thathelped metoclarifymythoughtandmyexpositionsofseveralpoints,andalsoprompted metoprovidetheintroductorychapterandglossaryoftechnicalterms.Iamalso very grateful to David Rabouin, Lucia Oliveri, Laurynas Adomaitis, Jeffrey Elawani,andAngelaAxworthyfortheirsubstantialcriticalresponsestosamples Isentthem;toFilippoCostantiniforwelcomeadviceandcommentary,especially onthemereologyinAppendix1;toPaulLodge,JeffreyMcDonough,andMattia Brancato for their suggestions and comments on some of the material; and to Massimo Mugnai, Samuel Levey, Ed Slowik, Nico Bertoloni Meli, Pauline Phemister, Daniel Garber, Tzuchien Tho, Jan Cover, Stefano Di Bella, Ohad Nachtomy, Ursula Goldenbaum, Don Rutherford, Doug Jesseph, Jean-Pascal Anfray, Enrico Pasini, Stephen Puryear, Martha Bolton, Mic Detlefsen, Marco Panza, Laurence Bouquiaux, Arnaud Pelletier, and Gianfranco Mormino for fruitfulexchangesofviewsovertheyearsonvariousaspectsofwhatisdiscussed here.Thanks,also,toDavidRabouinfordrawingmyattentiontotextsonanalysis situs recently prepared from manuscript sources by his team in the ANR MATHESIS project in collaboration with the Leibniz Research Centre in Hanover (Leibniz-Archiv),andtohim,Siegmund Probst,VincenzoDeRisi,and MichaelKempeforpermissiontopublishtranslationsofthreeofthemhere(they  xi are to appear under the Creative Commons licence CC-by-NC 4.0.). I am particularly indebted to Siegmund Probst for his prompt and invaluable expert helpindatingthesemanuscripts. Thanks, finally, to Peter Momtchiloff of Oxford University Press for his unstinting help in seeing this project through to completion, and to family and friendsfortheirforbearanceandsupportinthecreativeprocess.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.