ebook img

Law as Politics: Carl Schmitt’s Critique of Liberalism PDF

333 Pages·1998·22.051 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Law as Politics: Carl Schmitt’s Critique of Liberalism

LAW as POLITICS en U I - ...J o c.. Carl Schmitt's Critique of Liberalism Edited by David Dyzenhaus Foreword by Ronald Beiner <C DUKE UNIVERSITY PRESS ...J DURHAM AND LONDON © 1998 DUKE UNIVERSITY PRESS All rights reserved I Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper @) I Typeset in Trump Mediaeval by Tseng Information Systems, Inc. I Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data appear on the last printed page of this book. Grateful acknowledgment is made for permis- sion to reprint the following material in this volume: I Ernst-Wolfgang Bockenforde, "Der Begriff des Politischen als Schliissel zum staats rechtlichen Werk Carl Schmitts," in Ernst-Wolfgang Bockenforde, Recht; Staat; Freiheit: Studien zur Rechtsphilosophie, Staatstheorie und Verfassungs geschichte. © Suhrkamp Verlag Frankfurt am Main 199I. I William E. Scheuerman, "Revolutions and Constitutions: Hannah Arendt's Challenge to Carl Schmitt." © Rowen & Littlefield Publishers, Inc., Lanham, Md., 1998. I Portions of this volume were previously published in The Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence, vol. IO, no. I 119971. II) Foreword Ronald Beiner vii I 1 1 Z Acknowledgments xi LLI 1 I Z Introduction: Why Carl Schmitt? David Dyzenhaus II o 1 U PART I POLITICAL THEORY AND LAW Carl Schmitt's Critique of Liberalism: Systematic Recon struction and Countercriticism Heiner Bielefeldt 23 1 1 The Concept of the Political: A Key to Understanding Carl Schmitt's Constitutional Theory Ernst-Wolfgang 1 Bockenforde 37 1 From Legitimacy to Dictatorship-and Back Again: Leo Strauss's Critique of the Anti-Liberalism of Carl Schmitt 1 Robert Howse 56 1 Hostis Not Inimicus: Toward a Theory of the Public in the Work of Carl Schmitt Ellen Kennedy 192 1 Pluralism and the Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy 1 Dominique Leydet 109 1 Liberalism as a "Metaphysical System": The Methodological Structure of Carl Schmitt's Critique of Political Rationalism 1R einhard Mehring 1131 Carl Schmitt and the Paradox of Liberal Democracy 1 Chantal Mouffe 1159 PART II LECAL THEORY AND POLITICS Carl Schmitt on Sovereignty and Constituent Power Renato 1 Cristi 1 179 vi Contents The 1933 "Break" in Carl Schmitt's Theory I Ingeborg Maus I 196 The Dilemmas of Dictatorship: Carl Schmi~t and Constitu tional Emergency Powers I John P. McCormick I 217 Revolutions and Constitutions: Hannah Arendt's Challenge to Carl Schmitt I William E. Scheuerman 1252 Carl Schmitt's Internal Critique of Liberal Constitutional ism: Verfassungslehre as a Response to the Weimar State Crisis I Jeffrey Seitzer I 281 Notes on Contributors I 313 Index 1315 Foreword Ronald Beiner It should come as no surprise that there are radically conflicting con ceptions of what it is to practice political philosophy; and the clash between these opposed interpretations of the praxis of theorizing is not only inevitable but also desirable. According to one dominant concep tion, of which Rawls's Political Liberalism is an exemplary instance, we start with an implicit consensus on what we share as members of a liberal political order, and the job of the philosopher is to articulate the basis of this consensus and raise it to theoretical explicitness. According to a different and more radical understanding of political philosophy, this liberal consensus, if such exists, counts for nothing; rather, the phi losopher's responsibility is to theorize political order from the ground up, even if it ends up calling into fundamental question the opinions and beliefs that currently sustain social life within a liberal democratic horizon. From this alternative point of view, political philosophy prac ticed in a Rawlsian mode is a form of theoretical cowardice, perhaps even a betrayal of what properly defines philosophical duty. There is no question that Carl Schmitt embodies the latter conception of theory in its most uncompromising version. As David Dyzenhaus ex presses with beautiful clarity in his introductory chapter, Schmitt raises questions about the ultimate grounding of political and legal order that have dogged modern philosophy and jurisprudence since Hobbes first came to awareness of the obsolescence of pre-modern justifications of political authority. In pursuing this radical inquiry, Schmitt challenges, root-and-branch, all the notions that "we" modern liberals take to be morally authoritative-the meaning of the rule of law, the legitimacy of parliamentary government, the superiority of reason and rational delib eration over sheer will, the reasonableness of political secularity. None viii Foreword of these notions carries any obvious authority for Schmitt; all of them are put to the test. I don't think anyone can plausibly argue that contemporary liberal democracies are subject to the kind of thoroughgoing crisis of political order that Schmitt encountered in the Weimar Germany of the 1920S and that provoked him, throughout his work, to interrogate liberalism at the level of first principles. On the other hand, neither does it seem that the foundations of liberal politics are so secure, theoretically or politically, that reflection at the level of first principles has been ren dered pointless. One can identify both universalistic (philosophical) and particularistic (political) reasons for pursuing the debate with liberalism at the bracing level at which it is pursued by Schmitt. First, as human beings we of course have a universal interest in knowing whether the social order we happen to inhabit actually possesses the kind of norma tive authority that it claims for itself. The historically established name for pursuit of this human interest is philosophy. Second, as citizens of a liberal regime, we can only vindicate the liberal idea that intellec tual openness and freedom of inquiry strengthen rather than subvert a political order by entering into dialogue with those forms of thought that are furthest from the liberal horizon. If political philosophy involves not only reconfirming the reason ableness of the beliefs to which we are already committed but also challenging those beliefs (Socratically) from a position well outside the boundaries of liberalism, then we can derive immense instruction from the very fine essays that Dyzenhaus has assembled in this volume. See ing what our liberal world looks like from an illiberal point of view is not only indispensable for intellectual life within a liberal society; it may even do liberal politics some good. As Chantal Mouffe helpfully reminds us at the beginning of her essay, it's no accident that Rawls refers to Schmitt's antiliberalism on the last page of his introduction to the paperback edition of Political Liberalism, in the context of re stating why the constitutional stability of the liberal polity continues to require liberal political philosophy. Is a dialogue between Rawls and Schmitt possible? If, as liberals, we know in advance that Rawls must triumph in such a debate, what is the point of pursuing this intellectual contest in the first place? Liberal aca demics and democratic theorists certainly aren't immersing themselves in the study of Schmitt because they welcome the possibility that he will persuade them to jettison their liberal and democratic commitments. Foreword ix Rather, they study Schmitt because they know that, philosophically, liberal principles have not (yet) established an unchallengeable claim to normative authority, and because only by engaging in dialogue with a steadfast enemy of liberal dialogue like Schmitt can they vindicate both liberalism and the endless dialogue that is political philosophy.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.