ebook img

Legal Conventionalism PDF

197 Pages·2019·2.167 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Legal Conventionalism

Law and Philosophy Library 126 Lorena Ramírez-Ludeña Josep M. Vilajosana Editors Legal Conventionalism Law and Philosophy Library Volume 126 Series editors Francisco J. Laporta, Autonomous University of Madrid, Spain Frederick Schauer, University of Virginia, USA Torben Spaak, Stockholm University, Sweden Editorial Board Aulis Aarnio, Secretary General of the Tampere Club, Finland Humberto Ávila, University of São Paulo, Brazil Zenon Bankowski, University of Edinburgh, UK Paolo Comanducci, University of Genoa, Italy Hugh Corder, University of Cape Town, South Africa David Dyzenhaus, University of Toronto, Canada Ernesto Garzón Valdés, Johannes Gutenberg Universitat, Germany Riccaro Guastini, University of Genoa, Italy Ho Hock Lai, National University of Singapore, Singapore John Kleinig, City University of New York, USA Claudio Michelon, University of Edinburgh, UK Patricia Mindus, Uppsala University, Sweden Yasutomo Morigiwa, Meiji University, Japan Giovanni Battista Ratti, University of Genova, Italy; University of Girona, Spain Wojchiech Sadurski, University of Sydney, Australia Horacio Spector, University of San Diego, USA; Universidad Torcuato Di Tella, Argentina Robert S. Summers, Cornell University, USA Michel Troper, Université de Paris Ouest - Nanterre, France Carl Wellman, Washington University, USA The Law and Philosophy Library, which has been in existence since 1985, aims to publish cutting edge works in the philosophy of law, and has a special history of publishing books that focus on legal reasoning and argumentation, including those that may involve somewhat formal methodologies. The series has published numerous important books on law and logic, law and artificial intelligence, law and language, and law and rhetoric. While continuing to stress these areas, the series has more recently expanded to include books on the intersection between law and the Continental philosophical tradition, consistent with the traditional openness of the series to books in the Continental jurisprudential tradition. The series is proud of the geographic diversity of its authors, and many have come from Latin America, Spain, Italy, the Netherlands, Germany, and Eastern Europe, as well, more obviously for an English-language series, from the United Kingdom, the United States, Australia, and Canada. More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/6210 Lorena Ramírez-Ludeña • Josep M. Vilajosana Editors Legal Conventionalism Editors Lorena Ramírez-Ludeña Josep M. Vilajosana Pompeu Fabra University Pompeu Fabra University Barcelona, Spain Barcelona, Spain ISSN 1572-4395 ISSN 2215-0315 (electronic) Law and Philosophy Library ISBN 978-3-030-03570-9 ISBN 978-3-030-03571-6 (eBook) https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-03571-6 Library of Congress Control Number: 2018965182 © Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. This Springer imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Switzerland AG The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland Contents Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 Lorena Ramírez-Ludeña and Josep M. Vilajosana Part I T he Notion of Convention Pre-conventions. A Fragment of the Background . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9 Bruno Celano Re-examining Deep Conventions: Practical Reason and Forward-Looking Agency. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31 Verónica Rodríguez-Blanco Part II C onventions and the Rule of Recognition Conventions, Reasons and the Law . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 47 Andrei Marmor The Rule of Recognition as a Constitutive Convention . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 65 Jorge L. Rodríguez Social Facts and Law: Why the Rule of Recognition is a Convention . . . . 89 Josep M. Vilajosana Cooperative Conventions, Rules of Recognition and Institutional Practices . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 109 Rodrigo E. Sánchez Brigido On Identifying the Law and Its Supposed Conventional Foundations. A Set-Theory Approach . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 127 Giovanni Battista Ratti v vi Contents Part III Conventions and Legal Interpretation Conventionalism Unchained and Sceptical. A Defence of a Quasi-Realist Account of Legal Statements Against Dworkin’s Criticisms . . . . . . . . . . . 147 Federico José Arena Conventionalism and the Causal Theory of Reference . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 179 Lorena Ramírez-Ludeña The Interpretation of Plans . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 191 Scott Shapiro Introduction Lorena Ramírez-Ludeña and Josep M. Vilajosana The existence of a convention in a given community requires the presence of a recurring behaviour, the belief that the existence of this behaviour is a reason to fol- low it, and a set of expectations generated by the common knowledge of these cir- cumstances. This characterization is already found in the seminal work of David Lewis, and has been adopted, with some variations, as the starting point of the cur- rent discussion on legal conventionalism. The defence of the existence of a connection between legal conventionalism and legal theory has generally been carried out within a positivistic framework. Legal positivists attempt to explain the existence and content of legal systems by making reference to complex social facts. According to them, such facts are dependent on the acceptance of rules, which involve, among other considerations, the adoption of certain conventions on how to recognize or identify those rules. In this respect, the Hartian rule of recognition can be understood as a convention. Taking the previous ideas into consideration, the present work will analyse some of the problems in legal conventionalism, including defining the main features of conventions, the possibility of understanding the rule of recognition as a conven- tion, its role with respect to the existence of legal systems, its normative nature, and the role that conventions play in legal interpretation. All these problems intersect with each other throughout the following chapters. The first part of this book contains the writings of Bruno Celano and Verónica Rodríguez-Blanco, who deal more directly with the problems posed by the notion of convention. In his paper, Celano argues that there are conventions of a peculiar sort that are neither norms nor regularities of behaviour, but both at once. After a brief analysis of the meaning of “convention”, he provides examples of the kind of phenomena he has in mind: bodily skills, know-how, taste and style, habitus (P. Bourdieu), and L. Ramírez-Ludeña (*) · J. M. Vilajosana (*) Law Department, Pompeu Fabra University, Barcelona, Spain e-mail: [email protected]; [email protected] © Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019 1 L. Ramírez-Ludeña, J. M. Vilajosana (eds.), Legal Conventionalism, Law and Philosophy Library 126, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-03571-6_1 2 L. Ramírez-Ludeña and J. M. Vilajosana “disciplines” (M. Foucault). He then puts forth arguments supporting his claim: (a) considerations about the identity conditions of precedents (D. Lewis) and the pro- jectibility of predicates in inductive inference generally (N. Goodman); (b) thoughts about rule-following (L. Wittgenstein); and (c) an examination of some of J. R. Searle’s ideas about the “background” of intentionality. He concludes with some remarks about the time-honoured antithesis nature v. convention. According to Rodríguez-Blanco, there are many key distinctions that play an important role in mapping out plausible ways of thinking about law construed as a social practice. Among the varied dichotomies, the one that has probably been most influential is the distinction between a description of an action and the normative characterisation of an action. The former aims to explain an action without resorting to the values or principles of the agent, while the latter aims to show how actions are part of a normative landscape, where values, principles, and other normative stan- dards play a key role. The focus might be on values, principles, and standards of the agent or on values, principles, and standards that are objective. In previous work she has defended the view that the primary conception of intentional action is normative all the way through. There are no “brute” or “pure” facts about actions, and there- fore actions cannot be grasped primarily by descriptors of the world either mentally, physically, or of a similar sort. She has argued that in order to make intentional actions intelligible, we need to resort to the values, principles, or good-making char- acteristics that the agent aims to bring about in the world. We also need to under- stand that the values, principles, or good-making characteristics of the action provide a unity and intelligibility to the various bodily movements of the agent. This is a complex and occasionally difficult understanding of agency but one that, in her view, is sound. The core elements of this account of agency are that (a) there is a parallel between practical reason or deliberative reasoning and intentional action; (b) practical reasoning involves practical knowledge that is non-observational; (c) the error of an action stems not from what the world looks like but from the perfor- mance of the agent; and (d) intentional action is primarily from the first person or deliberative point of view and therefore it is forward-looking. In her contribution to this book, Rodríguez-Blanco focuses only on (d) and argues that this feature pro- vides the key premise for the conclusion that a characterisation of actions in social practices, including law, cannot be carried out on the basis of descriptions. She first shows that (d) is true and she then describes the best account of actions in terms of descriptions provided by legal philosophers in recent years: the idea that actions and resulting social practices can correctly be grasped as “deep conventions”. Finally, Rodríguez-Blanco shows that conventions sensu stricto and deep conventions require (d) to be intelligible. The second part of the book contains five texts that focus on analysing whether the rule of recognition, first postulated by Hart, can be understood as a convention. In particular, the first three texts are mainly concerned with whether the rule of rec- ognition is a constitutive convention. According to Marmor, many critics have held that Hart did not provide any good reason to think that the rules of recognition are conventions, and in any case, no conventional understanding of such rules is plausible. Others, including Marmor Introduction 3 himself, defend the conventional character of those rules, albeit on different grounds. His main aim in this essay is to clarify his position and provide further arguments in support of the view that constitutive conventions are within the foundations of law. In particular, he tries to show, in the face of criticism that his proposal has received from Postema, that it is still necessary to postulate the constitutive character of the rule of recognition. Indeed, Postema has argued that it is sufficient to extend the notion of coordination employed by Lewis and himself at some earlier time (he now prefers to speak in terms of “cooperation”) to argue that it is not necessary to take Marmor’s step. In contrast, Marmor argues that there are innumerable conventional practices, which would be wrongly described as solutions to pre-existing coordina- tion problems. In his view, insisting on coordination belittles our talent and inven- tiveness as human beings. Our sophisticated social practices are not limited to solving the problems in which we find ourselves. People create practices and activi- ties that they consider valuable, one of them being the law. The second text of the second section, written by Rodríguez, is precisely intended to criticize the position that Marmor has defended in previous works. Essentially, his criticism is that a convention cannot be constitutive, and therefore the rule of recognition cannot be a constitutive convention. According to Rodríguez, the con- cept of convention employed by Marmor is too weak and would lead to considering a rule to be conventional even though all the members of a community follow it because they consider it to be correct. The rule may not be conventional, though everyone is following it because others follow it. Moreover, it seems pointless to speak of constitutional conventions inasmuch as, according to Rodríguez, the idea of the arbitrary character of conventions is incompatible with the constitutive char- acter of a rule. Consequently, Marmor’s view is affected by an internal inconsis- tency because, by its own definitions, the constitutive character of the rule of recognition would be incompatible with its conventional character. The third text, by Vilajosana, is intended to show that the existence of law in a given society requires a unitary practice of rule identification (a rule of recognition). It is also argued that the best way of understanding this rule is to see it as a constitu- tive convention, which allows for the autonomous identification of the law of a particular community. According to Vilajosana, “just as the existence of money requires the belief that it exists, the existence of a legal system depends ultimately on a set of beliefs shared by the relevant persons”. After developing this position, a series of recurrent criticisms against conventional conceptions is revisited with the aim of rejecting them. These criticisms include that the rule of recognition as a con- vention does not account for the normative nature of the convention, nor would it account for the presence of principles in legal systems, nor the disagreements between lawyers. Finally, the problem of the arbitrariness of the rule of recognition and its alleged banality is addressed. The second section ends with the contributions of Sánchez Brigido and Ratti. According to Sánchez Brigido, after abandoning the idea that the rule of recognition is a coordinative convention in Lewis’s sense, Postema offered a new, more sophis- ticated version of conventionalism. According to this new version, the rule of recog- nition should be understood not as a coordinative convention, but as a cooperative

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.