ebook img

Law and Philosophy of Language: Ordinariness of Law PDF

135 Pages·2021·1.96 MB·
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Law and Philosophy of Language: Ordinariness of Law

Law and Philosophy of Language Academic legal production, when focusing on the study of law, generally grasps this concept on the basis of a reference to positive law and its practice. This book differs clearly from these analyses and integrates the legal approach into the phi- losophyofnormative language,philosophical realismandpragmatism. Notonlyis the aim to place the examination of law in the immanence of its practice, but also totakenoteof thefact thatlegal enunciationmust betakenseriously. Inorderto arrive at this analysis, it is necessary to go beyond traditional perspectives and to basethereflectiononaninvestigationoftheconditionsforenunciatinglawinour democracies. Thus, this analysis offers a renewal of the ethics inherent in the action of jurists and an original reflection on the role of certain legal tools such as concepts, categories, or "provisions". In this sense, the work nourishes its origin- ality not only by the transversality of its approach, but also by the will to situate legal thought in concrete forms of its implementation. The book will be essential reading for academics working in the areas of legal theory, legal philosophy and constitutional theory. Pascal Richard is Lecturer in Public Law at the University of Toulon, France. Routledge Research in Constitutional Law This series features thought-provoking and original scholarship on constitutional lawandtheory.Booksexplorekeytopics,themesandquestionsinthefieldwitha particularemphasisoncomparativestudies.Whererelevant,titleswillengagewith political and social theory, philosophy and history in order to offer a rounded analysis of constitutions and constitutional law. Series Editor: David Marrani Available titles in this series include: Constitutional Law, Religion and Equal Liberty The Impact of Desecularization Azin Tadjdini Kant, Global Politics and Cosmopolitan Law The World Republic as a Regulative Idea of Reason Claudio Corradetti Diversity of Law in the United Arab Emirates Privacy, Security and the Legal System Kristin Kamøy Sovereignty, Civic Participation, and Constitutional Law The People versus the Nation in Belgium Edited by Brecht Deseure, Raf Geenens and Stefan Sottiaux Law and Philosophy of Language Ordinariness of Law Pascal Richard For more information about this series, please visit: www.routledge.com/Routledge-Research-in-Constitutional-Law/book-series/ CONSTLAW Law and Philosophy of Language Ordinariness of Law Pascal Richard Firstpublished2021 byRoutledge 2ParkSquare,MiltonPark,Abingdon,OxonOX144RN andbyRoutledge 605ThirdAvenue,NewYork,NY10158 RoutledgeisanimprintoftheTaylor&FrancisGroup,aninformabusiness ©2021PascalRichard TherightofPascalRichardtobeidentifiedasauthorofthisworkhasbeen assertedbyhiminaccordancewithsections77and78oftheCopyright, DesignsandPatentsAct1988. Allrightsreserved.Nopartofthisbookmaybereprintedorreproducedor utilisedinanyformorbyanyelectronic,mechanical,orothermeans,now knownorhereafterinvented,includingphotocopyingandrecording,orinany informationstorageorretrievalsystem,withoutpermissioninwritingfromthe publishers. Trademarknotice:Productorcorporatenamesmaybetrademarksorregistered trademarks,andareusedonlyforidentificationandexplanationwithoutintent toinfringe. BritishLibraryCataloguing-in-PublicationData AcataloguerecordforthisbookisavailablefromtheBritishLibrary LibraryofCongressCataloging-in-PublicationData Acatalogrecordhasbeenrequestedforthisbook ISBN:978-0-367-65562-4(hbk) ISBN:978-0-367-65564-8(pbk) ISBN:978-1-003-13010-9(ebk) DOI:10.4324/9781003130109 TypesetinGalliard byTaylor&FrancisBooks Contents List of illustrations vi Introduction 1 1 The constitutional judge to the test of transgression: The example of the decision of March 26, 2020 8 2 The categoryof “fundamentalrights”: Fundamentalityorthevirtueof importance 29 3 Is it still possible to criticise the Council of State?: For a logical examination of the validity of the administrative judge’s “creations” 49 4 The meaning of the fault “as such …” 64 5 “Dispositional concepts” in law 78 6 The impossible experience of rapport in the work of Professor A. Conte… 98 7 The ordinariness of a political commitment and its normativities 106 Bibliography 118 Index 123 Illustrations Figure 1.1 Topology and boundaries 28 Tables 1.1 Synoptic tables of validities and relationships between the dimensions of validity 26 5.1 References of legal statements: synthesis of theoretical approaches 95 Introduction Byusingthisreferencetothe“ordinarinessofthelaw”wecangivetheappearance of giving in to a facility of language and thus mask an ambiguity that would be inherent in our discourse: the rhetorical ornament would then become the bedrock of equivocation. Indeed, what is the nature of this ordinary that will be the core of our discourse? Is it the ordinary of the interpretation of law? Is it the ordinary of its implementation? The ordinary of its creation? Similarly, what law are we talking about? Is it a disciplinary field? Is it a specific dis- course? Positive law? Will the law be an opportunity, through a metonymic shift, to deal with the norm, the legal rule or the legal utterance? Theaimofthisbookistosynthetisizeinitsownway,thesevariousquestionsand to offer an original response to the question of the nature of law and its effective integration into a social space. The challenge lies, in this way, in our willingness to question some dichotomies (law and language, effectiveness and validity, meaning and significance, norms and law, normativism and realism) which are strongly rootedinlegalthinkingandwhichnowseemtohavetobeovercomebecausethey are so many resistances to the legal phenomenon itself. Very often, thought, when enlever le “it is” constructed on the basis of such opposition, avoids grasping the very nature of this dichotomy and its consequences for the object that is to be thought about: the semblance of this dialectic obscures its essence or reality. What makestheordinaryoflawascreenisthusthescreenonwhichitisprojectedinlegal language: its representation. For Kelsen, for example, the norm can be understood either as a simply thought norm or as a valid norm. The simply thought norm can be hypothetical (this is the case of the fundamental norm) or an effective norm which ismerelythe representationinawarenessofthe valid norm.1 The reason why we have relied – in this book – on this idea of the ordinary of law is to evoke the ultimately simple and pragmatic – but always hidden – notion that the extraordinary of the legal phenomenon (its “magic” capacity to generate normative effects) exists in legal discourse only as the ordinary of a discourse that 1 On a remarkable analysis of this distinction between lived and thought norms: L. PAS- SERINI-GLAZEL,“Lesnormesvécuesetlesnormessimplementpenséesnoemadéontique etexpériencenormativedansKelsen,Weber,Petraz.yckiandWeinberger,”inSociologie dudroit(2018),1. DOI: 10.4324/9781003130109-1 2 Introduction is rationally as ordinary as any other. Indeed, whatever is stated is irremediably only a “saying” and to answer for it from the ordinary of the situation in which it is expressed. We do not refute the idea that some contexts are singular. However, these usually remain contexts linked to enunciation. What is ordinary is that in some wayoranother“I”isenunciatingsomething.Whatis“extraordinary”isfinallythe ordinary of social life and the always singular way supprimer actors agree in it and generate normativity. It is then a question of accounting for a reconciliation in the same “flesh” of enunciationsandstatements,objectivityandsubjectivityaswellasimmanenceand transcendencethathauntlegaldiscourseintheformofduplicatingrealitythatcan only generate ghosts within legal thinking. The ordinariness of law is that there is no other world than the one in which the legal operator finds himself immersed and where he must assume the unimpeachable part of enunciation that is present in his utterance. Everyone should be responsible for their statements from the place where they make them. It is only on this condition that an ethics of legal discourse develops and not just a flat and uniform social morality. It is obvious, of course, that this empiricism – or realistic pragmatism – does not obscurethefactthatinthisworldtheargumentsthatlegalstatementscarryintheform of legal propositions seem to belong to a specific rationality and a singular logic (modal,ethical,etc.).Indeed,weneedascreenonwhichtoprojectourlegalpreten- sions and make the film of law. If the mechanism is ordinary, the film can be extra- ordinary.Thisdifferentiationbetweenthediegeticspaceofadiscourseanditsspaceof enunciationisclassic andis manifested inthe variousmethodsthat make it possible, withvaryingdegreesofsuccess,toshowthisgapandtolinkonespacetoanother. Positivelawthusclosesitselfofftoitsenunciationbypresentingitasheterogeneous: aspolitical,factual,moral,etc.Thetruthofthelawwouldbeinherentinitsownorder. Thisclosureiseventhehallmarkofthedefinitionoflegalpositivism:lawisthenwhat lawconsiderstobelaw.Thestatusofthetruthofadiscourseinthisperspectivealways takes the form of the ideology that makes one never really know what one is doing. Thisideologydoesnotsomuchconfirmthepresenceofrealignoranceasofabadfaith whichthathauntsanalysesandtestifiestoareadinesstoavoidtheembarrassmentsof the ordinary in favor of the apparent certainties that are inherent in practical and operationaldiscourses.Inthishypothesis,theordinarinessofthelawisobscuredbythe presence of a habit (a “habit of action,” i.e., a belief according to pragmatic approa- ches).Thecommondistinctionbetweenfaithandbeliefcanbefoundhereinasecu- larised form: true faith borne of doubt is an ever-repeated struggle against doubt, whereas belief is inscribed in an apparent certainty: it expresses a certain resting of thought.Beliefinthediscourseoflaw–whichhappenstobesupprimeronlyahabitin apragmaticapproach–operates,inthisway,tothedetrimentofacriticalfaithinwhat lawcouldbe.Beliefinlawideologicallyerasesthenecessarilyfragilefaith inlaw.The ordinaryunderstoodinthiswayisnecessarilyethical,becauseitexpressesresistanceto the supprimer all too easy slope of belief: the awareness of a difference and a gap between the doxa and the epistèmê, one might say.… Between opinions and absolute certaintyinahabitthereisobvie:theincrediblyfragileordinaryofa“formoflife.” Introduction 3 Thus, truth, rationality and values are generally separated in the legal discourse inherent in positive law. Truthapprehendedintheclassicalformofcorrespondenceengenders,inessence,a duality between an object and what it refers to and as such must correspond. The truthofsupprimerlawwouldthereforebefoundinitsreferenceordenotation,and each person, depending on what he or she “is,” will then construct this correspon- dence,whichisalwaysfallacious(inmorality,inatranscendence,inafactualreality,in a practice … we find here the recurring idea in legal discourse of the presence of “sourcesoflaw”)becauseitisinscribed,fromtheoutset,intheprisonofalanguage inwhichthesignwillperpetuallybethetombofthething. Rationality, foritspart, will be apprehended: either as the discovery of a general law, or as the discovery of regularities.…Thelawwillthen,forexample,berenewedtothelawofthevalidityof thenorm(whichwouldthusonlybetheanalogyofcausality)orreducedtothedis- coveryofaseriesofregularitiesthatwillhavetoberenewed–possiblybyabduction– to a meaning. These are the various most influential schools of legal theory. The “good”–ormorality–asonlytheorderofsocialutilityoflaworbytheattachment to principles that are nothing but a disguise of the law of values that positive law rejectsanddismisses–moreorlesswellandmoreorlesseasily,asthecontemporary influenceofacertain“neo-constitutionalism”shows. Finally, the most faithful approach to this ordinary that we are calling to redis- coveristheonethatapprehendslaworruleasatoolintheordinaryoftheworld. A tool that would be at our fingertips: a compass or a ruler. A way of orienting ourselves in this world by taking stock of what is the particular way in which law appearsintheworld.Thephenomenologicalapproachisthusabletoperceivethat it is in the ordinariness of its appearance and its donation to consciousness that it offers not an access to the world, but a rationality to the implementation of our formoflife.Thelawregulatestheworldandtheworldgivesthenorm.Tofollow the rule is in this respect only to give a reason for a cause in order to provide ourselves with a tool to judge the regularity of our actions. Let us add that in the three-stranded rope – to use a famous formula – that form the mind, the body and the world, language is of essential importance. It is language that informs the whole and is, as such, fully our “form of life.” It is impossible to escape from it, even if it offers, through its infinite resources, many illusions and desirable “backgrounds.” It is thus enough to speak long enough to seem to give coherence to our discourse. In this respect, legal doctrine clearly gives meaning to legal statements: the discourse on law is intended to make explicit “a” meaning of the discourse of law. It offers the mind the rest of a habit and the oblivion for a time of reflection on the ordinariness of a practice. Language is thus in the world and legal language is only one of its operational forms. Law is a discourse that clearly has a function, and, in this sense, it works to build part of a specialised sub-system inherent in our world. It works towards a function of legitimising and receiving social expectations: it helps to generate trust and belief and to make it possible to deal with expectations. In the form of legal policy, it also performs a function of decision-making and guidance of conduct, in the form of legal command.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.