ebook img

Language and Empiricism - After the Vienna Circle PDF

198 Pages·2008·0.71 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Language and Empiricism - After the Vienna Circle

Language and Empiricism After the Vienna Circle Siobhan Chapman PPL-UK_LE-Chapman_FM.qxd 2/20/2008 6:52 AM Page i Language and Empiricism PPL-UK_LE-Chapman_FM.qxd 2/20/2008 6:52 AM Page ii Also by Siobhan Chapman ACCENT IN CONTEXT KEY IDEAS IN LINGUISTICS AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE (co-edited with Christopher Routledge) KEY THINKERS IN LINGUISTICS AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE (co-edited with Christopher Routledge) PAUL GRICE, Philosopher and Linguist PHILOSOPHY FOR LINGUISTS THINKING ABOUT LANGUAGE: Theories of English PPL-UK_LE-Chapman_FM.qxd 2/20/2008 6:52 AM Page iii Language and Empiricism After the Vienna Circle Siobhan Chapman Senior Lecturer in English Language, University of Liverpool PPL-UK_LE-Chapman_FM.qxd 2/20/2008 6:52 AM Page iv © Siobhan Chapman 2008 All rights reserved.No reproduction,copy or transmission of this publication may be made without written permission. No paragraph of this publication may be reproduced,copied or transmitted save with written permission or in accordance with the provisions of the Copyright,Designs and Patents Act 1988,or under the terms of any licence permitting limited copying issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency,90 Tottenham Court Road,London W1T 4LP. Any person who does any unauthorised act in relation to this publication may be liable to criminal prosecution and civil claims for damages. The author has asserted her right to be identified as the author of this work in accordance with the Copyright,Designs and Patents Act 1988. First published 2008 by PALGRAVE MACMILLAN Houndmills,Basingstoke,Hampshire RG21 6XS and 175 Fifth Avenue,New York,N.Y.10010 Companies and representatives throughout the world PALGRAVE MACMILLAN is the global academic imprint of the Palgrave Macmillan division of St.Martin’s Press,LLC and of Palgrave Macmillan Ltd. Macmillan® is a registered trademark in the United States,United Kingdom and other countries.Palgrave is a registered trademark in the European Union and other countries. ISBN-13:978-0-230-52476-7 hardback ISBN-10:0-230-52476-1 hardback This book is printed on paper suitable for recycling and made from fully managed and sustained forest sources.Logging,pulping and manufacturing processes are expected to conform to the environmental regulations of the country of origin. A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 17 16 15 14 13 12 11 10 09 08 Printed and bound in Great Britain by CPI Antony Rowe,Chippenham and Eastbourne PPL-UK_LE-Chapman_FM.qxd 2/20/2008 6:52 AM Page v Contents Introduction 1 1 The Vienna Circle 7 2 Falsification and Scientific Method 28 3 Holism 49 4 Ordinary Language Philosophy 68 5 Speech Acts and Implicatures 88 6 Oslo Philosophy 108 7 Interpretation and Preciseness 127 8 Empiricism in Linguistics 152 References 175 Index 186 v This page intentionally left blank PPL-UK_LE-Chapman_INTRO.qxd 2/15/2008 9:09 PM Page 1 Introduction This book is about different attitudes to empiricism in the study of lan- guage. It is the product of two apparently unrelated ideas that I have held for some time, voiced on occasion, but had not until recently explored in much detail. The first is that the logical positivism of the Vienna Circle had an impact on the development of present-day lin- guistics that has not generally been fully recognized. I had a hunch that this impact came about largely indirectly, as a result of adverse reactions to the Vienna Circle from philosophers of language who were more or less contemporary with it. The second idea, and one that is perhaps more widely held, is that disagreements in recent linguistics over the role and nature of data are in many cases wrongly focussed and even unnecessary. Linguists from different traditions are not looking at a single phenomenon and choosing radically different types of data by which to investigate it; they are simply investigating different subjects. These two ideas started to link together when I came across the work of the Norwegian philosopher Arne Naess. I was already familiar with J. L. Austin’s reaction against logical positivism, and his advocacy of ‘ordinary language philosophy’, which proceeded from the painstaking analysis of the philosopher’s own linguistic usage. But here was Naess, working at much the same time as Austin, similar in his dislike of the Vienna Circle’s high-handed and dismissive attitude to ordinary language, yet pioneering the very different techniques of ‘empirical semantics’. Austin worked in his armchair using contemplation and intuition. Naess worked on the streets of Oslo using clipboard and ques- tionnaire. The similarities between Naess’s now obscure work and main- stream, present-day disciplines such as sociolinguistics were too attractive to ignore. So too was the real-life debate that developed between Austin and Naess over methodology. Both ordinary language philosophy and 1 PPL-UK_LE-Chapman_INTRO.qxd 2/15/2008 9:09 PM Page 2 2 Language and Empiricism the empirical semantics of the Oslo school of Philosophy developed, in part, as reactions to logical positivism. Each proposed a methodology for the empirical study of language, and each had striking resonances with the two sides in the debate about data in linguistics. The different responses to the Vienna Circle from Austin and from Naess sent me back to the work of the Vienna Circle itself, and to some of the rest of the debate that it generated among its contemporaries. My main focus in this book, then, is not on present-day linguistics but on discussions of language that took place roughly during the half century from 1920 onwards. I am convinced that the story of these discussions should be of more than passing historical interest to linguists. Commenting in 1956 on what he saw as ‘the revolution in philosophy’ that had established analytic and linguistic methods as the dominant force, the British philosopher Gilbert Ryle wrote: The wise rambler occasionally, though not incessantly, looks back over his shoulder in order to link up the place he has got to with the country through which he has recently passed. It is equally wise for thinkers occasionally, though not incessantly, to try to fix in retro- spect the courses that they have followed and the positions from which they have moved. (Ryle 1956: 1) My aim in this book is to offer just such a retrospective view for those currently working in the various fields of present-day linguistics. The view is often obscured, in part at least, because some of the relevant courses run through the territory of philosophy. Work from philosophy has in many cases been highly influential on the development of linguistics, and in others can offer relevant insights and contributions to current debates in the subject, but is often not familiar, or not accessible, to linguists. There is no obvious reason why a linguist should decide to sit down with a copy of Russell and Whitehead’s Principia Mathematica, for instance, or to hunt out some of the more arcane publications of a Norwegian ecologist who long ago visited Vienna. But these are just two examples of the unlikely sounding sources that have a lot to tell us about what people said about language during the twen- tieth century, and how they decided it should be studied. Austin is still widely known and read by linguists. But even in the case of Austin’s work, there are aspects that are rarely discussed and a philosophical context that can shed a lot of light on what he was doing and why. Linguists know about speech acts. They do not necessarily know the PPL-UK_LE-Chapman_INTRO.qxd 2/15/2008 9:09 PM Page 3 Introduction 3 story of how Austin pioneered a methodology that sparked something close to a national debate on the nature and the purpose of the study of language. Austin’s major impact on present-day linguistics has been felt and is acknowledged chiefly in pragmatics. Other branches, however, are more reticent on the subject of philosophical forebears, and here too Ryle’s 50-year-old words prove relevant. In his overview of the revolution in philosophy, he outlined the reasons why attempts to trace the prece- dents of current thinking can be valuable. Switching metaphor, he sug- gested that: ‘Like reports of Royal Commissions, they help the student to understand the contemporary scene – partly by disabusing him of fashionable misconceptions of what is going on’ (ibid.). Ryle’s analogy is undoubtedly grandiose, even self-aggrandizing, but the point he was making can nevertheless be carried over to the contemporary linguistic scene. Branches such as sociolinguistics and corpus linguistics rarely have much to say about early origins of the approaches they embody, other than in celebrating the contributions of individual pioneers of the disciplines themselves. Yet philosophers were saying remarkably similar things about the purpose and methodology of language study several decades before the acknowledged founding of these branches of lin- guistics. In drawing attention to possible philosophical precedents I do not intend to belittle the importance of these developments in linguis- tics, or to claim that what they are doing is in some way ‘old hat’. Rather, my ambition is that identifying a philosophical pedigree for these approaches will afford them a position in the more general theo- retical debate about language with which they have not always seemed fully to engage. This book begins with a chapter on the intellectual context and the main doctrines of the Vienna Circle. This focusses on the notion of ver- ification as a criterion for meaningfulness, and the implications of this for the Vienna Circle’s views, both explicit and implicit, on language. These views were by no means the start of the philosophical link between language and empiricism. Discussions germane to the role of empiricism in language study can be traced back at least as far as the work of Aristotle, and were certainly prominent during the European Enlightenment. But the work of the Vienna Circle represents the high- point of the revolution in philosophy that Ryle identified, a revolution that saw the analysis of concepts, and of the language in which those concepts are expressed, taking central philosophical place. Perhaps as a result of the extremes to which it pushed the revolution, logical positivism generated enthusiasm and hostility in equal measure.

Description:
This book compares attitudes to empiricism in language study from mid-twentieth century philosophy of language and from present-day linguistics. It focuses on responses to the logical positivism of the Vienna Circle, particularly in the work of British philosopher J. L. Austin and the much less well
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.