ebook img

Learnability and Linguistic Theory PDF

220 Pages·1989·5.693 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Learnability and Linguistic Theory

LEARN ABILITY AND LINGUISTIC THEORY STUDIES IN THEORETICAL PSYCHOLINGUISTICS Managing Editors: Tom Roeper, Dept. of Linguistics, University of Massachusetts at Amherst Kenneth Wexler, Dept. of Brain and Cognitive Science, MIT, Cambridge, Mass. Editorial Board: Robert Berwick, Artificial Intelligence Laboratory, MIT, Cambridge, Mass. Manfred Bierwisch, Zentralinst. flir SprachwissenschaJt, Akademie der WissenschaJten der DDR Merrill Garrett, University ofA rizona,'Tucson Lila Gleitman, School of Education, University of Pennsylvania Mary-Louise Kean, University of California at Irvine Howard Lasnik, University of Connecticut at Storrs John Marshall, Neuropsychology Unit, Radcliffe Injirmwy, Oxford Daniel Osherson, MIT, Cambridge, Mass. Yukio Otsu, Tokyo Gakugei University, Tokyo Edwin Williams, Princeton University VOLUME 9 LEARNABILITY AND LINGUISTIC THEORY Edited by ROBERTI. MATTHEWS Rutgers University, New Brunswick, N.J., U.S.A. and WILLIAM DEMOPOULOS University of Western Ontario, London, Ontario, Canada KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERS DORDRECHT I BOSTON I LONDON Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Learnab11ity and linguistic theory I edited by Robert J. Matthews and William Demopoulos. p. cm. -- (Studies in theoretical psycholinguistics> Inc 1u des index. ISBN -13:978-0-7923-0558-3 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-009-0955-7 DOl: 10.1007/978-94-009-0955-7 1. Language acquisition. 2. Learning ability. 3. Grammar, Comparative and general. 4. Psycholinguistics. I. Matthews, Robert J., 1943- II. Demopoulos, William. III. Series. P118.L3898 1989 401 •• 93--dc20 89-2556 Published by Kluwer Academic Publishers, P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, The Netherlands. Kluwer Academic Publishers incorporates the publishing programmes of D. Reidel, Martinus Nijhoff, Dr. W. Junk, and MTP Press. Sold and Distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada by Kluwer Academic Publishers, 101 Philip Drive, Norwell, MA 02061, U.S.A. In all other countries, sold and distributed by Kluwer Academic Publishers Group, P.O. Box 322, 3300 AH Dordrecht, The Netherlands. All Rights Reserved © 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, The Netherlands Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 1989 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner TABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE vii ROBERT J. MATTHEWS I Introduction: Learnability and Linguistic Theory 1 DANIEL N. OSHERSON, MICHAEL STOB, and SCOTT WEINSTEIN I Learning Theory and Natural Language 19 ROBERT J. MATTHEWS I The Plausibility of Rationalism 51 WILLIAM DEMOPOULOS IOn Applying Learnability Theory to the Rationalism-Empiricism Controversy 77 HOWARD LASNIK IOn Certain Substitutes for Negative Data 89 STEVEN PINKER I Markedness and Language Development 107 JANET DEAN FODOR I Learning the Periphery 129 JOHN TRUSCOTT and KENNETH WEXLER I Some Prob- lems in the Parametric Analysis of Learnability 155 DAN FINER and THOMAS ROEPER I From Cognition to Thematic Roles: The Projection Principle as an Acquisition Mechanism 177 LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS 211 INDEX OF NAMES 213 INDEX OF SUBJECTS 215 v PREFACE The impetus for this volume developed from the 1982 University of Western Ontario Learnability Workshop, which was organized by the editors and sponsored by that University's Department of Philosophy and the Centre for Cognitive Science. The volume e~plores the import of learnability theory for contemporary linguistic theory, focusing on foundational learning-theoretic issues associated with the parametrized Government-Binding (G-B) framework. Written by prominent re searchers in the field, all but two of the eight contributions are pre viously unpublished. The editor's introduction provides an overview that interrelates the separate papers and elucidates the foundational issues addressed by the volume. Osherson, Stob, and Weinstein's "Learning Theory and Natural Language" first appeared in Cognition (1984); Matthews's "The Plausi bility of Rationalism" was published in the Journal of Philosophy (1984). The editors would like to thank the publishers for permission to reprint these papers. Mr. Marin Marinov assisted with the preparation of the indices for the volume. VB ROBERT 1. MATTHEWS INTRODUCTION: LEARNABILITY AND LINGUISTIC THEORY 1. INTRODUCTION Formal learning theory, as the name suggests, studies the learnability of different classes of formal objects (languages, grammars, theories, etc.) under different formal models of learning. The specification of such a model, which specifies (a) a learning environment, (b) a learn ing strategy, and (c) a criterion for successful learning, determines (d) a class of formal objects, namely, the class that can be acquired to the level of the specified success criterion by a learner implementing the specified strategy in the specified enviroment. jormal model oj learning: ----------(-;a", /b, c', )-d. ......... -..... -- --- ,,/,'. -. ..... ....- ," learning learning success class of formal objects environment strategy criterion (that can be acquired, in the sense of c, by bon in a) that tHe; IC;a.l11C;l 1 c;a.llL.C;~ d lc;:allll11e, lUlI\...-UUll tHdt 111ap~ un::; Ival1ung environment into these formal objects. Specifically, it is assumed that both the environment and acquired objects can be coded by the nat ural numbers, so that the learner can be construed as realizing a function on the natural numbers. Formal learning theory makes no general assumptions as to whether the learning function is, for ex ample, recursive or non-recursive, partial or total, computable or non computable, though, of course, the particular models of investigated by formal learning theorists will make such assumptions in the course of specifying the learning strategy employed in the models. Work in formal learning theory began in the mid-1960's, with papers by Solomonoff (1964), Gold (1967), Feldman (1972), Blum and Blum (1975), and others. Especially influential was Gold's paper "Language Identification in the Limit," which proved a number of important Robert f. Matthews and William Demopoulos (eds.). Leamability and Linguistic lheory. 1-17. © 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers. 2 ROBERTJ.MATTHEWS formal results regarding a restricted class of learning models which has come to be known as the "Gold paradigm." Much of the subsequent work in formal learning theory, most notably that of Osherson et al. (1982, 1984, 1986) and Osherson and Weinstein (1982, 1983), has concerned itself with extensions and generalizations of this paradigm. The intellectual interest of formal learning theory lies in the possibi lity that it may contribute significantly to an explanation of how it is that we are able to come to know what we know on the basis of limited experience (what Chomsky [1986] has dubbed "Plato's problem"). Presumably formal learning theory would do this by specifying the class of learning functions that human learners realize and in virtue of which they are able to map a course of experience into knowledge. Some hope that formal learning theory will enable us to recast the much-discussed debate between rationalists and empiricists in terms of competing claims regarding the learning functions realized by human learners. Such a reformulation of the debate might enable us to see what empirical evidence, if any, would decide the issues in that debate one way or another. Formal learning theorists have emphasized the import of their re sults for linguistics. Specifically, they claim that formal learning theory can provide non-trivial conditions of explanatory adequacy on theories of natural language.1 Osherson and Weinstein (1983, p. 37) put the claim this way: For a class of languages to be the natural languages, the class must be learnable by children on the basis of the kind of linguistic exposure typically afforded the young. Call this the leamability condition on the class of natural languages. Formal learning theory is an attempt to deploy precise versions of the learnability condition in the evaluation of theories of natural language. In the present context, such a theory will specify (a) the kind of linguistic input available to children, (b) the process by which children convert that experience into successive hypotheses about the input language, and (c) the criteria for "internalization of a language" to which children ultimately conform. From (a)-(c) it should be possible to deduce (d) the class of languages that can be internalized in the sense of (c) by the learning mechanism specified in (b) operating on linguistic input of the kind characterized in (a). Such a theory is correct only if (d) contains exactly the natural languages. Linguists agree that linguistic theories must satisfy a learnability condition, namely, that the set of grammars made available by an adequate linguistic theory must be such that any member of this set could be acquired by child-learners on the basis of the kind of linguistic experience typically afforded them for learning language. (This is just Chomsky's condition of explanatory adequacy.) Yet many linguists INTRODUCTION 3 tend to dismiss the claim of formal learning theorists to be able to provide non-trivial adequacy conditions on linguistic theories. More over, they assume (and indeed claim) that the fact that recently pro posed linguistic theories make available only a finite number of grammars for natural languages insures that these theories satisfy the learn ability condition. As one well-known linguist put it, "there's no theory of leamability if there's only a fInite number of core grammars." Both claims deserve careful scrutiny. 2. LEARNING-THEORETIC ADEQUACY CONDITIONS ON LINGUISTIC THEORY The reason that many linguists have thought it unlikely that formal learning theory can provide non-trivial adequacy conditions on ling uistic theory is presuIl)ably this: a set of conditIons are adequacy conditions on any explanatorily adequate linguistic theory only if they can be justified without recourse to any existing linguistic theory. Otherwise these conditions would simply affirm without independent argument a preference for the theoretical assumptions of a particular theory or class of theories. It is just this meta-requirement on ade quacy conditions that formal learning theorists would appear unable to meet. Adequacy conditions on linguistic theory are necessary con ditions for a linguistic theory's being true; such conditions are justified by demonstrating that they are (would be) satisfied by a true theory. The claim of formal learning theorists to be able to provide such conditions rests on the presumption that formal learning-theoretic re sults can provide the required justification for proposed conditions. But this, many linguists believe, is highly unlikely given that it does not seem possible even to formulate a correct (or even approximately correct) learning model for natural language using the recursive theoretic vocabulary in which formal learning-theoretic results are couched. If a reasonable approximation of the correct model cannot be formulated in the vocabulary of formal learning theory, then it is unclear how the learning-theoretic justification of proposed adequacy conditions would proceed: how could one demonstrate that these con ditions would be satisfied by a true theory? In order to appreciate formal learning theory'S inability to formulate even a reasonable approximation of the correct learning model for natural language, consider, for example, the empirically plausible sug gestion that the criterion of successful acquisition incorporated in the correct model of language learning permits the language acquired by a 4 ROBERTJ.MATTHEWS successful learner to differ in certain precise ways from the language to which he is exposed. It would be extremely implausible to suppose that the correct criterion is captured by any of the finite-difference criteria investigated by Osherson and Weinstein (1982). (Such criteria count the learner successful in acquiring a language L just in case he con verges on some language L' such that the symmetric difference be tween these two languages is finite.) The problem with these criteria is not simply that they would count as having s.uccessfully acquired English the learner who acquired a language differing from English in that all strings of length n or less (say, n = 2,000 words) were sentences of a different language (e.g., French), though this, of course, is a problem. Rather the problem is that these criteria focus on the number of differences permitted by the success criterion, rather than on the sort of differences permitted. Available empiricaI-evidence regarding idio lectal variation suggests that successful acquisition of a natural langu age requires that the learner acquire a core of a linguistic constructions shared by all speakers of the language, while permitting idiolectal variation in certain peripheral constructions. Thus, for example, suc cessful acquisition of English would seem to require that the learner master the aspects of bounding, government, thematic-role assign ment, binding, case, and control that are peculiar to English, while at the same time permitting idiolectal variation in such peripheral con structions as the optional contraction of I want to stay to I wanna stay. Of course, if as seems certain the idiolectal variation permitted by the success criterion must be stated in terms of grammatical rules or principles, then this variation will be non-finitary, since the differences in rules will be projected over the non-finitary fragment of the lan guage generated by means of derivations that employ the rules in question. (The symmetric difference between two languages that differ only in whether they permit wanna-contraction, for example, will be non-finitary. ) The point here is not that these finite difference criteria are not plausible candidates for the correct success criterion for natural lan guage learning; no one, including formal learning theorists such as Osherson and Weinstein, thinks that they are. Rather the point is that it seems extremely implausible to suppose that the correct criterion can be stated independently of the theoretical resources made available by the correct linguistic theory. Similar remarks could be made regarding the correct specification of the learning environment and the learning

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.