ebook img

Legal Knowledge and Analogy: Fragments of Legal Epistemology, Hermeneutics and Linguistics PDF

249 Pages·1991·4.983 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Legal Knowledge and Analogy: Fragments of Legal Epistemology, Hermeneutics and Linguistics

LEGAL KNOWLEDGE AND ANALOGY Law and Philosophy Library VOLUME 13 Managing Editors ALAN MABE, Department of Philosophy, Florida State University, Tallahassee, Florida 32306, U.S.A. MICHAEL D. BA YLESt, Department of Philosophy, Florida State University, Tallahassee, Florida 32306, U.S.A. AULIS AARNIO, Department of Civil Law, University ofH elsinki, Vuorikatu 5c, SF-OOIOO Helsinki, Finland Editorial Advisory Board ROBERT ALEXY, Lehrstuhlfur Offentliches Recht und Rechtsphilosophie, Christian Albrechts-Universitiit, Kiel GEORGE P. FLETCHER, School of Law, Columbia University ERNESTO GARZON VALDES, Institutfur Politikwissenschajt, Johannes Gutenberg Universitiit Mainz JOHN KLEINIG, Department of Law, Police Science and Criminal Justice Administration, John Jay College of Criminal Justice, City University o/New York NICOLA LACEY, New College, Oxford University NEIL MacCORMICK, Centre for Criminology and the Social and Philosophical Study of Law, Faculty ofL aw, University of Edinburgh ALEKSANDER PECZENIK, Juridiska Institutionen, University ofL und NIGEL SIMMONDS, Corvus Christi College, Cambridge University ROBERT S. SUMMERS, School of Law, Cornell University ALICE ERH-SOON TA Y , Faculty ofL aw, University of Sydney ERNEST 1. WEINRIB, Faculty 0/ Law, University of Toronto CARL WELLMAN, Department o/Philosophy, Washington University The titles published in this series are listed at the end of this volume. LEGAL KNOWLEDGE ANDANALOGY Fragments of Legal Epistemology, He rmeneutics and Linguistics edited by Patrick Nerhot European University Institute, Florence SPRINGER SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Legal ~nollledge Ind analogy fraglenu of legiI eplsulology, herlileneutlcs, and ltngututcs I Pltr!c~ Nerhot (ed.l. p. CI. -- (LiN & phllosophy 11brary : v. 13) Includes btbllographlcal references Ind lndu. ISBN 978-94-010-5438-6 ISBN 978-94-011-3260-2 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-011-3260-2 1. Lall--Interpretnlon and constructlon. 2. Law--Language. 3. ,Jurlsprudence. 1. Nerhot. Patrlck, 1953- II. Serles, La. Ind phl1osophy llbrary ; v. 13. K296.L44 1991 340·.01~--dC20 90-22507 ISBN 978-94-010-5438-6 Printed on acid-free paper AII Righls Reserved C 1991 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht OriginaJly published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1991 Soflco\'cr rcprint ofthc hardcovcr Ist cdition 1991 No part of the matenal protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any fonn or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner. TABLE OF CONTENTS PATRICK NERHUf Introduction.................... ...... ..... .......... ... .............................. ... 1 KARL-HEINZ LADEUR The Analogy between Logic and Dialogic of Law........................... 12 GIUSEPPE ZACCARIA Analogy as Legal Reasoning - The Hermeneutic Foundation of the Analogical Procedure...................................................... 42 CEES W. MARIS Milking the Meter - On Analogy. Universalizability and World Views ..... ........ ............... ............... .......................... 71 JACQUES LENOBLE The Function of Analogy in Law: Return to Kant and Wittgenstein...................................................................... 107 BERNARD S. JACKSON Analogy in Legal Science: Some Comparative Observations........................................................................... 145 vmoRIO Vll..lA Legal Analogy between Interpretive Arguments and Productive Arguments......................................................... 165 PATRICKNERHar Legal Knowledge and Meaning (The Example of Legal Analogy)................................................ 183 ZENON BANKOWSKI Analogical Reasoning and Legal Institutions................................. 198 JAN M. BROEKMAN Analogy in the Law ................................................................. 217 PATRICK NERHOf IN'IRODUCI'ION Reasoning by analogy, or the type of reasoning traditionally presented as the one in which one moves from one object to another on the idea that there is "something in common" between them, remains a fairly mysterious type of reasoning. The two definitions we shall offer, from Cornu and Geny, two famous French lawyersl, will not really eliminate this sense of mysteriousness. The former defines analogy as "the resemblance or conformity of several things among themselves", which may appear to be a minimalist approach, and considers reason by analogy as "a classic process of rational interpreta tion forming part of the exegetic method"2. The latter, traditionally pre sented as the decisive opponent of the French exegetic school, nevertheless locates the procedure of analogy at the very heart of what must according to it be a true science of law3• There is therefore a sense of mystery about a process of reasoning that is nevertheless common, since we very frequently establish a "resemblance" between two different objects and use the more 1 It should be easy to find equivalent definitions in other national legal cultures. 2 G. Cornu, Vocabulaire juridique, Association H. Capitant, P. U. F. , 1987, "Analogie". 3 F. Geny, Sciences et Technique en droit priYi positif, 1922, I; esp. p. 158ff. 2 PATRICK NERHaf accessible of the two to make the other one more comprehensible. There is no need for surprise, then, if this concept has had a "wretched" reputation4 and has been regarded as a "vague, soft, polymorphous, treacherous" con ceptS; Bachelard and Canguilhem have shown how analogy could in certain cases become an "epistemological obstacle". Conversely, the "analogical imagination", as Bachelard said, could playa constitutive role for a determinate science by helping to split up the area of investigation and suggest images that could each become concepts6• Analogy, accordingly, very clearly goes beyond the play of mere metaphors, and can act as an in termediary between already constituted disciplines and a newly constructed reality7. But what does it amount to in legal science? The whole set of texts we are offering has, it seems to me, the considerable interest of fairly substantially covering the major questions that analogical reasoning poses for us. We have thus a diversity of proposed approaches, though all with a common referent, the clearest expression of our modern legal culture (19th and 20th centuries), namely that of law conceived of as a full discourse: Not that our authors, any more than myself, put the question 4 Recherches interdisciplinaires du College de France, Vol. I, Aspects historiques "Analogie et Connaissance" sous la direction de A. Lichnerowicz, F. PerroUlt, G. Cadoffre, Introduction p. 5. 5 Ibid. 6 E. g. C. Menard, "L'analogie de l'equilibre economique exclut-elle l'histoire?", in Analogie et Connaissance, Recherches Interdisciplinaires du College de France, op. cit., p.208. 7 Thus Kepler, cited by D. Walker, in "Kepler's musical theories and analogy" in Analogie et Connaissance, op. cit., p. 65ff., who shows belief in an analogical structure of the universe and of history: "the movements of the heavens are nothing other than a perpetual symphony (rational, not vocal) which moves, through dissonances, through as it were certain suspensions or cadential formulae (through which men imitate the natural dissonances) towards definite, prescribed cadences, each chord being made up of six terms (as it were six voices), and by these marks (cadences) it divides and distinguishes the im mensity of time; so· that it is no longer astonishing that Man. the ape of his Creator, should finally have invented this way of singing in several parts, unknown to the An cients ...... INTRODUCTION 3 of law as an object that has always already been there, systematic and com plete. Quite the contrary. Some, indeed practically all of us, reject this sort of epistemology of law, and where the hypothesis of the coherence of the legal universe is put forward, this is in order to define it in very noticeably different terms from those traditionally used in legal scholarly accounts. If this referent, the law presented as a full discourses, runs through all of the contributions, this is because reasoning by analogy has to be found its specific place within this legal culture. It is the place to locate the problem of "lacunae" in law, which at bottom allows our various contributions to be classified. With Zaccaria and Maris, the question of lacunae is accepted as such (this is, we might say, the "traditionalist" aspect of these two articles, which is counterbalanced by - keeping to the same terminology - "modernist" emphases, sometimes Dworkinian in nature), and becomes the backdrop for considerations of purely hermeneutic type, in Zaccaria, ex tended in Maris to the field of ethics. The papers from Lenoble and Jackson, the former philosophical and the latter semiological, take as their main tar get this legal knowledge where the theory of lacunae finds its place. Then come legal epistemological contributions from Villa and Nerhot, the ques tion of the whys and hows of such a theory being taken as the object of consideration; and Dean Broekman then invites us, as it were, to change universes radically, to ask ourselves about this mysterious operation, which traditional legal methodology dodges, known as "legal qualification". Among these various positions, then, we select our order of presentation of the various authors, with the honour of kicking off going undisputedly to Ladeur. He offers us in particular a historical survey of the use of reason ing from analogy in German legal culture, accompanied by a brief quantita tive overview; this history fits in perfectly, in our view, with the special features of our European legal culture over these last two centuries. 8 A totality which has in the course of the last two centuries in Europe taken on various fonns, since, very schematically, in an initial period (say the last two·thirds of the 19th century) we perceive it as the completeness and systematic nature of law, while in a second period (late 19th century, first four decades of this century more or less, with some diver gence from one country to another) it appears as law's vocation towards completeness and system, and finally comes to be conceived of as coherence (perhaps for the first time in Betti, ureoria Generale della Interpretazione", A. Giuffre, Milan, 1955), law's systematic nature. 4 PATRICK Nl!RHOT While, for instance, the Volksgeist expressed the unity of law while analogy brought about the continuity of identity of the overall legal sys tem, let us not forget that during the same period the so-called exegetic method was also expressing this unity of law, and Comu9, moreover, today sees reasoning from analogy as "a classic process of rational interpretation forming part of the exegetic method". This comparative type of treatment I permit myself is not entirely innocent, since it seeks to show that two the ories always regarded as very different nevertheless come together to express something identical, and quite fundamental. I am thus inviting the reader, and we shall return to this point later, to seek to understand these theories, Volksgeist and exegesis, not as something to be regarded as the completed expression of some fundamental legal knowledge, but on the contrary as secondary, derived creations, more or less a trace of something more gener al, more systematic, more profound: "an order of knowledge" (using a phrase from M. Foucault, who saw what we know chronologically as the 19th century·as an epistemological break, a new way of stating and know ing things). We do not intend within the limits of this introduction to develop this hypothesis, but let us stress in this perspective that in the mid-19th centu ry, more or less, Linnaeus's seemingly impossible enterprise was apparent ly accomplished. The botanist, by looking at a leaf or a fruit, can manage to induce the whole of the tree or plant. In a very interesting work, F. Da gognetlO if even tells us that "with a few petals, Linnaeus unfolded the whole universe, since goo-botany had taught him that the plant implies a soil, a climate, an environment, a region". Cuvier too could describe the whole of an animal from a tooth or a bone. The science of nature ceased to be descriptive and came to constitute "a tight network through which it in formed the living". The scientific spirit of the age, this profound break with the epistemology of the classical age, lay in this articulation of knowledge enabling scientific prediction of the future, describing "this world below" even if not yet visible, inductively filling every type of vacuum. Our idea is that we must seek to understand legal science of the time on the basis of 9 Cornu, p. 1 above. 10 F. Dagognet, Le cataLoglUl de La vie, Presses Universitaires de France, 1970, p. 176. INIRODUcnoN 5 this episteme. Totality, unity (and thereupon systematicity or complete ness) certainty, prediction, were the categories on the basis of which this order of knowledge recognized itself. At bottom, what the rapid but instruc tive positive legal history of analogical reasoning presented by Ladeur in vites us to do is, then, to follow these constant shifts in the order of knowledge on the basis of the traces which are the various succeeding doc trines in legal dogmatics up to the present. Begriffsjurisprudenz (particularly through Laband) conceived of analogy within a philosophy where legal in stitutions were compared to, treated in the same way as, natural laws (Ladeur)ll. It was with the Weimar Republic that "the link between deduc tivism and the continuity of experience is broken" (Ladeur), and we then find Kelsen coming along to express the idea of incompleteness of the legal system. Here too, the argument is not typically German; it can be found particularly in France, despite the force of the civil-law tradition, in Italy etc., and once again what this should show us is what it more substantially reflected, this knowledge on the basis of which we recognize things. The argument becomes increasingly broad: "the assumption of the logi cal-syntactical· order of the legal system and the comprehension of legal practice as deductive rule-application and, ultimately, the presupposition of a system of legal rules which is not itself transformed by its own applica tion are given up" (Ladeur). However, despite acceptance of this "openness", using an item from today's terminology, of the process of self-transforma tion of legal know ledge that leads the idea of unity of the legal system astray, it seems to us that Ladeur is right to stress that the principle of unity as such should not yet be abandoned on that ground12. Having made these three general methodological remarks. and roughly brushed over the main features of our cultural legal context, we may now present our various authors, with the questions they raise. 11 Recall that Geny located the Begriff at the very heart of this "scientific search" for law, where the construct (i.e. legal institutions) expressed the datum (i.e. natural laws). 12 In this connection, it would be fairly easy to show the broad lines of continuity be tween Kelsen and Luhmann, specifically on the basis of this idea of self- creation of norms conceived conjointly with the principle of unity. On this question of autopoeisis, see in particular some conclusions of Ladeur himself, and the work of I. Broekman.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.